Crossref Citations
This article has been cited by the following publications. This list is generated based on data provided by
Crossref.
Shaw, Alex
2013.
Beyond “to Share or Not to Share”.
Current Directions in Psychological Science,
Vol. 22,
Issue. 5,
p.
413.
Shaw, Alex
and
Olson, Kristina
2014.
Fairness as partiality aversion: The development of procedural justice.
Journal of Experimental Child Psychology,
Vol. 119,
Issue. ,
p.
40.
Marczyk, Jesse
2015.
Moral Alliance Strategies Theory.
Evolutionary Psychological Science,
Vol. 1,
Issue. 2,
p.
77.
Shaw, Alex
2016.
Evolutionary Perspectives on Child Development and Education.
p.
193.
Abubakar, A. Mohammed
and
Arasli, Huseyin
2016.
Dear top management, please don’t make me a cynic: intention to sabotage.
Journal of Management Development,
Vol. 35,
Issue. 10,
p.
1266.
Tu, Yanping
Shaw, Alex
and
Fishbach, Ayelet
2016.
The Friendly Taking Effect: How Interpersonal Closeness Leads to Seemingly Selfish Yet Jointly Maximizing Choice.
Journal of Consumer Research,
Vol. 42,
Issue. 5,
p.
669.
Shaw, Alex
Choshen-Hillel, Shoham
and
Caruso, Eugene M.
2016.
The Development of Inequity Aversion.
Psychological Science,
Vol. 27,
Issue. 10,
p.
1352.
Gordon-Hecker, Tom
Choshen-Hillel, Shoham
Shalvi, Shaul
and
Bereby-Meyer, Yoella
2017.
Interdisciplinary Perspectives on Fairness, Equity, and Justice.
p.
93.
Marczyk, Jesse
and
Xia, Cheng-Yi
2017.
Human punishment is not primarily motivated by inequality.
PLOS ONE,
Vol. 12,
Issue. 2,
p.
e0171298.
Shaw, Alex
DeScioli, Peter
Barakzai, Anam
and
Kurzban, Robert
2017.
Whoever is not with me is against me: The costs of neutrality among friends.
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,
Vol. 71,
Issue. ,
p.
96.
Shaw, Alex
and
Choshen-Hillel, Shoham
2017.
It’s not fair: Folk intuitions about disadvantageous and advantageous inequity aversion.
Judgment and Decision Making,
Vol. 12,
Issue. 3,
p.
208.
Niemi, Laura
Wasserman, Emily
and
Young, Liane
2018.
The behavioral and neural signatures of distinct conceptions of fairness.
Social Neuroscience,
Vol. 13,
Issue. 4,
p.
399.
Barakzai, Anam
and
Shaw, Alex
2018.
Friends without benefits: When we react negatively to helpful and generous friends.
Evolution and Human Behavior,
Vol. 39,
Issue. 5,
p.
529.
Shaw, Alex
Choshen-Hillel, Shoham
and
Caruso, Eugene M.
2018.
Being biased against friends to appear unbiased.
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,
Vol. 78,
Issue. ,
p.
104.
Sullivan-Toole, Holly
Dobryakova, Ekaterina
DePasque, Samantha
and
Tricomi, Elizabeth
2019.
Reward circuitry activation reflects social preferences in the face of cognitive effort.
Neuropsychologia,
Vol. 123,
Issue. ,
p.
55.
Shaw, Alex
Barakzai, Anam
and
Keysar, Boaz
2019.
When and Why People Evaluate Negative Reciprocity as More Fair Than Positive Reciprocity.
Cognitive Science,
Vol. 43,
Issue. 8,
Gordon‐Hecker, Tom
Schneider, Iris K.
Shalvi, Shaul
and
Bereby‐Meyer, Yoella
2021.
Leaving with something: When do people experience an equity–efficiency conflict?.
Journal of Behavioral Decision Making,
Vol. 34,
Issue. 2,
p.
213.
Ein‐Gar, Danit
Levontin, Liat
and
Kogut, Tehila
2021.
The Adverse Effect of Choice in Donation Decisions.
Journal of Consumer Psychology,
Vol. 31,
Issue. 3,
p.
570.
Gordon-Hecker, Tom
Shaw, Alex
and
Choshen-Hillel, Shoham
2022.
One for me, two for you: Agency increases children's satisfaction with disadvantageous inequity.
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,
Vol. 100,
Issue. ,
p.
104286.
Kraft-Todd, Gordon T.
Kleiman-Weiner, Max
and
Young, Liane
2023.
Virtue Discounting: Observability Reduces Moral Actors’ Perceived Virtue.
Open Mind,
Vol. 7,
Issue. ,
p.
460.
