Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-kw2vx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-11T04:27:08.607Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Opportunities for emotion and mental health research in the resource-rationality framework

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 March 2020

Evan M. Russek
Affiliation:
Max Planck UCL Centre for Computational Psychiatry and Ageing Research, LondonWC1B 5EH, UK. e.russek@ucl.ac.ukr.moran@ucl.ac.ukd.mcnamee@ucl.ac.ukyunzhe.liu.16@ucl.ac.uka.reiter@ucl.ac.ukr.dolan@ucl.ac.ukq.huys@ucl.ac.uk The Wellcome Trust Centre for Neuroimaging, London, WC1N 3AR, UK
Rani Moran
Affiliation:
Max Planck UCL Centre for Computational Psychiatry and Ageing Research, LondonWC1B 5EH, UK. e.russek@ucl.ac.ukr.moran@ucl.ac.ukd.mcnamee@ucl.ac.ukyunzhe.liu.16@ucl.ac.uka.reiter@ucl.ac.ukr.dolan@ucl.ac.ukq.huys@ucl.ac.uk The Wellcome Trust Centre for Neuroimaging, London, WC1N 3AR, UK
Daniel McNamee
Affiliation:
Max Planck UCL Centre for Computational Psychiatry and Ageing Research, LondonWC1B 5EH, UK. e.russek@ucl.ac.ukr.moran@ucl.ac.ukd.mcnamee@ucl.ac.ukyunzhe.liu.16@ucl.ac.uka.reiter@ucl.ac.ukr.dolan@ucl.ac.ukq.huys@ucl.ac.uk The Wellcome Trust Centre for Neuroimaging, London, WC1N 3AR, UK
Andrea Reiter
Affiliation:
Max Planck UCL Centre for Computational Psychiatry and Ageing Research, LondonWC1B 5EH, UK. e.russek@ucl.ac.ukr.moran@ucl.ac.ukd.mcnamee@ucl.ac.ukyunzhe.liu.16@ucl.ac.uka.reiter@ucl.ac.ukr.dolan@ucl.ac.ukq.huys@ucl.ac.uk The Wellcome Trust Centre for Neuroimaging, London, WC1N 3AR, UK
Yunzhe Liu
Affiliation:
Max Planck UCL Centre for Computational Psychiatry and Ageing Research, LondonWC1B 5EH, UK. e.russek@ucl.ac.ukr.moran@ucl.ac.ukd.mcnamee@ucl.ac.ukyunzhe.liu.16@ucl.ac.uka.reiter@ucl.ac.ukr.dolan@ucl.ac.ukq.huys@ucl.ac.uk The Wellcome Trust Centre for Neuroimaging, London, WC1N 3AR, UK
Raymond J. Dolan
Affiliation:
Max Planck UCL Centre for Computational Psychiatry and Ageing Research, LondonWC1B 5EH, UK. e.russek@ucl.ac.ukr.moran@ucl.ac.ukd.mcnamee@ucl.ac.ukyunzhe.liu.16@ucl.ac.uka.reiter@ucl.ac.ukr.dolan@ucl.ac.ukq.huys@ucl.ac.uk The Wellcome Trust Centre for Neuroimaging, London, WC1N 3AR, UK
Quentin J.M. Huys
Affiliation:
Max Planck UCL Centre for Computational Psychiatry and Ageing Research, LondonWC1B 5EH, UK. e.russek@ucl.ac.ukr.moran@ucl.ac.ukd.mcnamee@ucl.ac.ukyunzhe.liu.16@ucl.ac.uka.reiter@ucl.ac.ukr.dolan@ucl.ac.ukq.huys@ucl.ac.uk Division of Psychiatry, University College London, London, W1T 7NF, UK Camden and Islington NHS Foundation Trust,London, NW1 0PEUnited Kingdom

Abstract

We discuss opportunities in applying the resource-rationality framework toward answering questions in emotion and mental health research. These opportunities rely on characterization of individual differences in cognitive strategies; an endeavor that may be at odds with the normative approach outlined in the target article. We consider ways individual differences might enter the framework and the translational opportunities offered by each.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2020

The resource-rationality framework presented by Lieder and Griffiths has the potential to open up new computational approaches to emotion, including in the setting of mental illness. However, pitfalls can arise from a strong emphasis on normative modeling when this is at the expense of approaches that allow for measurement of individual differences. We consider the latter important in many translation efforts.

