Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-hvd4g Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T09:16:14.177Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

An expanded “staying alive” theory (SAT) underplays complexity in Homo sapiens

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 July 2022

Agustín Fuentes*
Affiliation:
Department of Anthropology, Princeton University, Princeton, NJ 08540, USA afuentes2@princeton.eduhttps://anthropology.princeton.edu/people/faculty/agustin-fuentes

Abstract

The target article takes myriad human female patterns and aligns them as a unit emerging from an expanded version of “staying alive” theory (SAT). Females and males do differ, however, to treat the complexity of human response to threats as an explicit, evolved sexually dimorphic package is not reflective of current knowledge regarding health, sex/gender, and behavior in Homo sapiens.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

Campbell's “staying alive” theory (SAT) argues human females produce stronger self-protective reactions to aggressive threats because self-protection has higher fitness value for females. The SAT's core assumption is that female and male humans are under such distinct evolutionary pressures that selection structures females' bodies and minds producing “unique” adaptations relative to males. The target article takes myriad patterns (behavioral, physiological, social, cultural) in human females and aligns them as a unit emerging from an expanded version of the SAT. Human females and males do respond in overlapping but different distributions to threats, pathogens, and related health challenges, but why this is the case is extremely complex and influenced by multiple and diverse social, historical, biological, and contextual variables.

There are patterned differences between males and females in many species. For example, most mammalian females live longer than males and there are a number of processes that affect female longevity including sex chromosome heterogamy/homogamy and telomere length (Xirocostas, Everingham, & Moles, Reference Xirocostas, Everingham and Moles2020) and diversity and complexity in female life histories and behavior (e.g., Cooke, Reference Cooke2022; Morbeck, Galloway, & Zihlman, Reference Morbeck, Galloway and Zihlman1996). However, this article seeks not to complexify understandings of human behavioral variation, but to simplify them. And therein lies my first critique. Benenson et al.'s core assertion, and the assumptions of the SAT, rest heavily on the classic arguments by Bateman, Trivers, Hamilton, and others, about the relative costs of reproduction and their effects on parental investment and life histories. While these assumptions about evolutionary “costs” of being female and male remain common in biology textbooks, there are serious challenges to their precision and universality. Bateman's thesis, and work, is flawed and the realities of measuring and assessing relative costs of investment in reproduction and the implications/consequences for male and female behavior are complex (Drea, Reference Drea2005; Gowaty, Kim, & Anderson, Reference Gowaty, Kim and Anderson2012; Tang-Martinez & Ryder, Reference Tang-Martinez and Ryder2005). This complexity of patterns is especially true for humans (Borgerhoff-Mulder, Reference Borgerhoff-Mulder2004) given our complex neurobiologies (Eliot, Ahmed, Khan, & Patel, Reference Eliot, Ahmed, Khan and Patel2021), and distinctive sex/gender (Hyde, Bigler, Joel, Tate, & van Anders, Reference Hyde, Bigler, Joel, Tate and van Anders2018), life history (Sear, Reference Sear2020), and morphological (Dunsworth, Reference Dunsworth2020) processes. Specifically, parental investment in humans is more complex than the authors of this article acknowledge, and the potential evolutionary implication of this reality is not taken into account in their assessments. While noting complexity in human reproductive processes the authors' still frame their argument around assumptions of costs/benefits arising from a nuclear family/two-adult-plus-offspring core reproductive unit, which is not the basal form of residence, social organization, or childcare in humans (Gettler, Reference Gettler2016; Rosenberg, Reference Rosenberg2021; Sear, Reference Sear2021). They do acknowledge “grandmothering” and “cooperative care,” but emphasize that females do most childcare in contemporary societies, and leave it at that. However, these assessments (from the HRAF and contemporary forager/horticulturalist groups) might not reflect the range and structures of human evolutionary, and contemporary, processes related to reproduction and energetic investments and their integration into the broader range of human social behavior (Borgerhoff-Mulder & Rauch, Reference Borgerhoff-Mulder and Rauch2009; Fuentes, Reference Fuentes2016; Fuentes & Wiessner, Reference Fuentes and Wiessner2016; Spikins, Reference Spikins2015). There are other, equally valid, modes of explanation for human social organization and behavioral processes not solely grounded in assumptions of radically different evolutionary trajectories for females and males. The bottom line is that given current understandings of human evolution, physiology, and behavior one should question, and unpack, the basal framework of the SAT more extensively before building an entire thesis on it.

