Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-f46jp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T18:06:03.328Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Let us be careful with the evidence on mentalizing, cognitive biases, and religious beliefs

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 March 2016

Marjaana Lindeman
Affiliation:
Institute of Behavioural Sciences, University of Helsinki, FI-00014 University of Helsinki, Finland.marjaana.lindeman@helsinki.fiannika.svedholm@helsinki.fihttp://blogs.helsinki.fi/everyday-thinking/
Annika M. Svedholm-Häkkinen
Affiliation:
Institute of Behavioural Sciences, University of Helsinki, FI-00014 University of Helsinki, Finland.marjaana.lindeman@helsinki.fiannika.svedholm@helsinki.fihttp://blogs.helsinki.fi/everyday-thinking/

Abstract

Norenzayan et al.’s theoretical synthesis is highly plausible and commendable. However, the empirical evidence for the arguments on mentalizing, cognitive biases, and religious belief is currently not as strong as the writers suggest. Although certainly abundant and compelling, this evidence is indirect, contradictory, and weak and must be acknowledged as such. More direct studies are needed to support the theory.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2016 

Norenzayan et al. present an admirable and highly plausible theory on the development and spreading of prosocial religions. Their approach represents a significant advance in the psychological study of religion, integrating many central ideas into a unified theory and generating a host of testable hypotheses. We specifically applaud the theory for explicating how the effects of cultural factors and cognitive factors intertwine in bringing about specific types of religions.

That said, most of the theory's central arguments about the relationship between mentalizing, cognitive biases, and religion remain to be empirically tested and should be stated with less certainty than is currently the case. Although the evidence that the authors cite is abundant and compelling, it is indirect and must be acknowledged as such. Aside from the difficulty of proving evolutionary hypotheses, in order to properly test the theory, it needs to be complemented by direct evidence of a link between mentalizing, the cognitive biases, and religious beliefs.

The authors write that the “cognitive science of religion has begun to show that religious beliefs are rooted in a suite of core cognitive faculties” (sect. 2.1, para. 1), and that individual differences in mentalizing, teleological thinking, and dualism partly explain religious and other paranormal beliefs. They cite several papers and books in support of these arguments. Closer analysis of the references, however, reveals that rather than offering empirical evidence, they provide only theoretical or indirect information about the relationship under scrutiny. For example, although Barrett (Reference Barrett2004), Kirkpatrick (Reference Kirkpatrick1999), Lawson and McCauley (Reference Lawson and McCauley1993), Guthrie (Reference Guthrie1993), and Boyer (Reference Boyer2001) provide conceptual backgrounds for the authors’ theoretical position, they are mainly hypothetical discussions of the types of relationships that we might expect to find. As well, many of the sources present background information on the main concepts but do not directly deal with the associations between mentalizing, cognitive biases, and religious beliefs, and some do not mention religion at all (Frith & Frith Reference Frith and Frith2003). Other references present evidence that is empirical but indirect. For example, Waytz et al. (Reference Waytz, Gray, Epley and Wegner2010), Norenzayan and Shariff (Reference Norenzayan and Shariff2008), and Bloom (Reference Bloom2012) deal with the question of whether religion has effects on morality or on prosocial behavior; however, they do not address the cognitive mechanism through which these associations might be realized. Although we cannot criticize the citing of any of these references, the length of the reference list may give readers an incorrect impression that the relationships between mentalizing, cognitive biases, and religiosity are well established.

Further, there are several studies whose results are not in line with the argument that individual differences in mentalizing and cognitive biases partly explain belief in God and in paranormal events, but discussion of these studies is missing. For example, promiscuous teleology is not necessarily related to God beliefs (Lombrozo et al. Reference Lombrozo, Kelemen and Zaitchik2007). Strong mentalizers do not experience supernatural agency more strongly (Barnes & Gibson Reference Barnes and Gibson2013), and do not attribute their life events to God, any more often than others (Banerjee & Bloom Reference Banerjee and Bloom2014). Similarly, the evidence for the argument that reduced mentalizing abilities, as found in autistic spectrum disorders, predict reduced belief in God, and that schizotypal tendencies are associated with “hyperreligiosity,” is not as clear as Norenzayan et al. suggest. Individuals with autism spectrum disorder may consider religion to be important (Schaap-Jonker et al. Reference Schaap-Jonker, Sizoo, van Schothorst-van Roekel and Corveleyn2013), and schizotypy is not necessarily linked with any kind of religiosity (Diduca & Joseph Reference Diduca and Joseph1997; Maltby et al. Reference Maltby, Garner, Alan Lewis and Day2000). Linking religious beliefs with schizotypy and contrasting them with autistic traits and nonbelief is therefore an oversimplification.

The few existing papers that have thus far supported a positive relationship between mentalizing, cognitive biases, and religiosity (and that are cited) are problematic for a number of reasons. Firstly, the relationships have tended to be weak. For example, when mentalizing, autistic traits or promiscuous teleology have predicted religiosity (or vice versa), the beta coefficients have ranged from 0.07–0.18 (Kelemen et al. Reference Kelemen, Rottman and Seston2013; Norenzayan et al. Reference Norenzayan, Gervais and Trzesniewski2012; Willard & Norenzayan Reference Willard and Norenzayan2013; see also Lindeman et al. Reference Lindeman, Svedholm-Häkkinen and Lipsanen2015), implying that the ability of these predictors to explain variance in religiosity has ranged from trivial to small.

Secondly, mentalizing is a large-scale, multidimensional construct. It can refer to the capacity to understand that other people have minds different from one's own (the theory of mind proper); the capacity to understand what others feel or think; the ability to experience and share the emotions of others; the ability to interpret communicative signs, detect intentionality, and understand social outcomes; the mirror neuron system; and the ability to think about thinking (i.e., metacognition). It can pertain to attending, perceiving, recognizing, describing, interpreting, inferring, imagining, simulating, remembering, reflecting, and anticipating, making it a slippery concept, potentially extending beyond manageable bounds (Allen Reference Allen, Allen and Fonagy2006). The available instruments do not capture this variance in mentalizing among healthy adults. In most studies on supernatural beliefs, mentalizing has been operationalized either with the Empathy Quotient (Baron-Cohen & Wheelwright Reference Baron-Cohen and Wheelwright2004), or with the Eyes test (Baron Cohen et al. Reference Baron-Cohen, Wheelwright, Hill, Raste and Plumb2001), which according to recent studies may not tap mentalistic abilities (Valla et al. Reference Valla, Ganzel, Yoder, Chen, Lyman, Sidari and Wong2010). However, comprehensive and valid methods to assess mentalizing among healthy adults are not easily available. Hence, there is a pressing need for the field to develop better methods for studying how mentalizing and various biases are related to religiosity today.

In sum, we congratulate Norenzayan et al. for the much-needed theoretical synthesis, but we caution against relying too strongly on evidence that, at least for part of the theory, is currently scarce and contradictory. At present, the only thing that can be said is that there “may be” a relationship between mentalizing, certain cognitive biases, and religiosity. Evidence that would warrant using the wording “is” or even “probably is” does not yet exist.

ACKNOWLEDGMENT

This work was supported by the Research Funds of the Academy of Finland (No. 265518).

References

Allen, J. G. (2006) Mentalizing in practice. In: Handbook of mentalization-based treatment, ed. Allen, E. & Fonagy, P., pp. 330. Wiley.Google Scholar
Banerjee, K. & Bloom, P. (2014) Why did this happen to me? Religious believers' and non-believers' teleological reasoning about life events. Cognition 133:277303. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2014.06.017.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Barnes, K. & Gibson, N. J. (2013) Supernatural agency: Individual difference predictors and situational correlates. International Journal for the Psychology of Religion 23:4262. doi: 10.1080/10508619.2013.739066.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baron-Cohen, S. & Wheelwright, S. (2004) The empathy quotient: An investigation of adults with Asperger syndrome or high functioning autism, and normal sex differences. Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders 34:163–75. doi: 10.1023/B:JADD.0000022607.19833.00.Google Scholar
Baron-Cohen, S., Wheelwright, S., Hill, J., Raste, Y. & Plumb, I. (2001) The “Reading the Mind in the Eyes” test revised version: A study with normal adults, and adults with Asperger syndrome or high-functioning autism. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry 42:241–51. doi: 10.1111/1469-7610.00715.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Barrett, J. L. (2004) Why would anyone believe in God? AltaMira Press.Google Scholar
Bloom, P. (2012) Religion, morality, evolution. Annual Review of Psychology 63:179–99. doi: 10.1146/annurev-psych-120710-100334.Google Scholar
Boyer, P. (2001) Religion explained. The evolutionary origins of religious thought. Basic Books.Google Scholar
Diduca, D. & Joseph, S. (1997) Schizotypal traits and dimensions of religiosity. British Journal of Clinical Psychology 36:635–38. doi: 10.1111/j.2044-8260.1997.tb01270.x.Google Scholar
Frith, U. & Frith, C. D. (2003) Development and neurophysiology of mentalizing. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B: Biological Sciences 358:459–73. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2002.1218.Google Scholar
Guthrie, S. (1993) Faces in the clouds. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kelemen, D., Rottman, J. & Seston, R. (2013) Professional physical scientists display tenacious teleological tendencies: Purpose-based reasoning as a cognitive default. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 42:1074–83. doi: 10.1037/a0030399.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kirkpatrick, L. A. (1999) Toward an evolutionary psychology of religion and personality. Journal of Personality 67:921–52. doi: 10.1111/1467-6494.00078.Google Scholar
Lawson, E. T. & McCauley, R. N. (1993) Rethinking religion: Connecting cognition and culture. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lindeman, M., Svedholm-Häkkinen, A. M. & Lipsanen, J. (2015) Ontological confusions but not mentalizing abilities predict religious belief, paranormal belief, and belief in supernatural purpose. Cognition 134:6376. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2014.09.008.Google Scholar
Lombrozo, T., Kelemen, D. & Zaitchik, D. (2007) Inferring design: Evidence of a preference for teleological explanations in patients with Alzheimer's disease. Psychological Science 18:9991006. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9280.2007.02015.x.Google Scholar
Maltby, J., Garner, I., Alan Lewis, C. & Day, L. (2000) Religious orientation and schizotypal traits. Personality and Individual Differences 28:143–51. doi: 10.1016/S0191-8869(99)00090-2.Google Scholar
Norenzayan, A., Gervais, W. M. & Trzesniewski, K. H. (2012) Mentalizing deficits constrain belief in a personal God. PLOS ONE 7:e36880. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0036880.Google Scholar
Norenzayan, A. & Shariff, A. F. (2008) The origin and evolution of religious prosociality. Science 322:5862. Available at: http://dx.doi.org/10.1126/science.1158757.Google Scholar
Schaap-Jonker, H., Sizoo, B., van Schothorst-van Roekel, J. & Corveleyn, J. (2013) Autism spectrum disorders and the image of God as a core aspect of religiousness. International Journal for the Psychology of Religion 23:145–60. doi: 10.1080/10508619.2012.688005.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Valla, J. M., Ganzel, B. L., Yoder, K. J., Chen, G. M., Lyman, L. T., Sidari, A. P., Wong, S. K. (2010) More than maths and mindreading: Sex differences in empathizing/systemizing covariance. Autism Research 3:174–84. doi: 10.1002/aur.143.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Waytz, A., Gray, K., Epley, N. & Wegner, D. M. (2010) Causes and consequences of mind perception. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 14:383–88. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2010.05.006.Google Scholar
Willard, A. K. & Norenzayan, A. (2013) Cognitive biases explain religious belief, paranormal belief, and belief in life's purpose. Cognition 129:379–91. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2013.07.016.Google Scholar