1. Confirmation Measure Z
Crupi, Tentori, and Gonzalez (Reference Crupi, Tentori and Gonzalez2007) provide a very interesting set of theoretical and empirical arguments in favor of the following (piecewise) Bayesian measure of the degree to which evidence E confirms hypothesis H, relative to background knowledge K:Footnote 1

I will not go into their arguments in favor of Z here. Instead, I will present what I take to be a serious problem with Z. This will require a brief digression into the notion of independent evidence.
2. Independent Evidence Regarding a Hypothesis
Fitelson (Reference Fitelson2001) offers the following Bayesian account of what it means for two pieces of evidence E 1 and E 2 to be confirmationally independent, regarding hypothesis H, according to a confirmation measure 𝔠.
Independence. E 1 and E 2 are confirmationally independent regarding H, according to 𝔠 (i.e., E 1, E 2 are 𝔠-independent regarding H) if and only if both and
.Footnote 2
Intuitively, E 1 and E 2 are confirmationally independent regarding H, according to 𝔠, just in case the degree to which E 1 (E 2) confirms H (according to 𝔠) does not depend on whether E 2 (E 1) is already known.
As Fitelson shows, this notion can be applied in various useful confirmation-theoretic ways (e.g., to provide a Bayesian account of the value of varied/diverse evidence). I will not delve into Independence here. Rather, I will simply apply it to reveal that measure Z has a serious shortcoming when it comes to the handling of certain sorts of independent evidence.
3. A Problem for Measure Z
Sometimes, we have conflicting evidence regarding a hypothesis. That is to say, sometimes, the following property holds for a triple E 1, E 2, and H.
Conflict. E 1 and E 2 constitute conflicting evidence regarding H if and only if E 1 confirms H, while E 2 disconfirms H. Formally, E 1 and E 2 constitute conflicting evidence regarding H if and only if and
.
Intuitively, it should be possible for some triple E 1, E 2, and H to satisfy both Independence and Conflict. That is to say, intuitively, there sometimes exists independent, conflicting evidence regarding some hypotheses. More precisely, we have the following eminently plausible existence claim.
Existence. There exist some triples E 1, E 2, and H that satisfy both Independence and Conflict.
Indeed, Existence strikes me as so plausible as to require little justification. Having said that, it is worth giving a simple example that illustrates the intuitive plausibility of Existence.Footnote 3 Here, I borrow the following example, which belongs to a class of examples used by Fitelson (Reference Fitelson2001) to provide an intuitive illustration of Independence (with individual degrees of strength that can be tweaked via some simple parameters, which I have set here).
The Urn Example. An urn has been selected at random from a collection of urns. Each urn contains some balls. In some of the urns (the H-urns) the proportion of white balls to nonwhite balls is 1/3, and in all the other urns (the ∼H-urns) the proportion of white balls to nonwhite balls is 2/3. The proportion of H-urns is 1/2. Balls are to be drawn randomly from the selected urn, with replacement.
Let H be the hypothesis that the proportion of white balls in the urn is 1/3 (i.e., that the sampled urn is an H-urn). Let W i state that the ball drawn on the i th draw () is white. Intuitively, ∼W 1 and W 2 are confirmationally independent regarding H; that is, the triple 〈∼W 1, W 2, H〉 instantiates Independence.Footnote 4
Surprisingly, according to measure Z, Existence is false (a fortiori). That is, according to measure Z, it is conceptually impossible for any pair of evidence E 1, E 2 to be both independent regarding H and conflicting regarding H (for any hypothesis H).
Problem. According to measure Z, Existence is (analytically) false.
Proof. Suppose, for reductio, that there does exist some triple E 1, E 2, H that satisfies both Independence (according to measure Z) and Conflict. Then, we may reason as follows.

(1) | ![]() |
Assumption (Conflict) |
(2) | ![]() |
Assumption (Conflict) |
(3) | ![]() |
Assumption (Z-Independence) |
(4) | ![]() |
Assumption (Z-Independence) |
(5) | ![]() |
(1), (3), definition of Z |
(6) | ![]() |
(2), (4), definition of Z |
Now, let ,
, z = Pr(H), and
. Then, (5) and (6) can be rewritten as the following pair of algebraic equations.

(5) | ![]() |
(6) | ![]() |
Algebraically (assuming only that x, y, z, and u are real numbers), (5) and (6) entail that either (7) or (8)
. But, this contradicts our assumption that both (1)
and (2)
. QED
In closing, it is worth noting that it seems to be the piecewise nature of Z that causes Problem. For it can be shown that none of the non-piecewise-defined confirmation measures that have been discussed in the literature (see, e.g., Crupi et al. [Reference Crupi, Tentori and Gonzalez2007] and Crupi and Tentori [Reference Crupi and Tentori2014] for recent surveys) have this Problem (proof omitted). Finally, because Problem only rests on ordinal features, it will plague any measure that is ordinally equivalent to Z.Footnote 5