Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-d8cs5 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T10:29:33.042Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Mechanistic modeling for the masses

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 February 2022

Matthew A. Turner
Affiliation:
Department of Cognitive and Information Sciences, University of California, Merced, Merced, CA95343, USA. mturner8@ucmerced.edu; psmaldino@ucmerced.edu; http://mt.digital, http://smaldino.com
Paul E. Smaldino
Affiliation:
Department of Cognitive and Information Sciences, University of California, Merced, Merced, CA95343, USA. mturner8@ucmerced.edu; psmaldino@ucmerced.edu; http://mt.digital, http://smaldino.com

Abstract

The generalizability crisis is compounded, or even partially caused, by a lack of specificity in psychological theories. Expanding the use of mechanistic models among psychologists is therefore important, but faces numerous hurdles. A cultural evolutionary approach can help guide and evaluate interventions to improve modeling efforts in psychology, such as developing standards and implementing them at the institutional level.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

Yarkoni says there's a generalizability crisis, and we largely agree. In some ways it's actually worse than he suggests, because of widespread ambiguity and imprecision in specifying theories. It's very hard to test theories if they are imprecise (Smaldino, Reference Smaldino2019, Reference Smaldino2020). This isn't just a matter of limitations in mapping specific experiments to more general verbal constructs. Rather, those verbal constructs themselves are often so poorly described that severe tests of their applicability become nearly impossible (Mayo, Reference Mayo2018; Popper, Reference Popper1963). In this light, accounting for more sources of variance in the manner Yarkoni recommends might even be harmful if doing so props up theories that are poorly specified, further insulating such theories from further scrutiny (Smaldino, Reference Smaldino2016). It is plausible that failure to clearly specify the components, relationships, and processes in systems of interest leads to exactly those failures to align verbal and statistical models that characterize the generalizability crisis. If one cannot specify how system components influence one another, how could one begin to guess at how observed data might vary? We suggest that this difficulty in precision, which some have named the “theory crisis” (Oberauer & Lewandowsky, Reference Oberauer and Lewandowsky2019), is inherently interlinked with the generalizability crisis. Theories based solely on statistical correlation are notoriously hard to evaluate (Fried, Reference Fried2020; Meehl, Reference Meehl1990).

Mechanistic explanations and formal models can help by forcing the researcher to articulate their guiding assumptions, decomposing their study system into the parts, properties, and relationships critical for well-formed hypotheses (Kauffman, Reference Kauffman, Buck and Cohen1971; Smaldino, Reference Smaldino, Vallacher, Nowak and Read2017, Reference Smaldino2020). Mechanistic explanations also allow us to ask “what if things had been different” in a way that non-mechanistic explanations cannot (Craver, Reference Craver2006). When mechanistic models are operationalized as mathematical or computational models, simulation experiments can be performed that mirror real-world experiments to understand, a priori, how certain outcome variables might be affected by treatment or contextual variables (Schank, May, & Joshi, Reference Schank, May, Joshi, Griesemer, Wimsatt and Caporael2014). Even purely verbal mechanistic explanations are a welcome, if marginal, improvement over psychological theories that are too often founded on a series of interesting correlations – each of those correlations potentially a victim of non-replicability or overgeneralization. Mechanistic models facilitate expanded qualitative analyses as well, since mechanistic models can often simplify systems of interest to the point where they can be represented as simple box-and-arrow type diagrams for rapid comprehension, critique, correction, and extension.

Expanding the use of mechanistic explanations in psychology would require a substantial restructuring of the operation and training of psychological scientists. In the long run, this will likely require fairly major institutional change (Smaldino, Turner, & Contreras Kallens, Reference Smaldino, Turner and Contreras Kallens2019). It is unclear at the present whether the changes will come from within psychology and related departments, or by incursion from other disciplines better trained in formal methods and interested in the juicy problems previously guarded as the domain of psychologists (Smaldino, Reference Smaldino2020). Time will tell.

