Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-l4dxg Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-11T03:07:04.988Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Remembered events are unexpected

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 January 2018

Jean-Louis Dessalles*
Affiliation:
LTCI, Telecom ParisTech, Universite Paris-Saclay, F-75013 Paris, France. dessalles@telecom-paristech.frwww.dessalles.fr

Abstract

We remember a small proportion of our experiences as events. Are these events selected because they are useful and can be proven true, or rather because they are unexpected?

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2018 

Remembered events are universally and massively recounted during spontaneous human conversation. Despite early studies (e.g., Tannen Reference Tannen1984), the importance of the phenomenon has long been ignored: It occurs only among people who are already acquainted, and it is absent from most corpora recorded in the lab (Norrick Reference Norrick2000). According to some figures, telling past events may represent up to 40% of conversational time (Eggins & Slade Reference Eggins and Slade1997, p. 265). Measures I made through a sampling method on a corpus of family conversation (about 18 hours recorded during 3 years) resulted in the following estimates: 27% of conversational topics consisted in narratives about past events, while another 12% were about current events (Dessalles Reference Dessalles, Gunzelmann, Howes, Tenbrink and Davelaar2017). Although these proportions are expected to vary significantly depending on the corpus, they indicate that talking about events constitutes one of the main human activities. Is the prevalence of this form of communication consistent with Mahr & Csibra's (M&C's) claims about the role of episodic memory?

If the main function of episodic memory is communication, as M&C propose and as I myself submitted (Dessalles Reference Dessalles2007a), episodes get stored in memory just to be used during future conversations. This comes with a significant cost, if we consider that the large size of the brain sustained by humans is in part due to the need of making detailed retrieval of events possible (Suddendorf & Corballis Reference Suddendorf and Corballis2007). The benefit must be substantial to match this cost. What does this benefit consist of?

According to M&C, communicating about events gives senders an opportunity to induce “in their audience a representation of the past that is to their benefit” (sect. 3.2.3, para. 1). My study of spontaneous conversations does not support this schema. I have been unable to detect clear self-promotion in the narratives of my corpus or in other corpora. On many occasions, the converse can be observed (Rimé Reference Rimé2005). People do not hesitate to tell events in which they performed inappropriate actions. In Norrick's corpus, for instance, a narrator explains that she was hired at a Burger King restaurant for her first job. She was trained during one week, and then, as she was about to take her very first order from a customer, she said into the microphone “Welcome to McDonald's!” (Norrick Reference Norrick2000, pp. 30–31).

Another advantage of storing events, in M&C's view, is that past events can be used as justification during debates and are themselves designed to resist epistemic attacks. Indeed, narratives may be used as arguments during discussions, and conversely, inconsistencies may be pointed out when a narrative is told. But these phenomena remain marginal. In the aforementioned analysis (Dessalles Reference Dessalles, Gunzelmann, Howes, Tenbrink and Davelaar2017), only 16% of the narratives have a logical connection with the previous topic, and only 5% of the discussions are triggered by a narrative. Most narratives are connected to a preceding narrative topic through close analogy (42%) or through mere association (26%). The mention of a past event tends to prompt another, related narrative. This phenomenon has been named story rounds (Tannen Reference Tannen1984, p. 100). Narratives have their own dynamics, distinct from debating. If past events surface so often in human conversation, it must be for some reason other than their epistemic value.

If remembered events were selected for their epistemic robustness, we would prefer events for which evidence is available and can be produced on demand. “I flew from Boston to Paris on June 13, 2006” is such an event. But this episode together with the associated details is unlikely to be worth remembering or worth telling in most contexts, regardless of its epistemic solidity. In earlier work (Dessalles Reference Dessalles2007a), I suggested that events that are memorable are exactly those that are narratable. And we know what makes an event narratable: It has to be unexpected, that is, it has to be causally complex but conceptually simple (complexity and simplicity here refer to minimal description length – see www.simplicitytheory.science). In the Burger King story, the mention of the competitor is both conceptually simple (it is the best-known competitor) and causally complex (it was the last thing to say). The Boston–Paris example would have been more unexpected with a simpler date: “I flew from Boston to Paris on September 11, 2001” but less unexpected if the action was less complex to produce: “I had breakfast on September 11, 2001.” One can play with these two qualities – causal complexity and conceptual simplicity – to predict what will be remembered; their combined effect makes some events unforgettable for an entire life.

If events are remembered and told based on their unexpectedness, does it match the audience's interest? According to M&C, “receivers are interested in acquiring useful (i.e., true) information” (sect. 3.2.3, para. 1). Narratives are, however, ill-designed to convey useful knowledge. Memorized events are selected to be unexpected, not to be consequential. Most conversational narratives are indeed about futile matters, such as oddities or coincidences. In the case of fiction, the audience accepts giving up truthfulness and even likelihood just to enjoy being surprised by unexpected events. Nevertheless, we may wonder why, as M&C observe, it is still important for a reported past event to be regarded as true. Is it because the audience wants to draw general lessons from it? There is a better explanation. Unexpectedness depends on causal complexity, and causal complexity crucially depends on the story being true. If I am lying about my Boston–Paris flight on 9/11, the false event loses its causal complexity (because it did not really happen) and turns out to be devoid of interest.

Episodic memory is geared to supply human beings with unexpected events worth telling. In our species, producing unexpectedness is crucial for having a chance of attracting friends (Dessalles Reference Dessalles, Dor, Knight and Lewis2014). The question of reliability is subordinate to the criterion of unexpectedness. We select a tiny proportion of our experiences and we remember them, not because they are true, but because they are unexpected.

References

Dessalles, J.-L. (2007a) Storing events to retell them (Commentary on Suddendorf and Corballis: “The evolution of foresight”). Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30(3):321–22. Available at: http://www.dessalles.fr/papers/Dessalles_07051403.pdf.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dessalles, J.-L. (2014) Why talk? In: The social origins of language, ed. Dor, D., Knight, C. & Lewis, J., pp. 284–96. Oxford University Press. Available at: http://www.dessalles.fr/papers/Dessalles_12031903.pdf.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dessalles, J.-L. (2017) Conversational topic connectedness predicted by simplicity theory. Proceedings of the 39th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society, London, UK, 26–29 July 2017, ed. Gunzelmann, G., Howes, A., Tenbrink, T. & Davelaar, E., pp. 1914–19. Cognitive Science Society. Available at: https://mindmodeling.org/cogsci2017/papers/0368/.Google Scholar
Eggins, S. & Slade, D. (1997) Analysing casual conversation. Equinox.Google Scholar
Norrick, N. R. (2000) Conversational narrative: Storytelling in everyday talk. John Benjamins.Google Scholar
Rimé, B. (2005) Le partage social des émotions. Presses Universitaires de France – PUF.Google Scholar
Suddendorf, T. & Corballis, M. C. (2007) The evolution of foresight: What is mental time travel, and is it unique to humans? Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30(3):299313.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tannen, D. (1984) Conversational style – Analyzing talk among friends. Ablex.Google Scholar