Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-cphqk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T02:46:19.316Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The dynamics of episodic memory functions

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 January 2018

Dorthe Berntsen*
Affiliation:
Center on Autobiographical Memory Research (CON AMORE), Department of Psychology, Aarhus University, 8000, Aarhus C, Denmark. dorthe@psy.au.dkhttp://pure.au.dk/portal/da/persons/dorthe-berntsen(2a5c3e80-973a-4b35-883d-a7de4143885c)/cv.html?id=32505546

Abstract

There is no doubt that episodic memory serves communicative functions, but Mahr & Csibra (M&C) overlook that this is not the only function served by memories of past events. Autobiographical memory research has identified several other functions, including purely directive functions. The functionality of episodic memory is not stable across situations; it varies dynamically with the demands of the retrieval context.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2018 

Mahr & Csibra's (M&C's) basic idea that remembering serves the justification of beliefs and that this justification has communicative and social functions is not new, but was formulated by Bartlett almost 100 years ago. In his seminal book, Bartlett (Reference Bartlett1932) stated: “Remembering appears to be far more decisively an affair of construction rather than mere reproduction. … The construction that is effected is the sort of construction that would justify the observer's ‘attitude’” (pp. 205–206). This seems very close to the tenet in the target article that the construction of a past event serves to justify a present belief. Bartlett also considered the social and communicative functions of such constructions at length. Unfortunately, Bartlett's (Reference Bartlett1932) theory is not considered in the target article. It is therefore hard to evaluate exactly what M&C add to this classic of psychology.

In addition, an entire field seems to be neglected. M&C operate with two conceptions of memories for past events: episodic memory, which is characterized by a specific set of features (to which I will return shortly), and event memory, which is all other types of memory for past events. This division appears to leave no room for autobiographical memory, usually defined as memory for personal past events (Conway & Pleydell-Pearce Reference Conway and Pleydell-Pearce2000; Rubin Reference Rubin1986; Reference Rubin1996). It is unclear whether autobiographical memory should be viewed as an instance of episodic memory or event memory or neither. The target article mentions autobiographical memory in an endnote, leaving its role completely unclarified.

The problem is not simply failing to specify a slot for autobiographical memory in the taxonomy. The key problem is that a number of insights from the field of autobiographical memory could have informed M&C's theory but were ignored. For example, several autobiographical memory researchers have studied the perceived functions of memories for past events. They have developed psychometric tests to determine types of functions that people perceive to be associated with those memories and examined individual differences in their frequencies (Bluck et al. Reference Bluck, Habermas and Rubin2005; Harris et al. Reference Harris, Rasmussen and Berntsen2014; Webster Reference Webster1993). Using experimental manipulations, they have examined interactions between perceived memory functions and other memory characteristics, such as emotional valence (Rasmussen & Berntsen Reference Rasmussen and Berntsen2009; Walker et al. Reference Walker, Skowronski, Gibbons, Vogl and Ritchi2009) or retrieval processes (Rasmussen et al. Reference Rasmussen, Ramsgaard and Berntsen2015).

Contrary to M&C's position, this research leaves little empirical basis for claiming a unitary and privileged role for a communicative function. In the autobiographical memory literature, the communicative function is just one among several identified uses of event memories in daily life. For example, there is empirical evidence that people perceive their memories of past events to direct their current behavior (also in non-communicative contexts) as well as to support their identity and sense of self-continuity (Bluck et al. Reference Bluck, Habermas and Rubin2005; Pillemer Reference Pillemer1998; Reference Pillemer2003; Webster Reference Webster1993). There is also evidence that memories of past events serve emotion-regulation functions and that the tendencies to entertain these functionalities differ across age groups (e.g., Harris et al. Reference Harris, Rasmussen and Berntsen2014; Webster Reference Webster1994).

In essence, two crucial problems follow from neglecting many findings in the autobiographical memory literature. First, in the target article, M&C give themselves the task of developing a theory that can account for what they consider as three central characteristics of episodic memory: the “epistemic generativity, autonoetic character, and proneness to belief congruency” (sect. 3, para. 1). They claim that these features agree with the key role of the communicative function of the memories. Although this is likely true, the exact same characteristics are congruent with a number of other functions served by the memories, such as guiding and directing ongoing behavior. To use M&C's own example, a vivid recollection of having turned off the oven before leaving the house to go for a walk does not just serve a communicative function in relation to one's companion, but it also serves a directive function in relation to one's ongoing behavior and would also do so in a solitary context (“yes, it is OK to continue the walk, the oven is turned off”).

