1. Introduction
According to conventional wisdom in physics, von Neumann entropy corresponds to phenomenological thermodynamic entropy. The origin of this claim is von Neumann’s (Reference von Neumann1955) argument that his proposed entropy corresponds to the thermodynamic entropy, which appears to be the only explicit argument for the equivalence of the two entropies. However, Hemmo and Shenker (Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006)—and earlier, Shenker (Reference Shenker1999)—have argued that this correspondence fails, contrary to von Neumann. If so, this leaves conventional wisdom without explicit justification.
Correspondence can be understood, at the very least, as a numerical consistency check: in this context, this means that the von Neumann entropy has to be included in calculating thermodynamic entropy to ensure consistent accounting in contexts in which both thermodynamic and von Neumann entropy are physically relevant. Successful correspondence provides strong evidence of equivalence. While it does not guarantee equivalence, it seems to be at least a necessary condition for equivalence. If thermodynamic entropy and von Neumann entropy correspond, then we have reason to think that von Neumann entropy is rightfully thermodynamic in nature, since proper accounting of thermodynamic entropy would demand von Neumann entropy. By contrast, a failure of correspondence seems to entail that the von Neumann entropy is not thermodynamical in nature, since it is irrelevant to thermodynamic calculations in contexts in which both entropies are physically significant (e.g., when a system both has quantum degrees of freedom and is sufficiently large to warrant thermodynamical considerations).
Although Henderson (Reference Henderson2003), in my view, has successfully criticized Shenker’s earlier argument, little has been done in the philosophical literature to evaluate Hemmo and Shenker’s more recent arguments.Footnote 1 This lacuna is striking because, as I mentioned, von Neumann appears to offer the only explicit argument for correspondence for the two entropies.
My goal in this article is to fill this lacuna by providing a novel set of criticisms to Hemmo and Shenker. Here is the plan. I introduce key terms (sec. 2) and then present von Neumann’s thought experiment, which aims to establish the correspondence between thermodynamic entropy and von Neumann entropy; along the way, a novel counterpart to the usual argument for correspondence is discussed (sec. 3). I then present and criticize Hemmo and Shenker’s arguments for the single-particle case in the context of thermodynamics (sec. 4.1) and in the context of statistical mechanics (sec. 4.2), the N-particles case (sec. 4.3), and the infinite-particles case (sec. 4.4). I conclude that their argument fails in all cases—in turn, we have good reasons to reject their claim that the von Neumann entropy fails to correspond to thermodynamic entropy and, hence, the claim that von Neumann entropy is not thermodynamic in nature.
2. Key Terms
Let me first define the notions of thermodynamic entropy and von Neumann entropy. Following Hemmo and Shenker (Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006), I define the change in thermodynamic entropy S TD between two thermodynamic states in an isothermal quasi-static process as follows:Footnote 2

We will restrict our discussion to ideal gases in equilibrium (i.e., systems where pressure P, volume V, and temperature T remain constant).
Next, the von Neumann entropy S VN, for any pure or mixed quantum system, is defined as

where k is the Boltzmann constant and Tr(·) is the trace function. Generally, the density matrix ρ is such that

where ψ1, ψ2, … ψn correspond to the number of pure states in a statistical mixture represented by ρ, with p 1, p 2, … pn being their associated classical probabilities (which must sum to unity). In the case in which there is only one pure state possible for a system (e.g., when we are absolutely certain about its quantum state), then
, with probability 1, so the appropriate density matrix is
. For such a system in a pure state (i.e., represented by a single-state vector in Hilbert space),
. For mixed states (i.e., states that cannot be represented by a single-state vector in Hilbert space, hence mixture of pure states or a mixed state), Tr(ρ log ρ) < 1 and
in general. A mixed state is often said to represent our ignorance about a system—this will suffice as a first approximation (more on how to interpret this ignorance in sec. 4.2).
Prima facie, S VN and S TD appear to share nothing in common, apart from the word ‘entropy’. However, von Neumann claims that there are important correlations between the two, which suggests a correspondence between S TD and S VN.