My secondary critique involves the evidence offered in support of the authors' argument. For example, the causes of mortality in Figure 2 are all prevalent with substantive impact primarily in the recent evolutionary moment (post-last demographic transition and post-industrial revolution). The WHO data suggest that on average females die later or less from certain diseases, but to understand morbidity and mortality of cancers or cardiovascular disease (CVD) or hepatitis A solely, or even primarily, as the outcome of evolved differences between male and female biology is to elide decades of research and scholarship on the myriad interconnecting social, economic, historical, and biological processes at play (Krieger, Reference Krieger2020). Similarly, coronavirus disease-2019 (COVID-19) is a particularly bad example as social structures and inequities are central in structuring outcomes of morbidity/mortality in pandemics/syndemics (Gravlee, Reference Gravlee2020). Patterns of race, sex/gender, geography, region, and so on mortality from COVID are not the best locale to investigate female/male biological differences. Obviously, biological factors related to reproduction can be involved, but their relative contributions to the patterns and processes of the outcomes in the face of the societal/structural determinants of health are often relatively small, and often nonlinear. I do not have the space to engage the psychological and social behavior differences the authors review (e.g., smiling, politeness, sadness, anger, avoidance of confrontation, etc.). But, to see these as direct outcomes, and measures, of selection for behavioral differences in females and males due to differential patterns of reproductive investment is to ignore vast amounts of social scientific and ethnographic data/analyses on why/how humans smile, get mad, avoid specific kinds of social contexts, and so on. Of course, evolutionary histories affect these behaviors, but it stretches credulity to assume gender/sex differences in these behaviors are best represented as specific outcomes of targeted selection.

The authors are not ignorant of these critiques. In sections 7.2 and 7.3 they acknowledge complexity and state “we cannot specify which characteristics of sex/gender relate to self-protection.” But if this is the case, isn't that all the more reason to avoid simple and strictly targeted selection models such as the SAT? It is likely that many of the processes highlighted, including aspects of SAT, are at play in contemporary humans. But to compartmentalize them as a unit and focus on only one selection model, as if its explanatory power is more meaningful, is to oversimplify and misrepresent the dynamics of the human processes being explored. In sum, to treat the complexity of human response to threats as an explicit, sexually dimorphic package being driven by a relatively simple selection hypothesis, the SAT, is not reflective of the immense body of knowledge regarding health, sex/gender, reproduction, and behavior in Homo sapiens.

Financial support

This research received no specific grant from any funding agency, commercial, or not-for-profit sectors.

Conflict of interest

None.

References

Borgerhoff-Mulder, M. (2004). Are men and women really so different? Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 19(1), 36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Borgerhoff-Mulder, M., & Rauch, K. (2009). Sexual conflict in humans: Variations and solutions. Evolutionary Anthropology, 18, 201214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cooke, L. (2022). Bitch: On the female of the species. Basic Books.Google Scholar
Drea, C. M. (2005). Bateman revisited: The reproductive tactics of female primates. Integrative and Comparative Biology, 45(5), 915923.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dunsworth, H. M. (2020). Expanding the evolutionary explanations for sex differences in the human skeleton. Evolutionary Anthropology, 29(3), 108116.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Eliot, L., Ahmed, A., Khan, H., & Patel, J. (2021). Dump the “dimorphism”: Comprehensive synthesis of human brain studies reveals few male-female differences beyond size. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 125, 667697.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fuentes, A. (2016). The extended evolutionary synthesis, ethnography, and the human niche. Current Anthropology, 57(Suppl. 13), 1326. http://dx.doi.org/10.1086/685684.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fuentes, A., & Wiessner, P. (2016). Reintegrating anthropology: From inside out. Current Anthropology, 57(Suppl. 13), 312.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gettler, L. T. (2016). Becoming DADS: Considering the role of cultural context and developmental plasticity for paternal socioendocrinology. Current Anthropology, 57, S38S51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gowaty, P., Kim, Y.-K., & Anderson, W. (2012). No evidence of sexual selection in a repetition of Bateman's classic study of Drosophila melanogaster. PNAS, 109, 11740–5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gravlee, C. C. (2020). Systemic racism, chronic health inequities, and COVID-19: A syndemic in the making? American Journal of Human Biology, 32(5), e23482.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hyde, J. S., Bigler, R. S., Joel, D., Tate, C. C., & van Anders, S. M. (2018). The future of sex and gender in psychology: Five challenges to the gender binary. American Psychologist, 74(2), 171193.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krieger, N. (2020). Measures of racism, sexism, heterosexism, and gender binarism for health equity research: From structural injustice to embodied harm – An ecosocial analysis. Annual Review of Public Health, 41, 3762.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Morbeck, M. E., Galloway, A., & Zihlman, A. (1996). The evolving female: A life history perspective. Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenberg, K. (2021). The evolution of human infancy: Why it helps to be helpless. Annual Review of Anthropology, 50, 423440.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sear, R. (2020). Do human “life history strategies” exist? Evolution and Human Behavior, 41(6), 513526.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sear, R. (2021). The male breadwinner nuclear family is not the “traditional” human family, and promotion of this myth may have adverse health consequences. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, 376, 20200020.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Spikins, P. (2015). How compassion made us human: The evolutionary origins of tenderness, trust and morality. Pen & Sword Books Ltd.Google Scholar
Tang-Martinez, Z., & Ryder, T. B. (2005). The problem with paradigms: Bateman's worldview as a case study. Integrative and Comparative Biology, 45(5), 821830.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Xirocostas, Z. A., Everingham, S. E., & Moles, A. T. (2020). The sex with the reduced sex chromosome dies earlier: A comparison across the tree of life. Biology Letters, 16, 20190867.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed