1. Introduction
A space-time is counted as inextendible if, intuitively, it is “as large as it can be.” It has been argued that inextendibility is a “reasonable physical condition to be imposed on models of the universe” (Geroch Reference Geroch, Carmeli, Fickler and Witten1970, 262) and that a space-time must be inextendible if it is “to be a serious candidate for describing actuality” (Earman Reference Earman1995, 32). Here, in a variety of ways, we register some skepticism with respect to such positions.
2. Preliminaries
We begin with a few preliminaries concerning the relevant background formalism of general relativity.Footnote 1 An n-dimensional, relativistic space-time (for ) is a pair of mathematical objects (M, gab), where M is a connected n-dimensional Hausdorff manifold (without boundary) that is smooth and gab is a smooth, nondegenerate, pseudo-Riemannian metric of Lorentz signature (−, +, …, +) defined on M. We say two space-times (M, gab) and (M′,
) are isometric if there is a diffeomorphism
such that
. Two space-times (M, gab) and (M′,
) are locally isometric if, for each point
, there is an open neighborhood O of p and an open subset O′ of M′ such that O and O′ are isometric, and, correspondingly, with the roles of (M, gab) and (M′,
) interchanged.
A space-time (M, gab) is extendible if there exists a space-time (M, gab) and a proper isometric embedding . Here, the space-time (M′,
) is an extension of (M, gab). A space-time is inextendible if it has no extension. A
-space-time is a space-time with property
. A
-space-time (M′,
) is a
-extension of a
-space-time (M, gab) if (M′,
) is an extension of (M, gab). A
-space-time is
-extendible if it has a
-extension and is
-inextendible otherwise. We say (M, gab, F) is an n-dimensional framed space-time if (M, gab) is an n-dimensional space-time and F is an orthonormal n-ad of vectors {ξ1, … , ξn} at some point
. We say an n-dimensional framed space-time (M′,
, F′) is a framed extension of the n-dimensional framed space-time (M, gab, F) if there is a proper isometric embedding
, which takes F into F′.
For each point , the metric assigns a cone structure to the tangent space Mp. Any tangent vector ξa in Mp will be time-like if
, null if
, or space-like if
. Null vectors create the cone structure; time-like vectors are inside the cone, while space-like vectors are outside. A time orientable space-time is one that has a continuous time-like vector field on M. In what follows, it is assumed that space-times are time orientable.
For some connected interval , a smooth curve
is time-like if the tangent vector ξa at each point in γ[I] is time-like. Similarly, a curve is null (respectively, space-like) if its tangent vector at each point is null (respectively, space-like). A curve is causal if its tangent vector at each point is either null or time-like. A causal curve is future directed if its tangent vector at each point falls in or on the future lobe of the light cone. We say a time-like curve
is closed if
. A space-time (M, gab) satisfies chronology if it does not contain a closed time-like curve. For any two points p,
, we write
if there exists a future-directed time-like curve from p to q. This relation allows us to define the time-like past of a point p:
. We say a space-time (M, gab) satisfies past distinguishability if there do not exist distinct points p,
such that
. We say a set
is achronal if there do not exist p,
such that
.
An extension of a curve is a curve
such that I is a proper subset of I′ and
for all
. A curve is maximal if it has no extension. A curve
in a space-time (M, gab) is a geodesic if
, where ξa is the tangent vector and ∇a is the unique derivative operator compatible with gab. A point
is a future endpoint of a future-directed causal curve
if, for every neighborhood O of p, there exists a point
such that
for all
. A past endpoint is defined similarly. A causal curve is inextendible if it has no future or past endpoint. A causal geodesic
in a space-time (M, g) is past incomplete if it is maximal and there is an
such that
for all
.
For any set , we define the past domain of dependence of S, written D −(S), to be the set of points
such that every causal curve with past endpoint p and no future endpoint intersects S. The future domain of dependence of S, written D +(S), is defined analogously. The entire domain of dependence of S, written D(S), is just the set
. The edge of an achronal set
is the collection of points
such that every open neighborhood O of p contains a point
, a point
, and a time-like curve from r to q that does not intersect S. A set
is a slice if it is closed, achronal, and without edge. A space-time (M, gab) that contains a slice S such that
is said to be globally hyperbolic.
Given a space-time (M, gab), let Tab be defined by , where Rab is the Ricci tensor and R the scalar curvature associated with gab. We say that
satisfies the weak energy condition if, for each time-like vector ξa, we have
. We say that (M, gab) is a vacuum solution if
.
Let S be a set. A relation ≤ on S is a partial order if, for all a, b, , (i)
; (ii) if
and
, then
; and (iii) if
and
, then
. If ≤ is a partial ordering on a set S, we say a subset
is totally ordered if, for all a,
, either
or
. Let ≤ be a partial ordering on S, and let