3. Von Neumann’s Thought Experiment
For the sake of parity, I adopt Hemmo and Shenker’s (Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006) presentation of von Neumann’s thought experiment, which aims to show that changes in thermodynamic entropy can be made consistent with the laws of thermodynamics only if we considered the von Neumann entropy as contributing to the calculation of the thermodynamic entropy.Footnote 3 Figure 1 depicts the stages of the thought experiment.

Figure 1. Top to bottom, stages 1–7, as described by Hemmo and Shenker (Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006).
We begin, in stage 1, with a box with a partition in the middle. On one side of the partition there is a gas at volume V, constant temperature T, and constant pressure P. Each gas particle starts off having the pure state spin-up along the x-direction
, which is equivalent to a superposition of spin-up and spin-down pure states along the z-direction, labeled
and
respectively. According to standard quantum mechanics, the state of each particle is thus
.
In this context, particles with quantum behavior may be taken to be ideal gases, that is, sets of particles each of which does not interact with other particles and takes up infinitesimal space. Following von Neumann’s (Reference von Neumann1955, 361) assumptions, each gas particle is understood as a quantum particle with a spin degree of freedom contained inside a large impenetrable box, and each gas particle is put inside an even larger container isolated from the environment (i.e., the box we began with).Footnote 4 This ensures that each spin degree of freedom is incapable of interacting with other particles. These boxes’ sizes also ensure that the positions of these boxes (and hence of the particles) can be approximately classical. Since the container is much larger than each gas particle, this ensures that the gas particles take up negligible space relative to the massive container. Accepting these assumptions, we may then take these quantum particles to behave like an ideal gas.Footnote 5 Following Hemmo and Shenker, we further assume that the position degrees of freedom of the gas particles have no interaction with the spin degrees of freedom at this point, and “due to the large mass of the boxes, the position degrees of freedom of the gas may be taken to be classical and represented by a quantum mechanical mixture” (Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006, 155).
Moving on, stage 2 involves a spin measurement along the Z-axis on all the particles in the container, with a result being an equally weighted statistical mixture of particles with either
or
states. As a result, the spin state of each particle is represented instead by a density matrix ρspin, such that

More precisely, there should be terms for the measurement device too, when truly considering the entire system. Matrix ρspin describes only the subsystem (i.e., the quantum ideal gas) sans measurement device (i.e., a state with the measurement device traced out)—this is in line with von Neumann’s focus on the entropy changes due to changes in the subsystem (Reference von Neumann1955, 358–79). I follow Henderson (Reference Henderson2003) and Hemmo and Shenker (Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006) in talking about the system’s state as though I have already traced the measurement device out whenever measurement is involved.
Stages 3 and 4 are where the particles are (reversibly) separated according to their spin states by a semipermeable wall into two sides of the box, each with volume V.Footnote 6 As a result of this separation, we in effect double the mixture’s volume. The gas expands to fill up volume V on each side.
Stage 5 involves an isothermal and quasi-static compression of the mixture so that we return to a total volume V (effectively halving the volume on each side of the box), while pressure on both sides becomes equal. Importantly, because of this compression, S TD decreases because of the decrease in volume.
Stage 6 brings all the particles into the pure spin state
quasi-statically and without work done, while stage 7 removes the semipermeable wall, such that the system returns to its original state.
Now consider how S VN and S TD change across the various stages. Stage 7 ends with the body of gas having the same thermodynamic state (same V, same P, and constant T) as stage 1. Furthermore, all the thermodynamic transformations performed were reversible, and removing the wall alone does no additional work. Thus, the system at stage 1 must have the same thermodynamic entropy as stage 7 (i.e.,
) since S TD depends only on the initial and final state of the system. From stages 1 to 7,
too, since the system is in the same state in both the first and seventh stages.
Since stage 6 does not involve thermodynamic transformations, there is no change in S TD. Likewise, the transformation of ρspin to
here does not change S VN, as the transformation can be performed unitarily. This is possible as a result of our separation of the gases to different sides of the box according to their spin eigenstates—given this, we can perform unitary operations on each side of the box (or perform the more general measurement procedure recommended by von Neumann [Reference von Neumann1955, 365–67]), to transform them into the same state as stage 1. Both unitary transformations and von Neumann’s procedure do not increase S VN, and so there is no change in S VN at stage 6 as a result.
There are no changes in S TD or S VN in stages 3 and 4. While there is an increase in the gas’s volume, as noted above, from V to 2V, and hence an accompanying increase in S TD by n.R.log 2,Footnote 7 there is also a compensating change in the thermodynamic entropy of mixing, by −n.R.log 2, which exactly compensates this increase in S TD (see Hemmo and Shenker Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006, 157 n. 4).Footnote 8 Since the particles are in orthogonal spin states at this stage, there are no quantum effects (e.g., ‘collapse’ effects) from simply filtering the gases with the semipermeable walls, and hence S VN does not change either.Footnote 9
However, importantly, there is a decrease in S TD in stage 5, of −n.R.log 2, because of the isothermal compression and decrease in volume. Yet, nowhere else is there any further change in S TD. We have to account for why the overall change in S TD from the first to the seventh stages is 0.
As von Neumann argues, only one possibility remains. While S TD remains constant in stage 2, notice that there was an increase in S VN, of
, as a result of the spin measurement.Footnote 10 This is equivalent to the change of S TD in stage 5. The state of each particle changes from a pure state
to a mixed state represented by ρspin, and hence S VN for the gas increases on the whole. In order to ensure that entropic changes are consistent, von Neumann thinks that we should accept S VN’s contribution to S TD in this context, where both quantum effects and thermodynamical considerations are at play. Without accepting S VN in our entropic accounting, we end up with a violation of thermodynamics since we have a reversible thermodynamic cycle with nonzero change in S TD, contra the Second Law. In other words, we should accept that S VN corresponds to S TD.
The correspondence of S VN and S TD in this context can be defended from another perspective, apart from considerations about consistency from the thermodynamic perspective: consistent accounting from the perspective of quantum mechanics also demands correspondence. This is simply a change in perspective with regard to the thought experiment, but, to my knowledge, this argument has not been explicitly made in the literature, thus underselling the case for correspondence in von Neumann’s thought experiment.
Instead of arguing for correspondence by considering thermodynamic consistency, that is, ensuring that
throughout the cycle, we can consider consistency from the quantum mechanical perspective. We started and ended with the same spin state, and so it should be the case that
throughout the cycle. Yet, there is an inconsistency: if we only consider the increase of S VN in stage 2 as a result of measurement, we should end in stage 7 with an increase in S VN, not
. As described, there is nowhere else in the thought experiment where S VN changes. However, there is a decrease in S TD in stage 5 because of the thermodynamic process of isothermal compression, exactly balancing out the increase in S VN. Hence, we can ensure consistency (i.e., that
), only by taking S VN to correspond to S TD. In other words, just as the thermodynamic accounting of S TD is consistent only if we consider S VN, the quantum entropic accounting of S VN is also consistent only if we consider S TD. Consistency from a quantum mechanical perspective also demands correspondence between S VN and S TD.
Although the debate has largely focused only on how the thought experiment demonstrates one direction of correspondence, of S VN to S TD as a result of thermodynamical considerations, the correspondence demonstrated by this thought experiment in fact goes both ways. Of course, since von Neumann was focused on demonstrating the thermodynamic nature of S VN (specifically the irreversibility of measurement), rather than the quantum nature of S TD, it was natural that he chose to approach it the way he did.
4. Hemmo and Shenker’s Arguments
Hemmo and Shenker disagree with von Neumann’s argument and criticize it by considering three cases: the single-particle case, the finite but large N particles case, and the infinite-particles case.
4.1. Single-Particle Case: Thermodynamics
Hemmo and Shenker first consider von Neumann’s argument in the single-particle case (see fig. 2). They claim that the argument does not go through here, since S TD actually remains constant, contrary to our thought experiment’s description. In other words, using thermodynamical considerations, they find that S VN should not be included in our accounting for S TD.

