Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-mzp66 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T08:52:48.322Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Negative results are needed to show the specific value of a cultural explanation for g

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 August 2017

Ruben C. Arslan
Affiliation:
Department of Biological Personality Psychology, Georg Elias Müller Institute of Psychology, Georg August University Göttingen, 37073 Göttingen, Germanyruben.arslan@gmail.comchristoph.borell@psych.uni-goettingen.delpenke@uni-goettingen.dehttps://www.psych.uni-goettingen.de/en/arslanhttps://www.psych.uni-goettingen.de/en/biopers/team/borellhttps://www.psych.uni-goettingen.de/en/biopers/team/penke Leibniz ScienceCampus Primate Cognition, 37077 Göttingen, Germany
Christoph J. von Borell
Affiliation:
Department of Biological Personality Psychology, Georg Elias Müller Institute of Psychology, Georg August University Göttingen, 37073 Göttingen, Germanyruben.arslan@gmail.comchristoph.borell@psych.uni-goettingen.delpenke@uni-goettingen.dehttps://www.psych.uni-goettingen.de/en/arslanhttps://www.psych.uni-goettingen.de/en/biopers/team/borellhttps://www.psych.uni-goettingen.de/en/biopers/team/penke Leibniz ScienceCampus Primate Cognition, 37077 Göttingen, Germany Research Training Group 2070 – Understanding Social Relationships, Georg August University Göttingen, 37073 Göttingen, Germany
Julia Ostner
Affiliation:
Leibniz ScienceCampus Primate Cognition, 37077 Göttingen, Germany German Primate Center Leibniz Institute for Primate Research, 37077 Göttingen, Germany Department of Behavioral Ecology, Johann-Friedrich-Blumenbach Institute for Zoology and Anthropology, Georg August University Göttingen, 37073 Göttingen, Germanyjulia.ostner@biologie.uni-goettingen.dehttps://www.uni-goettingen.de/en/164051.html
Lars Penke
Affiliation:
Department of Biological Personality Psychology, Georg Elias Müller Institute of Psychology, Georg August University Göttingen, 37073 Göttingen, Germanyruben.arslan@gmail.comchristoph.borell@psych.uni-goettingen.delpenke@uni-goettingen.dehttps://www.psych.uni-goettingen.de/en/arslanhttps://www.psych.uni-goettingen.de/en/biopers/team/borellhttps://www.psych.uni-goettingen.de/en/biopers/team/penke Leibniz ScienceCampus Primate Cognition, 37077 Göttingen, Germany

Abstract

Burkart et al. suggest that social learning can explain the cognitive positive manifold for social animals, including humans. We caution that simpler explanations of positive trait intercorrelations exist, such as genetic load. To test the suggested explanation's specificity, we also need to examine non-social species and traits, such as health, that are distal to cognitive abilities.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2017 

We commend Burkart et al. for writing a clear review of the available data on intraspecies g and interspecies G. Although data on individual differences on nonhuman animals are scarce, mapping out the potentially far-ranging implications will, we hope, encourage more high-quality nonhuman individual differences research. The authors' effort to establish clearer and cross-species terms in the modularity debate and to highlight the existence of secondary modules is very welcome. Together with the acknowledgment, as nicely laid out by Burkart et al., that evolution is a tinkerer, not an engineer (Jacob Reference Jacob1977), we think these efforts will lead to progress in the understanding of the evolution and genetics of general intelligence.

We agree that integration between subdisciplines currently focused either on universals or individual differences (e.g., evolutionary psychology and behavior genetics) is necessary (Arslan & Penke Reference Arslan, Penke and Buss2015; Penke et al. Reference Penke, Denissen and Miller2007) and hope warnings about the lack of generalizability in nonhuman animal cognition research will be heeded (Arden et al. Reference Arden, Bensky and Adams2016; Thornton & Lukas Reference Thornton and Lukas2012). On the other hand, we are unsure whether the effort to connect the appearance of psychometric g to the presence of general intelligence in a species succeeds. This leads us to examine what could cause g in the absence of a core intelligence trait.

We agree with the authors that psychometric g and domain-general intelligence should not be thoughtlessly equated (Penke et al. Reference Penke, Borsboom, Johnson, Kievit, Ploeger and Wicherts2011). Although a species whose individuals vary in a core domain-general intelligence ability should exhibit a psychometric g, finding a psychometric g does not imply that variation in a core ability causes it. If g were caused by a core ability, then training this ability should show transfer effects to distal cognitive abilities. The authors cite such training studies, but acknowledge controversy about bias and methods (see also Colom et al. Reference Colom, Román, Abad, Shih, Privado, Froufe, Escorial, Martínez, Burgaleta, Quiroga, Karama, Haier, Thompson and Jaeggi2013; Redick Reference Redick2015). Noack et al. (Reference Noack, Lövdén and Schmiedek2014) concluded that the existing literature cannot establish such latent transfer effects. Claims of bilingual advantage have been similarly contested (Paap et al. Reference Paap, Johnson and Sawi2015). If training of purported core abilities such as executive functions does not increase latent g, the case for core abilities causing the positive manifold weakens considerably. Moreover, positive correlations have not only been found among cognitive abilities but also between cognitive abilities and other fitness-related traits such as health, psychopathology, and height (Arden et al. Reference Arden, Bensky and Adams2016). Hagenaars et al. (Reference Hagenaars, Gale, Deary and Harris2016a) showed molecular evidence that a shared genetic aetiology underlies the phenotypic associations between health and intelligence.

Reasonable, less cognition-specific explanations have been put forward to explain such positive manifolds. First among them is probably genetic load (Hill et al. Reference Hill, Davies, Harris, Hagenaars, Liewald, Penke, Gale and Deary2016a; Penke et al. Reference Penke, Denissen and Miller2007). Individuals vary in the number of deleterious genetic mutations they carry. Depending on where they occur, such wrong turns on the genotype-phenotype map could affect the integrity and condition of the whole organism, its brain, or more specific abilities. If many of the variants affecting cognitive abilities are pleiotropic (be that because they affect early development steps or because they disrupt frequently re-used genetic patterns), then we would also expect positive correlations between cognitive abilities and other fitness-related individual differences (Deary Reference Deary2012; Houle Reference Houle, Bock, Goode and Webb2000). Although causal inference from genetic correlations is hard (Johnson et al. Reference Johnson, Penke and Spinath2011; Solovieff et al. Reference Solovieff, Cotsapas, Lee, Purcell and Smoller2013), we ought to consider the possibility that biological pleiotropy, not just health behavior, explains associations between intelligence and health (Hagenaars et al. Reference Hagenaars, Harris, Davies, Hill, Liewald, Ritchie, Marioni, Fawns-Ritchie, Cullen, Malik, Worrall, Sudlow, Wardlaw, Gallacher, Pell, McIntosh, Smith, Gale and Deary2016b). For example, evolutionarily conserved genomic regions are strongly enriched for genetic variants affecting intelligence (Hill et al. Reference Hill, Davies, Harris, Hagenaars, Liewald, Penke, Gale and Deary2016a). We think this can explain part of the g phenomenon. An explanation based on genetic load can even explain correlations between abilities resulting from primary modules. Other sources of individual differences such as stochastic events in early development can take an explanatory role similar to genetic load, by affecting early developmental steps and pervasive building blocks of the organism (Deary Reference Deary2012).

Hence, our null hypothesis should not be complete independence of cognitive abilities, even if we knew they were primary modules. Some intercorrelation should be expected. The expected degree of intercorrelation depends on many unknowns, among them the degree of pleiotropy, the mutational target size, metabolic costs, and ontogeny of cognitive abilities.

With the nonhuman data available so far, we see a gap in the authors' case: the absence of clear negative results in the search for g/G. The authors report no taxon where the search for the g factor was conducted with sufficient power and appropriate methods but still failed. We suggest that only after also gathering data from less social species can we ask whether, for example, social learning increases correlations between cognitive abilities. And only when correlations with non-cognitive abilities are compared can we ask what explains the increased correlation between cognitive abilities. As the authors point out, nonhuman research can help test explanations for g with designs infeasible in humans, such as cross-fostering experiments. This extends to genetic load. Using genetically uniform strains and mutation accumulation lines (although these are already extremely time-consuming in micro-organisms) could help clarify the involvement of genetic load.

We lack the space to fully address alternative explanations for interspecies G, but hope to also see joint phylogenetic tree analyses of sociality and variance explained by g. To be able to test this, recommendations for increased sample sizes in such studies should be followed (Thornton & Lukas Reference Thornton and Lukas2012). Differential measurement error across subtests and species has to be modelled and corrected for, not just used to explain negative findings.

In conclusion, we would add the following to the authors' call for research: We need individual differences of data along the whole gradient of sociality including maybe even octopuses, and studies should also examine more distal traits such as health and size. Then, the specific added value of the proposed model can be tested. We want to echo this and previous calls (Arden et al. Reference Arden, Bensky and Adams2016; Thornton & Lukas Reference Thornton and Lukas2012) for more individual differences research on nonhuman animal cognition. We hope for more stimulating evolutionary theorizing on individual differences, as in this target article.