For now, there are some things individuals and institutions can do in the short term to kickstart improvements. Strengthening the theoretical foundations in ways needed to mitigate the generalizability and theory crises requires increased interdisciplinarity, technical expertise, and philosophical scrutiny of assumptions (Smaldino, Reference Smaldino2020). Agencies could help by increasing funding for interdisciplinary work between researchers using different approaches to study related problems in the social and behavioral sciences, fostering deeper collaborations between experts in modeling and complex systems and topic experts more familiar with experimental or observational methods. Such projects could also include funding for research software developers and other professional research staff to assist with technical intricacies and provide modeling expertise required to model and analyze complex systems mechanistically. These interdisciplinary teams could collaboratively produce new cyberinfrastructure tools to make mechanistic modeling easier for modeling novices. Later iterations could even extend these tools to automate the generation of computer models and computational experiments to identify sources of variance, and automatically generate statistical models based on the generated computational model (Rand, Reference Rand, Davis, O'Mahony and Pfautz2019).

The study of cultural evolution provides some insights into how we might think about the spread of better practices (Gervais, Reference Gervais2021; Smaldino et al., Reference Smaldino2019; Smaldino & O'Connor, Reference Smaldino and O'Connor2020), including the use and improvement of mechanistic explanations in psychology literature. One approach is to consider that the strategy of failing to align verbal and statistical models is a communication strategy which has been culturally transmitted to generations of psychology trainees. The lack of specificity and resulting lack of alignment between theory and statistical model may be an instance of deceptive signaling (in the ecological sense, which doesn't imply intent to deceive), where a lack of theoretical rigor is covered up with statistical tests and a recitation of related observed correlations. This maps the generalizability crisis onto analogous problems for which models already exist as starting points, including models of signaling in collaborative environments (Smaldino & Turner, Reference Smaldino and Turner2020; Smaldino, Flamson, & McElreath, Reference Smaldino, Flamson and McElreath2018; Tiokhin et al., Reference Tiokhin, Panchanathan, Lakens, Vazire, Morgan and Zollman2021), the evolution of scientific knowledge on networks (O'Connor & Weatherall, Reference O'Connor and Weatherall2018, Reference O'Connor, Weatherall, Allen and Howell2020; Zollman, Reference Zollman2007, Reference Zollman2010, Reference Zollman2013), and the effect of prevailing social power on individual choices (Bergstrom, Foster, & Song, Reference Bergstrom, Foster and Song2016; Henrich & Boyd, Reference Henrich and Boyd2008; Higginson & Munafò, Reference Higginson and Munafò2016; O'Connor, Reference O'Connor2019). With some further development, these models could be used to conduct several “what if things are different” computational experiments under a variety of assumptions to understand what might happen if various interpersonal or institutional changes were instituted. If any of the considered approaches seem promising in silica, it will strengthen the case to expend resources to try them in the real world.

Doing all this is likely to be hard, but worth it. A lack of mechanistic modeling at least complicates the generalizability crisis and is perhaps partly to blame. While this problem is frustrating, it also provides a valuable opportunity to apply social science to an important problem: its own bad state of affairs. The recent, rapid adoption of better practices in psychology and across the sciences, including replication (even if sometimes misguided), registered reports, open science initiatives, data management plans, and more, indicate that many scientists are willing to make changes toward better practices. Changes to institutional incentives must follow.

Financial support

This research received no specific grant from any funding agency, commercial or not-for-profit sectors.

Conflict of interest

None.

References

Bergstrom, C. T., Foster, J. G., & Song, Y. (2016). Why scientists chase big problems: Individual strategy and social optimality. arXiv, 1605.05822.Google Scholar
Craver, C. F. (2006). When mechanistic models explain. Synthese, 153(3), 355376.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fried, E. I. (2020). Lack of theory building and testing impedes progress in the factor and network literature. Psychological Inquiry, 31(4), 271288.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gervais, W. M. (2021). Practical methodological reform needs good theory. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 16(4), 827843.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Henrich, J., & Boyd, R. (2008). Division of labor, economic specialization, and the evolution of social stratification. Current Anthropology, 49(4), 715724.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Higginson, A. D., & Munafò, M. R. (2016). Current incentives for scientists lead to underpowered studies with erroneous conclusions. PLoS Biology, 14(11), e2000995.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kauffman, S. A. (1971). Articulation of parts explanation in biology and the rational search for them. In Buck, R. C. & Cohen, R. S. (Eds.), PSA 1970 (pp. 257272). Irvine, CA: Philosophy of Science Association.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayo, D. G. (2018). Statistical inference as severe testing. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meehl, P. E. (1990). Why summaries of research on psychological theories are often uninterpretable. Psychological Reports, 66, 195244.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Connor, C. (2019). The origins of unfairness. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Connor, C., & Weatherall, J. O. (2018). Scientific polarization. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 8(3), 855875.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Connor, C., & Weatherall, J. O. (2020). False beliefs and the social structure of science: Some models and case studies. In Allen, D. M. & Howell, J. W. (Eds.), Groupthink in science (pp. 3748). Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oberauer, K., & Lewandowsky, S. (2019). Addressing the theory crisis in psychology. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 26(5), 15961618.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Popper, K. (1963). Conjectures and refutations. Routledge.Google Scholar
Rand, W. (2019). Theory-interpretable, data-driven agent-based modeling. In Davis, P. K., O'Mahony, A. & Pfautz, J. (Eds.), Social-behavioral modeling for complex systems (pp. 337357). Wiley.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schank, J. C., May, C. J., & Joshi, S. S. (2014). Models as scaffold for understanding. In Griesemer, J. R., Wimsatt, W. C. & Caporael, L. R. (Eds.), Developing scaffolds in evolution, culture, and cognition (pp. 147167). MIT Press.Google Scholar
Smaldino, P. (2019). Better methods can't make up for mediocre theory. Nature, 575, 9.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Smaldino, P. E. (2016). Not even wrong: Imprecision perpetuates the illusion of understanding at the cost of actual understanding. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 39, e163.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Smaldino, P. E. (2017). Models are stupid, and we need more of them. In Vallacher, R. R., Nowak, A. & Read, S. J. (Eds.), Computational social psychology (pp. 311331). Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smaldino, P. E. (2020). How to build a strong theoretical foundation. Psychological Inquiry, 31(4), 297301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smaldino, P. E., Flamson, T. J., & McElreath, R. (2018). The evolution of covert signaling. Scientific Reports, 8, 4905. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41598-018-22926-1.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Smaldino, P. E., & O'Connor, C. (2020). Interdisciplinarity can aid the spread of better methods between communities. MetaArXiv. Retrieved from https://osf.io/preprints/metaarxiv/cm5v3/.Google Scholar
Smaldino, P. E., & Turner, M. A. (2020). Covert signaling is an adaptive communication strategy in diverse populations. SocArXiv. Retrieved from https://osf.io/preprints/socarxiv/j9wyn/.Google Scholar
Smaldino, P. E., Turner, M. A., & Contreras Kallens, P. A. (2019). Open science and modified funding lotteries can impede the natural selection of bad science. Royal Society Open Science, 6(8), 191249.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tiokhin, L., Panchanathan, K., Lakens, D., Vazire, S., Morgan, T., & Zollman, K. (2021). Honest signaling in academic publishing. PLoS ONE, 16(2), e0246675.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Zollman, K. J. S. (2007). The communication structure of epistemic communities. Philosophy of Science, 74(5), 574587.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zollman, K. J. S. (2013). Network epistemology: Communication in epistemic communities. Philosophy Compass, 8(1), 1527.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zollman, K. J. S. (2010). Social structure and the effects of conformity. Synthese, 172(3), 317340.CrossRefGoogle Scholar