be totally ordered. An upper bound for T is an element
such that for all
,
. A maximal element of S is an element
such that for all
, if
, then
. Zorn’s lemma (which is equivalent to the axiom of choice) is as follows: Let ≤ be a partial order on S. If each totally ordered subset
has an upper bound, there is a maximal element of S.
3. Definition
Recall the standard definition of space-time inextendibility.
Definition. A space-time (M, gab) is inextendible if there does not exist a space-time (M′, ) such that there is a proper isometric embedding
.
The definition requires that an inextendible space-time be “as large as it can be” in the sense that one compares it to a background class of all “possible” space-times. Standardly, one takes this class to be the set of all (smooth, Hausdorff) Lorentzian manifolds as defined in the previous section. But what should this class be? The answer is unclear.
Consider Misner space-time (Hawking and Ellis Reference Hawking and Ellis1973). Let Misner* be the globally hyperbolic “bottom half” of Misner space-time. By the standard definition of inextendibility, Misner* is extendible and cannot be extended and remain globally hyperbolic (see below). But suppose that a version of the cosmic censorship conjecture is correct and all physically reasonable space-times are globally hyperbolic (Penrose Reference Penrose, Hawking and Israel1979). Then should Misner* not be considered “as large as it can be”? It follows that whether Misner* space-time should count as inextendible depends crucially on the outcome of this version of the cosmic censorship conjecture—a conjecture that is far from settled (Earman Reference Earman1995; Penrose Reference Israel1999) and perhaps may never be settled (Manchak Reference Manchak2011).
Because of examples like these, one is tempted to revise the definition of inextendibility.Footnote 2 But Geroch (Reference Geroch, Carmeli, Fickler and Witten1970, 278) has argued that a revision is less urgent if one can show, for a variety of physically reasonable properties , that the following statement is true.
(*) Every -inextendible
-space-time is inextendible.
The significance of (*) is this: if a property satisfies (*), then any
-space-time is inextendible if and only if it is
-inextendible. Effectively, it makes no difference in such cases whether one defines inextendibility relative to the standard class of all space-times or a revised class of all
-space-times. Accordingly, one would like to investigate (*) with respect to a variety of properties
. Already from the Misner* example above, we have the following proposition (a proof is provided in the appendix).
Proposition 1. If is global hyperbolicity, (*) is false.
Are there physically reasonable properties that render (*) true? Geroch (Reference Geroch, Carmeli, Fickler and Witten1970, 289) has suggested a number of good candidates, including being a vacuum solution, satisfying chronology, and satisfying an energy condition. The first two cases are still open. Here, we settle the case in which
is the weak energy condition (a proof is provided in the appendix).
Proposition 2. If is the weak energy condition, (*) is false.
We see that the prospect of avoiding the need to revise to the definition of inextendibility does not look good. In the meantime, we may conclude that it is not yet clear that the standard definition captures the intuitive idea that an inextendible space-time is “as large as it can be.”
4. Metaphysics
A number of experts in general relativity (Penrose Reference Penrose1969; Geroch Reference Geroch, Carmeli, Fickler and Witten1970; Clarke Reference Clarke1976) seem to be committed to the following statement. “Metaphysical considerations suggest that to be a serious candidate for describing actuality, a spacetime should be [inextendible]. For example, for the Creative Force to actualize a proper subpart of a larger spacetime would seem to be a violation of Leibniz’s principles of sufficient reason and plenitude. If one adopts the image of spacetime as being generated or built up as time passes then the dynamical version of the principle of sufficient reason would ask why the Creative Force would stop building if it is possible to continue” (Earman Reference Earman1995, 32).
These metaphysical views are underpinned by an important result due to Geroch (Reference Geroch, Carmeli, Fickler and Witten1970).
Proposition 3. Every extendible space-time has an inextendible extension.
The result (which makes use of Zorn’s lemma) seems to show that the Creative Force can always build space-time until it is no longer possible to build. But of course, this interpretation presupposes that we have been working with the proper definition of inextendibility. And as we have noted, it is not yet clear that we are. Accordingly, one would like to know, for a variety of physically reasonable properties , whether the following version of the Geroch (Reference Geroch, Carmeli, Fickler and Witten1970) result is true.
(**) Every -extendible
-space-time has a
-inextendible
-extension.
With a bit of work (and Zorn’s lemma), one can show the following proposition (a proof is provided in the appendix).
Proposition 4. If is chronology, (**) is true.
We see that if we revise the definition of inextendibility to be relative to the class of all chronological space-times (rather than the standard class of all space-times), we have an analogue of the Geroch (Reference Geroch, Carmeli, Fickler and Witten1970) result. This is certainly good news for those committed to the metaphysical views expressed above. But are there physically reasonable properties that render (**) false? There are.
Of course, space-time properties may be considered physically reasonable in various senses. Let us conservatively restrict attention to a property usually taken to be satisfied by models of our own universe: the property of having every inextendible time-like geodesic be past incomplete. Let us call this the big bang property, given that it is satisfied by all of the standard “big bang” cosmological models. We are now in a position to state the following proposition (Manchak Reference Manchak2016b).
Proposition 5. If is the big bang property, (**) is false.
We see that if we revise the definition of inextendibility to be relative to the class of all space-times with the big bang property (rather than the standard class of all space-times), we do not have an analogue of the Geroch (Reference Geroch, Carmeli, Fickler and Witten1970) result. It is not yet clear that the Creative Force always has the option of building space-time to be “as large as it can be.”
5. Epistemology
What observational evidence is there (or could there be) in support of the position that space-time is “as large as it can be”? Following Malament (Reference Malament, Earman, Glymour and Stachel1977), let us say that a space-time (M, gab) is observationally indistinguishable from another space-time (M′, ) if, for every point
, there is a point
such that I −(p) and I −(p′) are isometric. One can show the following proposition (Manchak Reference Manchak2011).
Proposition 6. Every chronological space-time is observationally indistinguishable from some other (nonisometric) space-time that is extendible.
Under the standard definition of inextendibility, it seems that any observer in a chronological space-time is not in a position to know that her space-time is “as large as it can be.” But this interpretation presupposes that we have been working with the proper definition of inextendibility. And as we have noted, it is not yet clear that we are. Accordingly, one would like to know, for a variety of physically reasonable properties , whether the following version of the Manchak (Reference Manchak2011) result is true.
(***) Every chronological -space-time is observationally indistinguishable from some other (nonisometric)
-space-time that is
-extendible.
It turns out that a large class of physically reasonable properties render (***) true. Following Manchak (Reference Manchak2011), let us say that a property on a space-time is local if, given any two locally isometric space-times (M, gab) and (M′,
), (M, gab) has
if and only if (M′,
) has
. Local properties include being a vacuum solution and satisfying the weak energy condition. We are now in a position to state the following proposition (a proof is provided in the appendix).
Proposition 7. If is a local property, (***) is true.
We see that, whenever is a local property, if we revise the definition of inextendibility to be relative to the class of all
-space-times (rather than the standard class of all space-times), we have an analogue of the Manchak (Reference Manchak2011) result. It is not yet clear that we can ever have observational evidence that space-time is “as large as it can be.”
6. Conclusion
We have registered some skepticism with respect to the position that space-time must be inextendible—that it must be “as large as it can be” in some sense. We have done this in a variety of ways. First we have shown that it is not yet clear that the standard definition of inextendibility captures the intuitive idea that an inextendible space-time is “as large as it can be.” Second, we have shown, by exploring some plausible revisions to the definition of inextendibility, that it is not yet clear that a space-time can always be extended to be “as large as it can be.” Finally we have shown, by exploring a class of plausible revisions to the definition of inextendibility, that it is not yet clear that we can ever know that space-time is “as large as it can be.”
Appendix
Proposition 1. If is global hyperbolicity, (*) is false.
Proof. Let (N, gab) be Misner space-time. So, and
, where the points (t, φ) are identified with the points (t,
) for all integers n. Now, let
and consider the space-time (M, gab). Clearly, it is extendible. It is also globally hyperbolic since the slice
is such that
. We need only show that any extension to (M, gab) fails to be globally hyperbolic.
Let (M′, ) be any extension of (M, gab), and let p be a point in
. In any neighborhood of p, there will be a point
such that
. One can verify that
. Thus, (M′,
) is not past distinguishing and therefore not globally hyperbolic (Hawking and Ellis Reference Hawking and Ellis1973). QED
Proposition 2. If is the weak energy condition, (*) is false.
Proof. Consider Minkowski space-time (ℝ4, ηab) in standard (t, x, y, z) coordinates, where . Let
be the function defined by
. Consider the space-time (ℝ4, gab), where
. Associated with gab we have (Wald Reference Wald1984, 446)