Jack Abramoff, one of the most notorious lobbyists in the last decade, made millions of dollars by delivering huge profits to his clients at the expense of others and the public good (Stone Reference Stone2006). Abramoff's relationship with the legislators was a classic example of mutualistic cooperation. He provided money to the legislators and, in return, the legislators provided their votes on key issues. This is precisely the sort of phenomenon for which Baumard et al.'s theory offers an elegant explanation.
Yet, though the actions of the legislators certainly made them effective partners in a mutualistic exchange, these actions would not generally be regarded as paradigm examples of fairness. On the contrary, in this case there is a direct conflict between the aim of being a good partner and the aim of acting fairly. The most fair thing to do in this situation would be to not show any preference for one's own partner and simply to vote in a way that advanced the public good.
Thus, we suggest that fairness is not reducible to mutualism. Baumard and colleagues may be correct in their claim that the best model of mutualistic cooperation involves partner choice, but it would be a mistake to suppose that mutualistic cooperation is itself sufficient to explain intuitions about fairness. Instead, fairness often acts in opposition to the discriminative generosity that partner choice demands by asking individuals to treat others impartially.
Although mutualistic cooperation and impartiality can be congruent, they often make different behavioral prescriptions. In repeated dyadic interactions, mutualistic cooperation and fairness prescribe the same behavior. Reciprocity makes Bill both a good mutualist and also impartial. However, things change once at least three actors are involved. If Jack is overly generous to Bill in one interaction, and Bill has resources to share with him and another individual at a later date, then mutualistic cooperation and fairness make different prescriptions. Mutualistic cooperation says Bill should reciprocate the past generosity, giving more to Jack than he does to other people. By contrast, impartiality says that Bill should split the resources completely equally. To the extent that people show such a preference for equality, their behavior cannot be understood in terms of mutualism alone and must also involve a concern for impartiality.
An especially striking example of people's preference for equality arises in cases where people actually destroy resources to avoid creating inequity (Blake & McAuliffe Reference Blake and McAuliffe2011; Dawes et al. Reference Dawes, Fowler, Johnson, McElreath and Smirnov2007). In an extreme display of this tendency toward destructive fairness, Shaw and Olson (Reference Shaw and Olson2012) presented 6- to 8-year-old children with a choice between (a) giving a person an additional resource and thereby introducing inequality or (b) simply throwing that resource in the trash. The majority of participants chose to throw the resource in the trash even when it was made clear to them that the two recipients did not know each other and would not know what the other received. This behavior shows a strong concern with equality, but it is hard to see any way of explaining it with models based on mutualism and partner choice. If one were trying to develop a mutually beneficial partnership with either of these individuals, then giving an additional resource could improve this budding partnership.
To determine whether adults would exhibit similar tendencies, we conducted a follow-up experiment. Forty participants (M = 37.5 years, SD = 10.2, 26 females) were assigned either to the Equality Condition or the Inequality Condition. Participants in the Equality Condition were told that two employees had each received a $2/hour raise and were then asked what the company should do with an additional $1/hour raise: (a) give it to one of the two employees, or (b) give it to neither of them. Participants in the Inequality Condition were told that one employee had received a $3/hour raise, while the other had received a $2/hour raise, and were asked the same question. All participants were told that the employees did not know each other and would not know about the other's raise. In the Equality Condition, the majority of participants (90%) chose not to give the dollar to either employee, whereas in the Inequality Condition only a minority of participants (10%) preferred this option, χ2 (1, N = 40)=22.5, p < 0.001. These results suggest that adults, too, are willing to destroy resources in the name of fairness; this would not be expected under models of mutualistic cooperation. Mutualistic cooperation would predict that individuals should give an extra benefit to one of the employees, since doing so could foster future cooperative interactions (Binmore Reference Binmore1998a) and increase the employee's work output (Fehr & Schmidt Reference Fehr and Schmidt1999). In contrast, such destructive fairness is expected if fairness is rooted in impartiality.
One open question is: Why would natural selection have favored impartiality? The answer to this question may be rooted in the dynamics of human alliances. The human tendency to form alliances nicely exemplifies the tension between favoritism and impartiality. People rank their allies, but do not want others to know that they rank their allies (DeScioli & Kurzban Reference DeScioli and Kurzban2009). One possibility is that people do not want to be explicit about ranking others because they want to avoid negative reactions from those who receive a low rank. This leads to a possible explanation for why fairness may have evolved: as a way for people to signal to others that they are impartial, and thereby avoid being condemned by third parties for trying to demonstrate or initiate alliances based on preferential sharing.
Abramoff and the legislators he influenced made a great deal of money (based on mutualistic cooperation), but when their work was revealed to the public, many of them paid a heavy price (based on fairness). Although not normally reaching such extremes, human social life often involves this delicate balance between showing favoritism towards one's partners and appearing impartial to others. We suggest that neither of the two can simply be reduced to the other.