Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-kw2vx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-11T18:57:34.736Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The contributions of non-numeric dimensions to number encoding, representations, and decision-making factors

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 July 2017

Darko Odic*
Affiliation:
University of British Columbia, Vancouver, British Columbia, V6T 1Z4, Canadadarko.odic@psych.ubc.cahttp://www.odic.psych.ubc.ca

Abstract

Leibovich et al. suggest that congruency effects in number perception (biases towards smaller, denser, etc., dots) are evidence for the number's dependence on these dimensions. I argue that they fail to differentiate between effects at three distinct levels of number perception – encoding, representations, and decision making – and that differentiating between these allows the number to be independent from, but correlated with, non-numeric dimensions.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2017 

Visual and auditory number stimuli inherently correlate with dimensions such as size, density, rate, and so forth, and observers are sometimes biased towards these dimensions: Changing the density of a collection of dots also changes which set observers believe to be more numerous. Leibovich et al., following the footsteps of recent findings reporting such “congruency effects,” argue that number may be entirely or partly dependent on these dimensions – that there is no innate number sense independent from our perception of density, convex hull, size, and so forth.

However, their critique leaves a key question open: At what level of processing do non-numeric dimensions exert their hold on number? There are at least three independent possibilities, and only one of them is consistent with the central claim against an independent number sense.

The first possibility is that number is encoded using low-level visual features, such as orientation, contrast, spatial frequency, and so forth, which are shared with other dimensions, rather than out of its own dedicated feature detectors (e.g., Dakin et al. Reference Dakin, Tibber, Greenwood, Kingdom and Morgan2011 vs. Burr & Ross Reference Burr and Ross2008). For example, consider that face perception strongly depends on a unique mix of low- and high-spatial frequency, and, therefore, changing frequency information also changes which emotion is most strongly perceived (Vuilleumier et al. Reference Vuilleumier, Armony, Driver and Dolan2003). In this same manner, there are now many reasons to suspect that number encoding depends on features such as low-spatial frequency (Dakin et al. Reference Dakin, Tibber, Greenwood, Kingdom and Morgan2011), and that it may even depend on distinct features at different levels of crowding (Anobile et al. Reference Anobile, Cicchini and Burr2014). Thus, manipulating density (i.e., low-spatial frequency information) can result in changes in number perception, not because of number being represented as density, but rather because of their shared dependence on identical low-level features. Congruency effects, therefore, could be interpreted as positive results describing the nature of low-level features used to encode number, not as evidence against its dependence on non-numeric dimensions. At the very least, claims to number's non-independence must first account for the shared low-level features.

The second possibility is that number and non-numeric dimensions compete for the same decision-making component, such as putting a common load on working memory or yielding similar response conflicts (Hurewitz et al. Reference Hurewitz, Gelman and Schnitzer2006; Odic et al. Reference Odic, Lisboa, Eisinger, Olivera, Maiche and Halberda2016; Van Opstal & Verguts Reference Van Opstal and Verguts2013). Once again, consider an analogy: congruency effects found in the Stroop effect do not imply that color perception is dependent on and statistically learned from reading ability, but rather that multiple dimensions can compete for the same response. Because we know that density and area perception tend to be more accurate in adults compared with number, there is plenty of reason to think that these dimensions will win a “horse race” for the same response as number, creating congruency effects without any shared representations (Hurewitz et al. Reference Hurewitz, Gelman and Schnitzer2006). Consistent with this, my colleagues and I have demonstrated that number and time perception only correlate when individual differences in working memory are not controlled for (Odic et al. Reference Odic, Lisboa, Eisinger, Olivera, Maiche and Halberda2016). More recently, we have found that the effect of non-numeric dimensions such as contour length is entirely eliminated when Stroop-like response conflicts are alleviated (Picon & Odic, Reference Picon and Odicin preparation). Together, these results suggest that many demonstrated congruency effects could be response conflicts, and that any claim for dependence between number perception and non-numeric dimensions should first control for these factors.

Finally, the third possibility for the link between number and non-numeric dimensions – and one that is most consistent with the claims of Leibovich et al. – is that number may be (antecedently) represented on the same representational scale as other dimensions, either by being directly represented as, for example, area, or alternatively by being represented on a domain-general, unitless magnitude scale that simply codes for more versus less (Cantrell & Smith Reference Cantrell and Smith2013; Lourenco & Longo Reference Lourenco and Longo2010; Walsh Reference Walsh2003). Although Leibovich et al. suggest that statistical learning eventually separates number from these dimensions, their theory requires that – from birth until some later age – numerical information is represented in one of these two ways. But, as reviewed previously, evidence for shared representations must first control for the possibility of shared encoding or decision-making factors; given that the majority of existing work fails to do so, what is the evidence for shared/unified representations? Perhaps the most convincing case cited by Lebovich et al. is that of Tudusciuc and Nieder (Reference Tudusciuc and Nieder2007), who found neurons in the parietal cortex that respond to both number and length. But a closer inspection of their data reveals that these neurons often code in opposing ways: The same neuron may code for small numbers, but very long lengths, or vice versa, running contrary to the idea of a shared scale and instead consistent with a set of overlapping population coding neurons that play different roles for each dimension.

Another approach at demonstrating shared representations is to simultaneously measure number and the candidate shared dimensions, such as area, length, density, and time; if number shares the scale for these representations, any individual and developmental variability within number should be accounted for by differences in these other dimensions. Recently, my lab followed this logic through and tested 2- to 12-year-old children and adults on these five discrimination tasks. We found that number develops independently from area, length, density, and time, which in turn develop independently from it stretching back to age 2 (Odic Reference Odic2017; see also Odic et al. Reference Odic, Libertus, Feigenson and Halberda2013). Hence, unless the kind of proposed statistical learning proposed leads to complete differentiation by age 2, it is difficult to imagine how these results could be obtained without a significant independence between number and area, length, density, and time perception.

To conclude, Leibovich et al. make a bold claim – that congruency effects are illustrative of number's dependence on non-numeric dimensions – but their critique fails to account for the possibility that these effects stem from shared encoding or decision-making components, not shared representations. Future work exploring number's dependence should carefully disentangle the contributions of other dimensions to encoding and decision making, as these levels are not constitutive of the independent representations of number.

References

Anobile, G., Cicchini, G. M. & Burr, D. C. (2014) Separate mechanisms for perception of numerosity and density. Psychological Science 25(1):265–70. doi: 10.1177/0956797613501520.Google Scholar
Burr, D. & Ross, J. (2008) A visual sense of number. Current Biology 18(6):425–28. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2008.02.052.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cantrell, L. & Smith, L. B. (2013) Open questions and a proposal: A critical review of the evidence on infant numerical abilities. Cognition 128(3):331–52. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2013.04.008.Google Scholar
Dakin, S. C., Tibber, M. S., Greenwood, J. A., Kingdom, F. A. A. & Morgan, M. J. (2011) A common visual metric for approximate number and density. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 108(49):19552–57. doi: 10.1073/Pnas.1113195108.Google Scholar
Hurewitz, F., Gelman, R. & Schnitzer, B. (2006) Sometimes area counts more than number. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 103(51):19599–604. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0609485103.Google Scholar
Lourenco, S. F. & Longo, M. R. (2010) General magnitude representation in human infants. Psychological Science 21:873–81.Google Scholar
Odic, D. (2017) Children's intuitive sense of number develops independently of their perception of area, density, length, and time. Developmental Science. 2017:e12533. doi: 10.1111/desc.12533 Google Scholar
Odic, D., Libertus, M. E., Feigenson, L. & Halberda, J. (2013) Developmental change in the acuity of approximate number and area representations. Developmental Psychology 49(6):1103–12.Google Scholar
Odic, D., Lisboa, J. V., Eisinger, R., Olivera, M. G., Maiche, A. & Halberda, J. (2016) Approximate number and approximate time discrimination each correlate with school math abilities in young children. Acta Psychologica 163:1726.Google Scholar
Picon, E. & Odic, D. (in preparation) Visual illusions reveal the primitives of number perception.Google Scholar
Tudusciuc, O. & Nieder, A. (2007) Neuronal population coding of continuous and discrete quantity in the primate posterior parietal cortex. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 104(36):14513–18. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0705495104.Google Scholar
Van Opstal, F. & Verguts, T. (2013) Is there a generalized magnitude system in the brain? Behavioral, neuroimaging, and computational evidence. Frontiers in Psychology 4:435.Google Scholar
Vuilleumier, P., Armony, J. L., Driver, J. & Dolan, R. J. (2003) Distinct spatial frequency sensitivities for processing faces and emotional expressions. Nature Neuroscience 6(6):624–31. doi: 10.1038/nn1057.Google Scholar
Walsh, V. (2003) A theory of magnitude: Common cortical metrics of time, space and quantity. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 7(11):483–88. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2003.09.002.Google Scholar