We note that and
. Of course,
. Simplifying, we have

Einstein’s equation requires that

In (ℝ4, gab), consider any time-like vector , where k 0, k 1, k 2,
and
. We have

Because , we know
. And for
, we know
. It follows that
for
.
Let . We have shown that the space-time (M,
) is such that it satisfies the weak energy condition and is extendible. It remains for us to show that any extension to (M,
) fails to satisfy the weak energy condition.
Let be any extension to (M,
). Let p be a point in
. Let (O, φ) be a chart with
such that we can extend the coordinates (t, x, y, z) on M to
. So, for some p 1, p 2,
we have
. Find some
such that
. For
, let
.
Consider the smooth function given by
, where
. Of course, for all
, we have

Smoothness requires that . This allows us to find an
such that
for all
. So ζa is time-like at p(t) for all
.
Consider the smooth function given by
, where
is defined on M′ in the natural way (using the metric
and Einstein’s equation). Of course, for all
, we have

Because and
, we have for all

Smoothness requires that and
. This allows us to find a
such that
for
. Thus, the weak energy condition is violated at p(t) for all
. QED
Definition. Let denote the set of framed space-times. Let ≤ denote the relation on
such that
if and only if (M′,
, F′) is a framed extension of (M, gab, F).
Lemma 1. The relation ≤ is a partial ordering on .
Proof. See Geroch (Reference Geroch1969, 188–89). QED
Lemma 2. Let denote the set of framed space-times that satisfy chronology.
is partially ordered by ≤. Every subset
that is totally ordered by ≤ has an upper bound in
.
Proof. Since , it follows from lemma 1 that
is partially ordered by ≤. Let
be a subset of
that is totally ordered by ≤. Following Hawking and Ellis (Reference Hawking and Ellis1973, 249), let M be the union of all the Mi, where, for
, each
is identified with φij(pi), where
is the unique isometric embedding that takes Fi into Fj. The manifold M will have an induced metric g equal to φi* gi on each φi[Mi], where
is the natural isometric embedding. Finally, take F to be the result of carrying along a chosen Fi using
. Consider the framed space-time (M, g, F). We claim it is an upper bound for
. Clearly, for all i, we have
. We need only show that
.
Suppose , and let
be (the image of) a closed time-like curve. As a topological space (with induced topology from M), γ is compact. For all i, let γi be
. So,
is an open cover of γ. By compactness, there must be a finite subset
that is also a cover of γ. One can use the relation ≤ on
to order the finite number of elements in A′ into a nested sequence of subsets
. It follows that
. So,
: a contradiction. QED
Proposition 4. If is chronology, (**) is true.
Proof. Let be chronology, and let (M, gab) be a
-space-time that is
-extendible. Let F be an orthonormal n-ad at some point
. So,
, where
is the set of framed space-times that satisfy chronology. By lemma 2 and Zorn’s lemma, there is a maximal element
such that
. It follows that (M′,
) is a
-inextendible
-extension of (M, gab). QED
Proposition 7. If is a local property, (***) is true.
Proof. Let be any local property, and let (M, gab) be any chronological
-space-time. Now construct (M′,
) according to the method outlined in Manchak (Reference Manchak2009). Note that (M′,
) is a
-space-time by construction. Next, remove any point in the M(1, b) portion of the manifold M′, and call the resulting space-time (M″,
). One can verify that (i) (M, gab) is observationally indistinguishable from (M″,
), (ii) (M″,
) is a
-space-time, and (iii) (M, gab) is not isometric to (M″,
). Since (M′,
) is a
-extension to (M″,
), the latter is
-extendible. QED