1 Introduction
A subgroup H of a group G is called verbally closed [Reference Myasnikov and Roman’kov10] ( see also [Reference Roman’kov12, Reference Roman’kov and Khisamiev13, Reference Mazhuga7, Reference Klyachko and Mazhuga4, Reference Klyachko, Mazhuga and Miroshnichenko5, Reference Mazhuga8, Reference Bogopolski2, Reference Bogopolski3, Reference Mazhuga9, Reference Roman’kov and Timoshenko14]) if any equation of the form
where $w(x,y,\dots )$ is an element of the free group $F(x,y,\dots )$ and $h\in H$ , having a solution in G has a solution in H. If each finite system of equations with coefficient from $H:$
where $w_i\in H*F(x,y,\dots )$ (and $*$ stands for the free product), having a solution in G has a solution in H, then H is called algebraically closed in G.
Algebraic closedness is a stronger property than verbal closedness, but these properties turn out to be equivalent in many cases. A group H is called strongly verbally closed [Reference Mazhuga8] if it is algebraically closed in any group containing H as a verbally closed subgroup. Thus, the verbal closedness is a subgroup property, while the strong verbal closedness is an abstract group property. The class of strongly verbally closed groups is fairly wide; see the papers mentioned above. For instance, in [Reference Mazhuga8], it was proved that:
the fundamental group of any connected surface, possibly except for the Klein bottle, is strongly verbally closed.
The intriguing unique possible exception arose as follows:
-
• almost all surface groups are similar to free groups in a sense; for such groups, an “industrial” method works; this method goes back to the very first paper [Reference Myasnikov and Roman’kov10] on this subject and is based on the use of the Lie words [Reference Lee6] or their analogues;
-
• the remaining several groups are either
-
– abelian and, hence, strongly verbally closed (by a very simple reason) [Reference Mazhuga8],
-
– or this exceptional Klein bottle group $K=\langle a,b|a^b=a^{-1}\rangle$ , which is neither free-like nor abelian.
-
We obtain a natural addition to Mazhuga’s theorem:
the fundamental group of the Klein bottle is not strongly verbally closed.
A similar situation appeared some time ago. A general theorem with a unique possible exception was proved in [Reference Klyachko and Mazhuga4]:
all non-dihedral virtually free groups containing no non-identity finite normal subgroups are strongly verbally closed
(and the condition of absence of finite normal subgroups cannot be removed); later, it turned out (see [Reference Klyachko, Mazhuga and Miroshnichenko5]) that
the infinite dihedral group is strongly verbally closed too,
and this humble result was more difficult than the above-mentioned general theorem obtained in [Reference Klyachko and Mazhuga4] by the “industrial” method. Generally, if the reader takes their favorite nonabelian group, far from free (e.g., a finite group), then it would likely be difficult to decide whether this group is strongly verbally closed. Proving strong verbal closedness is not easy, nor is disproving this property (actually, it is not too easy to give an example of a group not being strongly verbally closed [Reference Klyachko and Mazhuga4]).
The Klein bottle group $K= \langle a,b|a^b=a^{-1}\rangle $ and the infinite dihedral group $D_\infty = \langle a,b|a^b=a^{-1},\ b^2=1\rangle $ are similar, of course. We use this similarity, apply the result of [Reference Klyachko, Mazhuga and Miroshnichenko5], and conclude that the Klein bottle group, though not strongly verbally closed, has a very similar property.
If a group H is equationally Noetherian (i.e., any system of equations over H with finitely many unknowns is equivalent to its finite subsystem), then the algebraic closedness is equivalent to the “local retractness” [Reference Klyachko, Mazhuga and Miroshnichenko5]:
an equationally Noetherian subgroup H of a group G is algebraically closed in G if and only if H is a retract (i.e., the image of an endomorphism $\rho $ such that $\rho {\circ }\rho =\rho $ ) of each finitely generated over H subgroup of G (i.e., a subgroup of the form $\left \langle H\cup X\right \rangle $ , where $X\subseteq G$ is a finite set).
All surface groups are linear [Reference Newman11], and all linear groups are equationally Noetherian [Reference Baumslag, Myasnikov and Remeslennikov1]. Thus, our main (and sole) result can be stated as follows.
Theorem The fundamental group K of the Klein bottle (unlike all other surface groups) embeds into a finitely generated group G as a verbally closed subgroup that is not a retract of G. However, any such G has an index-two subgroup containing K as its retract.
In the next section, we give an example proving the first assertion of the theorem (i.e., that K is not strongly verbally closed). Section 2 contains auxiliary lemmata. In the last section, we prove the second assertion of the theorem.
The author expresses his deep gratitude to Veronika Miroshnichenko; we have spent a long time trying together to solve this problem that seemed to be hard. I also thank Andrey Mazhuga for reading a draft of this text.
Our notation is fairly standard. Note only that, if x and y are elements of a group, then $x^y$ denotes $y^{-1}xy$ , The commutator $[x,y]$ is $x^{-1}y^{-1}xy$ . If X is a subset of a group, then $\left \langle X\right \rangle $ , $\left \langle \!\left \langle X\right \rangle \!\right \rangle $ , and $C_H(X)$ stand for the subgroup generated by X, the normal closure of X, and the centraliser of X in H (where H is a subgroup). The symbol $\left \langle x\right \rangle _k$ denotes the cyclic group of order k generated by x. The free group with a basis $x_1,\dots ,x_n$ is denoted as $F(x_1,\dots ,x_n)$ .
2 An Example
Let $V_4=\{1,d_1,d_2,d_3\}$ be the Klein four-group (i.e., the noncyclic group of order four). Consider the semidirect product
where the action is $ a_i^b=a_i^{-1},\ a_i^{d_i}=a_i,\ a_i^{d_j}=a_i^{-1} \mbox { for all }i\ne j. $
Proposition The subgroup $K=\left \langle a,b\right \rangle \subset G$ , where $a=a_1a_2a_3$ , (isomorphic to the Klein bottle group) is verbally closed in G, but not a retract.
Proof The subgroup K is not a retract, because a hypothetical retraction $G\to K$ should map finite-order elements $d_i$ to 1 (as K is torsion-free); then, the relation $a_i^{d_j}=a_i^{-1}$ would show that the images of $a_i$ are also of finite order and, hence, are 1 too; therefore, the image of $a=a_1a_2a_3\in K$ is also 1 that contradicts the fixedness of elements of K under the retraction.
It remains to show that K is verbally closed in G, i.e., any equation of the form
where $h\in K$ and $w(x,y,\dots )$ is an element of the free group $F(x,y,\dots )$ , solvable in G, is solvable in K. It is known that, by a change of variables, any such equation can be transformed into the form
where $h\in K$ and $u(x,y,\dots )$ lies in the commutator subgroup of the free group $F(x,y,\dots )$ . Suppose that equation (2.1) has a solution $(\tilde {x}, \tilde {y},\dots )$ in G. Since there is no principal difference between $d_i$ , we can assume that
where ${\varepsilon },l,k_i\in {\mathbb Z}$ . We have a homomorphism the first coordinate:
where $f(a_1)=a'$ , $f(a_2)=f(a_3)=f(d_1)=1$ , $f(b)=f(d_2)=f(d_3)=b'$ , and the natural homomorphism degree:
where $\deg (a_i)=\deg (d_i)=0$ , $\deg (b)=1$ , Applying these homomorphisms to the given equality $\tilde {x}^mu(\tilde {x},\tilde {y},\dots )=h$ , we obtain
and
Now, consider the elements $\hat {x},\hat {y},\dots \in K$ obtained from $\tilde {x},\tilde {y},\dots \in G$ by the changes
which preserve the first coordinate of any element. For instance, the element $\tilde {x}$ , given by expression (2.2), turns into
We claim that the tuple $(\hat {x},\hat {y},\dots )$ is a solution to equation (2.1) in K. Indeed,
-
• the first coordinates of $\hat {x}^mu(\hat {x},\hat {y},\dots )$ and h are the same:
$$ \begin{align*}f\big(\hat{x}^mu(\hat{x},\hat{y},\dots)\big) = f(\hat{x})^mu\big(f(\hat{x}),f(\hat{y}),\dots\big) {\mathrel{\mathop=\limits^{\scriptscriptstyle(4)}}} f(\tilde{x})^mu\big(f(\tilde{x}),f(\tilde{y}),\dots\big) {\mathrel{\mathop=\limits^{\scriptscriptstyle(3)}}} f(h) \end{align*} $$(where (2.4) and (2.3) imply the corresponding equalities); -
• and the degrees of $\hat {x}^mu(\hat {x},\hat {y},\dots )$ and h are the same:
$$ \begin{align*}\deg\bigl(\hat{x}^mu(\hat{x},\hat{y},\dots)\bigr)= m\cdot\deg(\hat{x}) {\mathrel{\mathop=\limits^{\scriptscriptstyle(5)}}} ml {\mathrel{\mathop=\limits^{\scriptscriptstyle(2)}}} m\cdot\deg(\tilde{x}) {\mathrel{\mathop=\limits^{\scriptscriptstyle(3)}}} \deg(h), \end{align*} $$
It remains to note that an element of $K\subset G$ is uniquely determined by its first coordinate and degree. Thus, $\hat {x}^mu(\hat {x},\hat {y},\dots )=h$ , we have found a solution to equation (2.1) in K, and this completes the proof.▪
3 Two Lemmata on Quotient Groups
Lawfication Lemma [13, Lemma 1.1] If $V(G)$ is a verbal subgroup of a group G, and H is a verbally closed subgroup of G, then $H\cap V(G)=V(H)$ (i.e., the verbal subgroup of H corresponding to the same variety), and the image $H/V(H)\subseteq G/V(G)$ of H under the natural homomorphism $G\to G/V(G)$ is verbally closed in $G/V(G)$ .
Dihedral-quotient Lemma If the Klein bottle group $K=\langle a,b | a^b=a^{-1}\rangle$ is a verbally closed subgroup of a group G, then
-
(i) $\left \langle {\!\left \langle {b^2}\right \rangle \!}\right \rangle \cap K=\left \langle b^2\right \rangle $ , where $\left \langle {\!\left \langle {b^2}\right \rangle \!}\right \rangle $ is the normal closure of $b^2$ in G;
-
(ii) the subgroup $D_\infty =K/\left \langle b^2\right \rangle \subseteq G/\left \langle {\!\left \langle {b^2}\right \rangle \!}\right \rangle $ is verbally closed in $G/\left \langle {\!\left \langle {b^2}\right \rangle \!}\right \rangle $ .
Proof We can assume that G satisfies the law $[x^2,y^2]=1$ (because this law holds in K, and, therefore, the lawfication lemma allows us to replace G with its quotient group by the corresponding verbal subgroup).
For groups with such a law, as well as for all metabelian groups, assertion (i) is a general fact:
If A is a normal abelian subgroup of a group G, and the quotient group $G/A$ is also abelian, then the intersection $C_A(X)$ of A and the centraliser of any subset $X\subseteq G$ is normal in G.
Indeed, $\bigl (C_A(X)\bigr )^g=C_A(X^g)\supseteq C_A(XA)=C_A(X)$ .
To obtain assertion (i), we put $A=\left \langle \{g^2\;|\;g\in G\}\right \rangle $ and $X=K$ ; we even get more than (i):
Let us prove (ii) now. Suppose that an equation
is solvable in $G/\left \langle {\!\left \langle {b^2}\right \rangle \!}\right \rangle $ . We have to show that this equation is solvable in $D_\infty =K/\left \langle b^2\right \rangle \subseteq G/\left \langle {\!\left \langle {b^2}\right \rangle \!}\right \rangle $ .
Case 1: $h=1$ . In this case, equation (3.1) has the trivial solution $(1,1,\dots )$ in $D_\infty $ .