Minds face extremely complex decision-making tasks that far outstrip available computational resources. An individual must decide how to optimally apportion cognitive resources, such as attention, what memories to prioritize, what actions to evaluate and in what order, what future situations to simulate, whether to expend or save energy resources, and so on. The computational burdens imposed by resource-rationality, to choose optimal internal actions, are huge and often mandate the use of fast, automatic, and approximate solutions.

Emotions and moods have long been characterized as states involving coordinated biases in all these domains (e.g. Scherer Reference Scherer2009), suggesting that they could function as psychological and physiological mechanisms by which humans implement approximate resource-rational computations (Huys & Renz Reference Huys and Renz2017). For example, different emotions prioritize distinct action sets for mental evaluation (Frijda et al. Reference Frijda, Kuipers and ter Schure1989); an effect which can be interpreted as implementing a solution to the meta-cognitive problem of the order in which a large space of actions should be evaluated. Moods involve longer-lasting biases toward particular emotions, and hence result in more persistent sets of cognitive choices to such internal demands. For example, low mood states are characterized by preferentially choosing to attend to negative stimuli, a prioritization of negative memories, a preferential evaluation of avoidance actions and not expending energy.

If it is true that moods are coherent, systematically covarying sets of internal cognitive choices that approximately address resource allocation problems, the question arises why a particular set of cognitive choices that define a mood state tend to co-occur. Furthermore, how these internal policies change and adapt becomes fundamental to understanding them. The framework of resource-rationality seems ideally placed in answering these questions. By defining what state features lead a resource rational agent to make the cognitive selections defined by a given mood, we can understand why particular cognitive actions become associated with one another in distinct meta-action sets, as well as what pieces of environmental information trigger mood shifts, and hence why the range of internal actions becomes partitioned into a particular set of emotions.

Cognitive action selections are likely aberrant in many mental illnesses. Most obviously, if emotions are indeed cognitive action policies, this suggests that mood disorders can arise from maladaptive solutions to internal resource allocation problems. Indeed, patients with depression are known to suffer from characteristic biases in their allocation of attention, memory recall, action, and energy expenditure (Elliott et al. Reference Elliott, Zahn, Deakin and Anderson2011; Mathews & MacLeod Reference Mathews and MacLeod2005; Whitton et al. Reference Whitton, Treadway and Pizzagalli2015). Similarly, a tendency to catastrophize might relate to resource-rational arguments for biasing mental simulation toward extreme events (Lieder et al. Reference Lieder, Griffiths and Hsu2018). However, this counter-intuitively links normative functions to maladaptive psychopathology, and begs the question about individual variability: not everybody should or does normatively suffer from mental illness.

Accommodating individual differences into the resource rationality framework, as it currently stands, is hindered by an emphasis on a modeling approach in which algorithmic hypothesis are developed by purely resource-rational considerations, and experiments that test group-level predictions of those hypothesis. This approach is at odds with characterizing individual differences. Indeed, Lieder and Griffiths explicitly argue against the alternative approach, common in computational cognitive neuroscience, of fitting components of models to human behavior. This latter approach could provide parametric accounts of individual differences in terms of component processes.

Nevertheless, even the current framework provides for some inter-individual variability. First, though viewed as a constant in the target article, individuals certainly differ in their capacity for, and hence cost of, cognitive operations. For one, some costs will be sensitive to representation and hence depend on individual experience. Individual cost functions might be measured through behavioral tasks while assuming resource-rational optimality with respect to that individual cost function. Such cost estimates could possibly assist in the development of tailored cognitive interventions. As a concrete example, multiple lines of evidence link the representation of time-based costs to an operation of specific catecholaminergic neuromodulators (Constantino et al. Reference Constantino, Dalrymple, Gilbert, Varanese, Di Rocco and Daw2017; Hauser et al. Reference Hauser, Moutoussis, Purg, Dayan and Dolan2018). This implies that dysregulated cognitive processing caused by irregular time-based costing could be amenable to pharmacological modulation.

Second, the tradeoff between cost and utility must be optimized with respect to an individual's environment. Similar to how different moods might reflect adaptive cognitive actions for different environmental states, inter-individual differences in cognitive heuristics may reflect adaptation to different environments. Mental illness may reflect cognitive strategies that are adaptive in certain environments. Though difficult, it is tantalizing to consider the possibility of using the resource rationality framework to characterize the environments that an individual's cognitive strategy might be optimized for.

Such considerations can also motivate research into the meta-learning processes by which individuals arrive at resource-optimal cognitive strategies. Aspects of cognitive behavioral therapy aimed at “cognitive restructuring” attempt to change an individual's cognitive heuristics so as to make them more adaptive (Beck Reference Beck1979). For example, in cognitive therapy patients are asked to identify a recent emotion triggering situation (e.g. “I wasn't invited to a party”), record the beliefs they had in that situation (e.g. “everyone hates me”), and then critically evaluate this belief (e.g. “how would someone else think about this?)”. Through the lens of resource-rational analysis, such approaches can be conceptualized as individuals learning to perform cognitive actions that lead to more adaptive inference regarding their current situations. More recent metacognitive treatments (Wells Reference Wells2011) could even be viewed as altering the very cost function by which internal actions are evaluated.

In conclusion, the notion of resource rationality raises tantalizing possibilities in the realm of mental illness, and we encourage an expanded methodological approach that embraces individual differences.

References

Beck, A. T. (1979) Cognitive therapy of depression. Guilford Press.Google Scholar
Constantino, S. M., Dalrymple, J., Gilbert, R. W., Varanese, S., Di Rocco, A. & Daw, N. D. (2017) A neural mechanism for the opportunity cost of time. bioRxiv 173443. Available at: http://doi.org/10.1101/173443.Google Scholar
Elliott, R., Zahn, R., Deakin, J. F. W. & Anderson, I. M. (2011) Affective cognition and its disruption in mood disorders. Neuropsychopharmacology 36(1):153–82. Available at: http://doi.org/10.1038/npp.2010.77.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Frijda, N. H., Kuipers, P. & ter Schure, E. (1989) Relations among emotion, appraisal, and emotional action readiness. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 57(2):212–28. Available at: http://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.57.2.212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hauser, T. U., Moutoussis, M., Purg, N., Dayan, P. & Dolan, R. J. (2018) Beta-blocker propranolol modulates decision urgency during sequential information gathering. Journal of Neuroscience 38(32):7170–78. Available at: http://doi.org/10.1523/JNEUROSCI.0192-18.2018.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Huys, Q. J. M. & Renz, D. (2017) A formal valuation framework for emotions and their control. Biological Psychiatry 82(6):413–20. Available at: http://doi.org/10.1016/j.biopsych.2017.07.003.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lieder, F., Griffiths, T. L. & Hsu, M. (2018b) Overrepresentation of extreme events in decision making reflects rational use of cognitive resources. Psychological Review 125(1):132. doi:10.1037/rev0000074.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mathews, A. & MacLeod, C. (2005) Cognitive vulnerability to emotional disorders. Annual Review of Clinical Psychology 1(1):167–95. Available at: http://doi.org/10.1146/annurev.clinpsy.1.102803.143916.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Scherer, K. R. (2009) The dynamic architecture of emotion: Evidence for the component process model. Cognition & Emotion 23(7):1307–51. Available at: http://doi.org/10.1080/02699930902928969.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wells, A. (2011) Metacognitive therapy for anxiety and depression. Guilford Press.Google Scholar
Whitton, A. E., Treadway, M. T. & Pizzagalli, D. A. (2015) Reward processing dysfunction in major depression, bipolar disorder and schizophrenia. Current Opinion in Psychiatry 28(1):712. Available at: http://doi.org/10.1097/YCO.0000000000000122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar