Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-g4j75 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T15:37:29.320Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Against free energy, for direct perception

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 September 2022

Thomas A. Stoffregen
Affiliation:
The School of Kinesiology, University of Minnesota, Minneapolis, MN 55455, USAtas@umn.eduhttps://apal.umn.edu/
Robert Heath
Affiliation:
Hiawatha Valley Education District, Winona, MN 55987, USAptbob55987@yahoo.com

Abstract

We question the free energy principle (FEP) as it is used in contemporary physics. If the FEP is incorrect in physics, then it cannot ground the authors' arguments. We also question the assumption that perception requires inference. We argue that perception (including perception of social affordances) can be direct, in which case inference is not required.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

We raise an issue relating to the physics that undergird the free energy principle (FEP), and one relating to whether the FEP actually is relevant to perception, and to phenomena of animacy, in general.

The authors argue the merits of various formulations of the FEP in relation to animacy (e.g., Markov blankets, Friston blankets, Pearl blankets). They acknowledge that “the core of the FEP rests upon an intertwined web of mathematical constructs borrowed from physics” (sect. 1, para. 4). They do not question the validity of the underlying physics of the FEP. However, a consistent thread of scholarship raises doubts about the validity of the FEP as a description of physical reality (rather than as a mathematical abstraction that is not meant to be taken as a claim about reality; Schrodinger, Reference Schrodinger1952a, Reference Schrodinger1952b).

All versions of the FEP assume that time is discrete. That is, the mathematical equations of the FEP are defined only if we assume that time is discrete. In most physics, models and theories are structured in ways that assume that time exists as discrete temporal units. This assumption is accepted even by scholars who have criticized other aspects of the FEP (e.g., Colombo and Palacios, Reference Colombo and Palacios2021; Raja, Valluri, Baggs, Chemero, and Anderson, Reference Raja, Valluri, Baggs, Chemero and Anderson2021; Unnikrishnan, Reference Unnikrishnan2020). Yet not everyone accepts this assumption. Bergson (Reference Bergson and Jacobson1922/1999) claimed that time does not exist in discrete units but, rather, exists as a continuum that cannot be sectioned into discrete units (Robbins, Reference Robbins2014). At minimum, Bergson's alternative conception of time alerts us to the fact that mainstream views of discrete time are assumptions or descriptions, rather than established facts (Schrodinger, Reference Schrodinger1952a, Reference Schrodinger1952b). Claims that are based on this assumption, such as Friston's FEP and the current authors' treatment, should more explicitly acknowledge their reliance on these contingent assumptions. It is also important to carefully evaluate the validity of Bergson's alternative perspective and the implications it may have for our understanding of both physics and animacy.

Bergson's (Reference Bergson and Jacobson1922/1999) conception of time is consistent with Gibson's conception of physics, including time. Gibson argued that traditional physics, including electromagnetism, thermodynamics, quantum mechanics, and abstract, discrete time, cannot account for the phenomena of animacy (Gibson, Reference Gibson, Fraser and Lawrence1975, Reference Gibson1979). More broadly, Rosen (Reference Rosen1991) argued that living things rely on physical principles (what he referred to as “new physics”) that are primary to the physics of inanimacy. Put plainly, each of these scholars raised deep questions, not only about the presumed primacy of traditional physics, but also about its literal accuracy as a description of reality. Friston's FEP is part of an ancient tradition by which the physics of inanimacy are assumed to be basic, with the physics of animacy being derivative. Bergson, Gibson, Rosen, and others argue just the opposite: That the physics of animacy are primary, and the physics of inanimacy derivative.

The above considerations relate intimately to our second issue, which concerns the authors' assumption that perception is inferential. They offer as options only inference with a model, or inference within a model. But other options exist. The ecological approach to perception and action claims that the animal–environment interaction lawfully structures patterns in ambient energy such that reality is specified (e.g., Gibson, Reference Gibson1966; Turvey, Reference Turvey2019). If reality is specified, then perception can be direct and, consequently, there is no requirement for inference. Bruineberg, Chemero, and Rietveld (Reference Bruineberg, Chemero and Rietveld2019) accepted this logic, but argued that social affordances cannot be specified and that, therefore, perception of social affordances cannot be direct. It would follow that knowledge of social affordances must depend upon inference. The sole basis for their argument was the fact that social affordances emerge from social conventions, such as linguistic grammar and syntax, or highway speed limits. However, they offered no evidence, either logical or empirical, that social conventions or social affordances actually cannot be specified.

The fact that social affordances emerge from social conventions does not imply that they are free of physical law, such that they cannot be specified. Social conventions are constrained by physical law. For example, all phonetic systems must conform to the acoustic capabilities of the speech organs. Similarly, grammar and syntax, which vary widely across languages, nevertheless exhibit consistencies, and cannot operate outside physical law. Language is used to communicate about physical reality, such that grammar and syntax may be constrained by the physical laws that constrain the events that are the principal subject of linguistic interaction (e.g., Anthony, Reference Anthony2007). Even metaphor is grounded in embodied experience (Gibbs, Lima, & Francozo, Reference Gibbs, Lima and Francozo2004). In short, the claim that social affordances cannot be specified and that, therefore, perception must be inferential, is a claim, rather than a self-evident fact. It may be that social affordances are specified in conformity with physical law, such that all perception can be direct (e.g., Stoffregen and Bardy, Reference Stoffregen and Bardy2001; Stoffregen, Mantel, and Bardy, Reference Stoffregen, Mantel and Bardy2017).

Empirical research can help to address the continuity or unity of perception. Empirical research is consistent with the idea that perception of social affordances may be direct. As one example, human observers can transition easily between perception of personal and interpersonal affordances (e.g., Richardson, Marsh, and Baron, Reference Richardson, Marsh and Baron2007), suggesting that perception of personal and interpersonal affordances may have a similar basis. Perception of social affordances may be grounded in the perception and control of affordances for the individual. For example, locomotor experience (typically, learning to crawl) causally drives the infant's developing understanding of referential communication (e.g., Campos et al., Reference Campos, Anderson, Barbu-Roth, Hubbard, Hertenstein and Witherington2000), while the physical experience of interpersonal synchrony has causal influence on the development of prosocial behavior (Cirelli, Reference Cirelli2018), and social conventions are taught through guided interactions (Nonaka & Stoffregen, Reference Nonaka and Stoffregen2020; Reed, Reference Reed1996). These findings suggest that perception of social affordances may emerge from the kinds of physical interactions that Bruineberg et al. (Reference Bruineberg, Chemero and Rietveld2019) accepted as being amenable to direct perception.

Acceptance of Friston's FEP mandates rejection of any form of direct perception (e.g., Friston, Reference Friston2013). This stark requirement may explain the uncritical nature of the authors' views on specification (Bruineberg et al., Reference Bruineberg, Chemero and Rietveld2019). The alternative is equally stark: If perception is direct, then Friston's FEP cannot be a factual description of animate systems.

Financial support

Thomas A. Stoffregen was supported by NSF-1901423, CHS: Medium: Prediction, Early Detection, and Mitigation of Virtual Reality Simulator Sickness.

Conflict of interest

None.

References

Anthony, D. W. (2007). The horse, the wheel, and language. Princeton University Press. https://doi.org/10.1515/9781400831104Google Scholar
Bergson, H. (1999). Duration and simultaneity. Trans. Jacobson, Leon. Clinaman Press. (Original work published in 1922).Google Scholar
Bruineberg, J., Chemero, A., & Rietveld, E. (2019). General ecological information supports engagement with affordances for “higher” cognition. Synthese, 196, 52315251. doi:10.1007/s11229-018-1716-9CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Campos, J. J., Anderson, D. I., Barbu-Roth, M., Hubbard, E. M., Hertenstein, M. J., & Witherington, D. (2000). Travel broadens the mind. Infancy, 1, 149219.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cirelli, L. K. (2018). How interpersonal synchrony facilitates early prosocial behavior. Current Opinion in Psychology, 20, 3539. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.copsyc.2017.08.009CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Colombo, M., & Palacios, P. (2021). Non-equilibrium thermodynamics and the free energy principle in biology. Biology & Philosophy, 36, 41. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-021-09818-xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friston, K. J. (2013). Life as we know it. Journal of the Royal Society Interface, 10, 20130475.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibbs, R. W., Lima, P. L. C., & Francozo, E. (2004). Metaphor is grounded in embodied experience. Journal of Pragmatics, 36, 11891210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibson, J. J. (1966). The senses considered as perceptual systems. Houghton-Mifflin.Google Scholar
Gibson, J. J. (1975). Events are perceivable but time is not. In Fraser, J. T. & Lawrence, N. (Eds.), The study of time II (pp. 295301). Springer-Verlag.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Houghton-Mifflin.Google Scholar
Nonaka, T., & Stoffregen, T. A. (2020). Social interaction in the emergence of toddler's mealtime spoon use. Developmental Psychobiology, 62, 11241133. doi:10.1002/dev.21978CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Raja, V., Valluri, D., Baggs, E., Chemero, A., & Anderson, M. L. (2021). The Markov blanket trick: On the scope of the free energy principle and active inference. Physics of Life Reviews, 39, 4972. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.plrev.2021.09.001CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Reed, E. S. (1996). Encountering the world: Toward an ecological psychology. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Richardson, M. J., Marsh, K. L., & Baron, R. M. (2007). Judging and actualizing intrapersonal and interpersonal affordances. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception & Performance, 33, 845859. doi:10.1037/0096-1523.33.4.845Google ScholarPubMed
Robbins, S. E. (2014). The mists of special relativity: Time, consciousness, and a deep illusion in physics. CreateSpace.Google Scholar
Rosen, R. (1991). Life itself. A comprehensive inquiry into the nature, origin, and fabrication of life. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Schrodinger, E. (1952a). Are there quantum jumps? Part I. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 3, 109123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schrodinger, E. (1952b). Are there quantum jumps? Part II. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 3, 233242. doi:10.1093/bjps/III.11.233CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stoffregen, T. A., & Bardy, B. G. (2001). On specification and the senses. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24, 195261.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Stoffregen, T. A., Mantel, B., & Bardy, B. G. (2017). The senses considered as one perceptual system. Ecological Psychology, 29, 165197.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turvey, M. T. (2019). Lectures on perception: An ecological perspective. Routledge.Google Scholar
Unnikrishnan, C. S. (2020). A new gravitational paradigm for relativity and dynamics, and its philosophical scope. Journal of Physics, Conference Series, 1466, 012007. doi: 10.1088/1742-6596/1466/1/012007CrossRefGoogle Scholar