Case 2: $h=b$ . In this case, the exponent sum of one of unknowns (say, x) in the word w has to be odd, because otherwise the solvability of equation (3.1) in $G/\left \langle {\!\left \langle {b^2}\right \rangle \!}\right \rangle $ would imply a decomposition of b into a product of squares in G, which contradicts the verbal closedness of K (because b is not a product of squares in K, even modulo $\left \langle a\right \rangle $ ). An equation with odd exponent sum of x and the right-hand side b has in $D_\infty $ an obvious solution: $x=b,\ y=1,\ z=1,\dots $ .
Case 3: $h=ba^k$ . This case is the same as the preceding one, because the dihedral group has an automorphism mapping $ba^k$ to b.
Case 4: (the last case modulo $\left \langle b^2\right \rangle $ ): $h=a^k$ , where $k\ne 0$ . Suppose that $\bigl (\tilde {x}\left \langle {\!\left \langle {b^2}\right \rangle \!}\right \rangle\! ,\;\tilde {y}\left \langle {\!\left \langle {b^2}\right \rangle \!}\right \rangle\! ,\dots \bigr )$ is a solution to equation (3.1) in $G/\left \langle {\!\left \langle {b^2}\right \rangle \!}\right \rangle $ . Then the equation
has a solution $(\tilde {t}=b,\;\tilde {x},\;\tilde {y},\dots )$ in G, because $\left \langle {\!\left \langle {b^2}\right \rangle \!}\right \rangle $ commutes with K as noted above. The verbal closedness of K in G implies that this equation has a solution in K, i.e.,
This means that:
-
• $\hat {t}\in b\left \langle a,b^2\right \rangle $ , because all other elements of K commute with squares; we can even assume that $\hat {t}=b$ , since a and $b^2$ commute with all squares and do not affect commutator (3.2);
-
• $\bigl (w(\hat {x},\hat {y},\dots )\bigr )^2\in \left \langle b^2\right \rangle \cup \left \langle a^2,b^4\right \rangle $ , because only these elements are squares in K;
-
• $\bigl (w(\hat {x},\hat {y},\dots )\bigr )^2\in a^{2k}\left \langle b^4\right \rangle $ , because, only for such elements of $\left \langle b^2\right \rangle \cup \left \langle a^2,b^4\right \rangle $ , the commutator with $\hat {t}=b$ gives $a^{4k}$ ;
-
• $w(\hat {x},\hat {y},\dots )\in a^k\left \langle b^2\right \rangle $ , because each element of the coset $a^{2k}\left \langle b^4\right \rangle $ has a unique square root in K.
We have found a solution $(\hat {x}\left \langle b^2\right \rangle\! ,\hat {y}\left \langle b^2\right \rangle\! ,\dots )$ to equation (3.1) in $D_\infty =K/\left \langle b^2\right \rangle $ ; this completes the proof.▪
4 Proof of the Second Assertion of the Theorem
Suppose that the fundamental group K of the Klein bottle is a verbally closed subgroup of a finitely generated group G. We have to construct a retraction onto K from an index-at-most-two subgroup of G containing K.
The group G has two normal subgroups: $ N_1=G'$ , the commutator subgroup, and $ N_2=\left \langle {\!\left \langle {b^2}\right \rangle \!}\right \rangle $ , the normal closure of $b^2$ . Taking the quotients transforms K into
(by the Lawfication and Dihedral-quotient Lemmata); these images of K in $G/N_i$ remain verbally closed in $G/N_i$ (by the same lemmata). Therefore, $K/K'$ and $K/\left \langle b^2\right \rangle $ are retracts of $G/N_i$ , because all abelian groups [Reference Mazhuga8] and the infinite dihedral group [Reference Klyachko, Mazhuga and Miroshnichenko5] are strongly verbally closed.
Thus, we obtain the epimorphisms
and
such that $\deg (b)=1$ , $f(b)=b\left \langle b^2\right \rangle $ , $f(a)=a\left \langle b^2\right \rangle $ .
Combining these two “pseudo-retractions”, we construct the homomorphism
The restriction $\varphi $ of $\Phi $ to K is injective, and the image of this restriction is so-called fibered product:
an index-two subgroup of ${\mathbb Z}\times D_\infty $ . Therefore, the subgroup $\Phi ^{-1}(\Phi (K))\subseteq G$ has index at most two in G and admits a retraction onto K: