Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-f46jp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-07T05:00:23.720Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Evolution after mirror neurons: Tapping the shared manifold through secondary adaptation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 April 2014

Matthew M. Gervais*
Affiliation:
Department of Anthropology, Center for Behavior, Evolution, and Culture, University of California, Los Angeles, Los Angeles, CA 90095. mgervais@ucla.eduhttps://sites.google.com/site/matthewmgervais/

Abstract

Cook et al. laudably call for careful comparative research into the development of mirror neurons. However, they do so within an impoverished evolutionary framework that does not clearly distinguish ultimate and proximate causes and their reciprocal relations. As a result, they overlook evidence for the reliable develop of mirror neurons in biological and cultural traits evolved to work through them.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2014 

Cook et al. have done a great service by marshaling the mounting evidence that experience influences the operation of mirror neurons (MNs). This work reinforces other recent calls (e.g., Henrich et al. Reference Henrich, Heine and Norenzayan2010) to study the effects of variable environments, both in humans (across cultures) and in nonhuman primates (across rearing and field settings), on the development of neural and psychological systems. Cook et al. advance this issue with the hypothesis that specific aspects of developmental environments influence the ontogeny and functions of MN systems. Encouragingly, anthropologists have documented relevant population variation, including in adult interactions with infants (e.g., Ochs & Schieffelin Reference Ochs, Schieffelin, Shweder and Levine1984), and in interactive practices across cultural domains (Fiske Reference Fiske1992). Primatologists and comparative psychologists have also increasingly catalogued variation in social behaviors across natural populations (Whiten et al. Reference Whiten, Goodall, McGrew, Nishida, Reynolds, Sugiyama, Tutin, Wrangham and Boesch2001) and captive environments (Call & Tomasello Reference Call, Tomasello, Russon, Bard and Parker1996; Russell et al. Reference Russell, Lyn, Schaeffer and Hopkins2011). While the painstaking comparative groundwork is just beginning, it is hard to dispute Cook et al. on the value of the enterprise.

However, Cook et al. rely on a curiously impoverished evolutionary framework that likely hinders the empirical project they advocate. The authors do not clearly distinguish and relate types of biological causation (Laland et al. Reference Laland, Sterelny, Odling-Smee, Hoppitt and Uller2011). To be sure, they do clearly propose both a proximate/ontogenetic and an ultimate/functional explanation of MNs – MN development is driven by action-perception contingency learning, and is a by-product of associative learning mechanisms that bear no evidence of adaptive specialization for MNs. However, Cook et al. develop alternative approaches to this “associative” account that are arbitrary conjunctions of ultimate and proximate explanations. Their “genetic” account weds a nativist ontogenetic explanation to a specific ultimate function, “action understanding.” That this account is said to “combine” questions of origin and function, while the associative account “dissociates” them, is an artificial consequence of the “genetic” hypothesis as presented. The authors are mistaken when they state that, “If MNs were a genetic adaptation, it is likely that their properties would be relatively invariant across developmental environments” (sect. 9.1.1). Natural selection operates on developmental systems through the phenotypes they produce, and MN development could be largely experience-dependent while having a specific evolved function (see Barrett Reference Barrett2012). Likewise, MNs could be highly canalized and reliably developing, yet could have evolved for functions other than “action understanding,” including empathy (Gallese Reference Gallese2003; Preston & de Waal Reference Preston and de Waal2002) – a widely discussed and investigated ultimate hypothesis that the target article relegates to a footnote. The “genetic” hypothesis is at best an arbitrary hypothesis, and at worst a straw man.

In addition, contrasting “canalization” and “exaptation” as Cook et al. do has the unfortunate effect of obscuring interesting phylogenetic questions. While the authors argue that “the motivation for invoking exaptation is not compelling” (sect. 8.2, para. 1), they advocate the purest possible exaptation hypothesis – an ancient adaptation was coopted for producing MNs without any “secondary adaptation” (Gould & Vrba Reference Gould and Vrba1982). The authors go on to argue that any species capable of associative learning should be capable of developing MNs, and they predict controlled training regiments will produce MNs in lab rats. Intriguing, but this raises a question: Why do humans and macaques (and likely other species: Mancini et al. Reference Mancini, Ferrari and Palagi2013; Mui et al. Reference Mui, Haselgrove, Pearce and Heyes2008; Range et al. Reference Range, Huber and Heyes2011) “naturally” develop mirror neurons, while rats apparently do not? Is this a happy accident of variation in early developmental environments? Or has there been varying selection pressures across species for secondary adaptations that facilitate MN development (such as mother–infant face-to-face interaction; Ferrari et al. Reference Ferrari, Paukner, Ionica and Suomi2009b)?

In general, the target article is overly restrictive in discussing such canalizing mechanisms. Cook et al. discuss only one attention bias, infant self-observation of reaching. They overlook other biases, both in infants and in adults, that could facilitate MN development. For example, in humans the properties of infant-directed speech (Bryant & Barrett Reference Bryant and Barrett2007) and adult encouragement and imitation (Bornstein et al. Reference Bornstein, Tamis-LeMonda, Tal, Ludemann, Toda, Rahn, Pêcheux, Azuma and Vardi1992) show evidence of invariance across cultures, while infants show perceptual preferences for faces (Valenza et al. Reference Valenza, Simion, Cassia and Umiltà1996) and infant-directed motion (Brand & Shallcross Reference Brand and Shallcross2008). In addition, no mention is made of mounting evidence that associative learning mechanisms often evince domain-specific design features, such as preparedness to learn particular fitness-relevant contingencies (Barrett & Broesch Reference Barrett and Broesch2012; Garcia & Koelling Reference Garcia and Koelling1966).

Cook et al. also fail to appreciate the likely evolutionary consequences of MNs reliably developing in a species. Although ultimate and proximate explanations are classically considered orthogonal, they can be reciprocally related, such as when proximate mechanisms become part of the selective environment (Laland et al. Reference Laland, Sterelny, Odling-Smee, Hoppitt and Uller2011). Selection for behaviors and capacities that exploit MNs would be a clear case of this. Expressions of emotion may be a case in point. There is strong evidence that emotional contagion and mimicry of expressions are mediated by MNs (Carr et al. Reference Carr, Iacoboni, Dubeau, Mazziotta and Lenzi2003; Kircher et al. Reference Kircher, Pohl, Krach, Thimm, Schulte-Rüther, Anders and Mathiak2013; Wicker et al. Reference Wicker, Keysers, Plailly, Royet, Gallese, Rizzolatti and Aiguier2003) and have significant consequences for social competencies (Pfeifer et al. Reference Pfeifer, Iacoboni, Mazziotta and Dapretto2008) and relationships (Lakin et al. Reference Lakin, Jefferis, Cheng and Chartrand2003). Given both mirror neurons and selection for empathy and/or emotional coordination, evolution could well craft emotional expressions for facilitating shared emotion. For example, we have argued that laughter evolved as a medium for playful emotional contagion that taps MNs to facilitate mutually beneficial social play (Gervais & Wilson Reference Gervais and Wilson2005; see also Davila-Ross et al. Reference Davila-Ross, Allcock, Thomas and Bard2011). To the extent that human expressions of emotion are elaborated homologues of ancestral ape expressions (Parr et al. Reference Parr, Waller and Vick2007), one might implicate uniquely human selection pressures that attended ratcheting interdependence (Tomasello et al. Reference Tomasello, Melis, Tennie, Wyman and Herrmann2012). Further, the emergence of cultural evolutionary processes in humans (Boyd et al. Reference Boyd, Richerson and Henrich2011) may have created an additional consequence of MNs – selection for cultural practices (e.g., religious rituals; Atkinson & Whitehouse Reference Atkinson and Whitehouse2011; Fiske Reference Fiske1992) that facilitate MN development and build social bonds through them.

Even if mirror neurons develop through associative learning, they may be reliably developing adaptations. Evidence of secondary adaptation, including biological and cultural traits designed to exploit MNs, would be evidence of a history of such reliable development. The investigation of such derived traits should thus be integral to the mirror neuron enterprise.

References

Atkinson, Q. D. & Whitehouse, H. (2011) The cultural morphospace of ritual form: Examining modes of religiosity cross-culturally. Evolution and Human Behavior 32(1):5062.Google Scholar
Barrett, H. C. (2012) A hierarchical model of the evolution of human brain specializations. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 109:10733–40.Google Scholar
Barrett, H. C. & Broesch, J. (2012) Prepared social learning about dangerous animals in children. Evolution and Human Behavior 33(5):499508.Google Scholar
Bornstein, M. H., Tamis-LeMonda, C. S., Tal, J., Ludemann, P., Toda, S., Rahn, C. W., Pêcheux, M. G., Azuma, H. & Vardi, D. (1992) Maternal responsiveness to infants in three societies: The United States, France, and Japan. Child Development 63(4):808–21.Google Scholar
Boyd, R., Richerson, P. J. & Henrich, J. (2011) The cultural niche: Why social learning is essential for human adaptation. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 108(Suppl. 2):10918–25.Google Scholar
Brand, R. J. & Shallcross, W. L. (2008) Infants prefer motionese to adult-directed action. Developmental Science 11(6):853–61.Google Scholar
Bryant, G. A. & Barrett, H. C. (2007) Recognizing intentions in infant-directed speech evidence for universals. Psychological Science 18(8):746–51.Google Scholar
Call, J. & Tomasello, M. (1996) The effect of humans on the cognitive development of apes. In: Reaching into thought: The minds of the Great Apes, ed. Russon, A. E., Bard, K. A., & Parker, S. T., pp. 371403. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Carr, L., Iacoboni, M., Dubeau, M. C., Mazziotta, J. C. & Lenzi, G. L. (2003) Neural mechanisms of empathy in humans: A relay from neural systems for imitation to limbic areas. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 100(9):5497–502.Google Scholar
Davila-Ross, M., Allcock, B., Thomas, C. & Bard, K. A. (2011) Aping expressions? Chimpanzees produce distinct laugh types when responding to laughter of others. Emotion 11(5):1013.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ferrari, P. F., Paukner, A., Ionica, C. & Suomi, S. J. (2009b) Reciprocal face-to-face communication between rhesus macaque mothers and their newborn infants. Current Biology 19(20):1768–72.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fiske, A. P. (1992) The four elementary forms of sociality: Framework for a unified theory of social relations. Psychological Review 99(4):689.Google Scholar
Gallese, V. (2003) The roots of empathy: The shared manifold hypothesis and the neural basis of intersubjectivity. Psychopathology 36(4):171–80.Google Scholar
Garcia, J. & Koelling, R. A. (1966) Relation of cue to consequence in avoidance learning. Psychonomic Science 4(1):123–24.Google Scholar
Gervais, M. & Wilson, D. S. (2005) The evolution and functions of laughter and humor: A synthetic approach. The Quarterly Review of Biology 80(4):395430.Google Scholar
Gould, S. J. & Vrba, E. S. (1982) Exaptation – a missing term in the science of form. Paleobiology 8(1):415.Google Scholar
Henrich, J., Heine, S. J. & Norenzayan, A. (2010) The weirdest people in the world. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33(2–3):6183.Google Scholar
Kircher, T., Pohl, A., Krach, S., Thimm, M., Schulte-Rüther, M., Anders, S. & Mathiak, K. (2013) Affect-specific activation of shared networks for perception and execution of facial expressions. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience 8(4):370377.Google Scholar
Lakin, J. L., Jefferis, V. E., Cheng, C. M. & Chartrand, T. L. (2003) The chameleon effect as social glue: Evidence for the evolutionary significance of nonconscious mimicry. Journal of Nonverbal Behavior 27(3):145–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laland, K. N., Sterelny, K., Odling-Smee, J., Hoppitt, W. & Uller, T. (2011) Cause and effect in biology revisited: Is Mayr's proximate-ultimate dichotomy still useful? Science 334(6062):1512–16.Google Scholar
Mancini, G., Ferrari, P. F. & Palagi, E. (2013) Rapid facial mimicry in Geladas. Scientific Reports 3(1527):16.Google Scholar
Mui, R., Haselgrove, M., Pearce, J. & Heyes, C. (2008) Automatic imitation in budgerigars. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 275(1651): 2547–53.Google Scholar
Ochs, E. & Schieffelin, B. (1984) Language acquisition and socialization: Three developmental stories and their implications. In: Culture Theory: Essays on mind, self, and emotion, ed. Shweder, R. A. & Levine, R. A., pp. 276320. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Parr, L. A., Waller, B. M. & Vick, S. J. (2007) New developments in understanding emotional facial signals in chimpanzees. Current Directions in Psychological Science 16(3):117–22.Google Scholar
Pfeifer, J. H., Iacoboni, M., Mazziotta, J. C. & Dapretto, M. (2008) Mirroring others' emotions relates to empathy and interpersonal competence in children. Neuroimage 39(4):2076–85.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Preston, S. D. & de Waal, F. (2002) Empathy: Its ultimate and proximate bases. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25(1):120.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Range, F., Huber, L. & Heyes, C. (2011) Automatic imitation in dogs. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 278(1703):211–17.Google Scholar
Russell, J. L., Lyn, H., Schaeffer, J. A. & Hopkins, W. D. (2011) The role of socio-communicative rearing environments in the development of social and physical cognition in apes. Developmental Science 14(6):1459–70.Google Scholar
Tomasello, M., Melis, A. P., Tennie, C., Wyman, E. & Herrmann, E. (2012) Two key steps in the evolution of human cooperation. Current Anthropology 53(6):673–92.Google Scholar
Valenza, E., Simion, F., Cassia, V. M. & Umiltà, C. (1996) Face preference at birth. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 22(4):892903.Google Scholar
Whiten, A., Goodall, J., McGrew, W. C., Nishida, T., Reynolds, V., Sugiyama, Y., Tutin, C. E. G, Wrangham, R. & Boesch, C. (2001) Charting cultural variation in chimpanzees. Behaviour 138(11):1481–516.Google Scholar
Wicker, B., Keysers, C., Plailly, J., Royet, J. P., Gallese, V., Rizzolatti, G. & Aiguier, C. J. (2003) Both of us disgusted in my insula: The common neural basis of seeing and feeling disgust. Neuron 40:655–64.Google Scholar