References

Arden, R., Bensky, M. K. & Adams, M. J. (2016) A review of cognitive abilities in dogs, 1911 through 2016: More individual differences, please! Current Directions in Psychological Science 25:307–12. doi: 10.1177/0963721416667718.Google Scholar
Arslan, R. C. & Penke, L. (2015) Evolutionary genetics. In: Handbook of evolutionary psychology, vol. 2, ed. Buss, D. M., pp. 1047–66. Wiley.Google Scholar
Colom, R., Román, F. J., Abad, F. J., Shih, P. C., Privado, J., Froufe, M., Escorial, S., Martínez, K., Burgaleta, M., Quiroga, M. A., Karama, S., Haier, R. J., Thompson, P. M. & Jaeggi, S. M. (2013) Adaptive n-back training does not improve fluid intelligence at the construct level: Gains on individual tests suggest that training may enhance visuospatial processing. Intelligence 41:712–27. doi: 10.1016/j.intell.2013.09.002.Google Scholar
Deary, I. J. (2012) Looking for “system integrity” in cognitive epidemiology. Gerontology 58:545–53. doi: 10.1159/000341157.Google Scholar
Hagenaars, S. P., Gale, C. R., Deary, I. J. & Harris, S. E. (2016a) Cognitive ability and physical health: A Mendelian randomization study. bioRxiv, 84798. doi: 10.1101/084798.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hagenaars, S. P., Harris, S. E., Davies, G., Hill, W. D., Liewald, D. C. M., Ritchie, S. J., Marioni, R. E., Fawns-Ritchie, C., Cullen, B., Malik, R., METASTROKE Consortium, International Consortium for Blood Pressure GWAS, SpiroMeta Consortium, CHARGE Consortium Pulmonary Group, CHARGE Consortium Aging and Longevity Group, Worrall, B. B., Sudlow, C. L., Wardlaw, J. M., Gallacher, J., Pell, J. McIntosh, A. M., Smith, D. J., Gale, C. R. & Deary, I. J. (2016b) Shared genetic aetiology between cognitive functions and physical and mental health in UK Biobank (N=112 151) and 24 GWAS consortia. Molecular Psychiatry 21:1624–32. doi: 10.1038/mp.2015.225.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hill, W. D., Davies, G., Harris, S. E., Hagenaars, S. P., The neuroCHARGE Cognitive Working Group, Liewald, D. C., Penke, L., Gale, C. R. & Deary, I. J. (2016a) Molecular genetic aetiology of general cognitive function is enriched in evolutionarily conserved regions. Translational Psychiatry 6(12):e980.Google Scholar
Houle, D. (2000) Is there a g factor for fitness? In: The nature of intelligence (Novartis Foundation Symposium 233), ed. Bock, G., Goode, J. & Webb, K., pp. 149–70. Wiley.Google Scholar
Jacob, F. (1977) Evolution and tinkering. Science, 196:1161–66. doi: 10.1126/science.860134.Google Scholar
Johnson, W., Penke, L. & Spinath, F. M. (2011) Heritability in the era of molecular genetics: Some thoughts for understanding genetic influences on behavioural traits. European Journal of Personality 25:254–66. doi: 10.1002/per.836.Google Scholar
Noack, H., Lövdén, M. & Schmiedek, F. (2014) On the validity and generality of transfer effects in cognitive training research. Psychological Research 78:773–89. doi: 10.1007/s00426-014-0564-6.Google Scholar
Paap, K. R., Johnson, H. A. & Sawi, O. (2015) Bilingual advantages in executive functioning either do not exist or are restricted to very specific and undetermined circumstances. Cortex 69:265–78. doi: 10.1016/j.cortex.2015.04.014.Google Scholar
Penke, L., Borsboom, D., Johnson, W., Kievit, R. A., Ploeger, A. & Wicherts, J. M. (2011) Evolutionary psychology and intelligence research cannot be integrated the way Kanazawa (2010) suggested. American Psychologist 66:916–17. doi: 10.1037/a0024626.Google Scholar
Penke, L., Denissen, J. J. A. & Miller, G. F. (2007) The evolutionary genetics of personality. European Journal of Personality 21:549–87. doi: 10.1002/per.629.Google Scholar
Redick, T. S. (2015) Working memory training and interpreting interactions in intelligence interventions. Intelligence 50:1420. doi: 10.1016/j.intell.2015.01.014.Google Scholar
Solovieff, N., Cotsapas, C., Lee, P. H., Purcell, S. M. & Smoller, J. W. (2013) Pleiotropy in complex traits: Challenges and strategies. Nature Reviews Genetics 14:483–95. doi: 10.1038/nrg3461.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Thornton, A. & Lukas, D. (2012) Individual variation in cognitive performance: Developmental and evolutionary perspectives. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences 367:2773–83. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2012.0214.Google Scholar