Second, although episodic memories are likely to have the characteristics mentioned by M&C, they have other central characteristics that go unmentioned. It is therefore not clear whether these other characteristics would fit or challenge the theory by M&C. For example, it is well-established that distinctive events are better remembered (Hunt Reference Hunt, Hunt and Worthen2006), and that episodic memories are cue sensitive and often come to mind unbidden. Involuntary (unbidden) memories of past events are at least as frequent as voluntary memories (Rasmussen et al. Reference Rasmussen, Ramsgaard and Berntsen2015). They can be highly vivid, are more often about specific events, and come with more emotional impact than their voluntarily retrieved counterparts (Berntsen Reference Berntsen2009). Such memories have a number of functions that are constrained by the ongoing situation and its demands (Pillemer Reference Pillemer2003; Rasmussen et al. Reference Rasmussen, Ramsgaard and Berntsen2015). The existence of such involuntary episodic memories with a diversity of functions also has implications for the claims of human uniqueness. Even if M&C are right that nonhuman animals do not make use of episodic memory in a communicative fashion, there is empirical evidence that they spontaneously retrieve memories of concrete past episodes to solve a problem in an ongoing situation, even after long delays, if exposed to distinct situational cues (Lewis et al. Reference Lewis, Call and Berntsen2017; Martin-Ordas et al. Reference Martin-Ordas, Berntsen and Call2013). This and similar studies speak against the claim that episodic memory is a uniquely human ability.

Perhaps the greatest problem with M&C's theoretical position is that they assume a unitary function of episodic memory and thus overlook that the functionality of episodic memory is inherently dynamic; that is, the functions served by any given memory vary as a function of the demands of the retrieval situation. Thus, the very same memory may have communicative functions in one situation and purely instrumental (or directive) functions in another depending on the retrieval context. Without such dynamics, episodic memory would not be adaptive.

References

Bartlett, F. C. (1932) Remembering: A study in experimental and social psychology. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Berntsen, D. (2009) Involuntary autobiographical memories. An introduction to the unbidden past. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bluck, S. Alea, N., Habermas, T. & Rubin, D. C. (2005) A TALE of three functions: The self-reported uses of autobiographical memory. Social Cognition 23(1):91117.Google Scholar
Conway, M. A. & Pleydell-Pearce, C. W. (2000) The construction of autobiographical memories in the self-memory system. Psychological Review 107:261–88.Google Scholar
Harris, C. B., Rasmussen, A. S. & Berntsen, D. (2014) The functions of autobiographical memory: An integrative approach. Memory 22(5):559–81.Google Scholar
Hunt, R. R. (2006) The concept of distinctiveness in memory research. In: Distinctiveness and memory, ed. Hunt, R. R. & Worthen, J. B., pp. 346. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, A., Call, J. & Berntsen, D. (2017) Non-goal-directed recall of specific events in apes after long delays. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 284: 20170518.Google Scholar
Martin-Ordas, G., Berntsen, D. & Call, J. (2013) Memory for distant past events in chimpanzees and orangutans. Current Biology 23:1438–41. Available at: http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0960982213007082.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pillemer, D. B. (1998) Momentous events, vivid memories. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Pillemer, D. B. (2003) Directive functions of autobiographical memory: The guiding power of the specific episode. Memory 11:193202.Google Scholar
Rasmussen, A. S. & Berntsen, D. (2009) Emotional valence and the functions of autobiographical memories: Positive and negative memories serve different functions. Memory & Cognition 37:477–92.Google Scholar
Rasmussen, A. S., Ramsgaard, S. B. & Berntsen, D. (2015) The frequency and functions of involuntary and voluntary autobiographical memories across the day. Psychology of Consciousness: Theory, Research, and Practice 2:185205.Google Scholar
Rubin, D. C., ed. (1986) Autobiographical memory. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rubin, D. C., ed. (1996) Remembering our past: Studies in autobiographical memory. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Walker, R. W., Skowronski, J. J., Gibbons, J. A., Vogl, J. R. & Ritchi, T. D. (2009) Why people rehearse their memories: Frequency of use and relations to the intensity of emotions associated with autobiographical memories. Memory 17:760–73.Google Scholar
Webster, J. D. (1993) Construction and validation of the Reminiscence Functions Scale. Journal of Gerontology 48:256–62.Google Scholar
Webster, J. D. (1994) Predictors of reminiscence: A lifespan perspective. Canadian Journal on Aging 13:6678.Google Scholar