Figure 2. Top to bottom, stages 1–7 for the single-particle case, as described by Hemmo and Shenker (Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006).
Here is their argument. Consider the stages where there are entropic changes. In stage 2 when the spin measurement was performed, S VN increases as before, since it tracks the change of the particle’s spin state from pure to mixed.
Contrariwise, S TD does not change in stage 5 (isothermal quasi-static compression) or anywhere else (this will be important later). After stage 2, the single particle is in either the
state or the
state. After stages 3 and 4, with the expansion and separation via a semipermeable wall, there is a particle in one side of the box only and not the other. We make an S TD-conserving location measurement to figure out which side of the box is empty and which side the particle is at, so as to compress the box against the empty side.Footnote 11 The compression is then performed as before. However, this compression does not decrease S TD.Footnote 12 To restore the volume of the ‘gas’ to V, no work needs to be done, since we are compressing against a vacuum. Since there is a change in S VN in this cycle, but no change in S TD, the apparent answer, in order to do our entropic accounting, is to ignore, not incorporate, S VN into S TD. Hence, S VN does not correspond to S TD.
Their analysis is problematic. Although their ultimate point in this analysis—that S TD fails to corresponds to S VN—still holds, it does not hold in the way they claim. In fact, the way it fails suggests to us that we should disregard the single-particle case.
For the single-particle case, they claim that “[S TD] is null throughout the experiment” (Hemmo and Shenker Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006, 162). This then allows them to claim that thermodynamic accounting for S TD is consistent only if we did not consider S VN. This then supports their claim that S VN does not correspond to S TD since adding S VN into the thermodynamic accounting actually renders the otherwise consistent calculations inconsistent.
They are right to say that the stage 5 compression (after location measurement) has no thermodynamic effect because we are compressing against a vacuum: no work needs to be done, and so
for stage 5. However, I claim that
for the single-particle case overall, because
in stages 3 and 4 in this context.
As far as I can tell, Hemmo and Shenker did not analyze stages 3 and 4 (i.e., the isothermal expansion and separation) in terms of the single-particle case at all. Rather, they seem to have assumed that
in these stages as with the original case of the macroscopic gas.Footnote 13 However, this assumes that there is both a change in entropy of n.R.log 2 because of isothermal expansion and a change in the entropy of mixing of −n.R.log 2 because of separation, as they say so themselves for the original case: “The increase of thermodynamic entropy due to the volume increase
is exactly compensated by the decrease of thermodynamic mixing entropy
(where wk is the relative frequency of molecules of type k) due to the separation” (Hemmo and Shenker Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006, 157 n. 4, emphasis mine).
In the single-particle case, it makes sense that isothermal expansion should still increase S TD, since the single-particle ‘gas’ is expanding against a piston and doing work. However, it does not make physical sense to speak of the entropy of mixing here at all, since there is no separation of gases in the single-particle case. The entropy of mixing is explicitly defined for systems where different gases are separated from/mixed with one another via semipermeable walls, but a single particle cannot be separated from/mixed with itself. The quote above makes this conceptual point explicit: by Hemmo and Shenker’s own lights, the relative frequency of a single particle is simply unity (and null for particles of other types), so the entropy of mixing is
. There is no thermodynamic entropy of mixing in the single-particle case.
Discounting the entropy of mixing, however, we find that
for stages 3 and 4, and hence for the entire process, contrary to Hemmo and Shenker’s claim. Interestingly, correspondence does fail to obtain between S TD and S VN, since
, despite the process being reversible ex hypothesi: incorporating S VN into thermodynamic accounting violates the Second Law.
However, on this new analysis, we gain some clarity as to why the single-particle case is problematic. While it is true that incorporating S VN into the thermodynamic accounting violates the Second Law, S TD accounting by itself violates the Second Law (contrary to Hemmo and Shenker Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006). Even without considering S VN,
despite the process being reversible. Thermodynamic accounting is inconsistent here no matter what we do, which suggests that the reversible process they described for the single-particle case is thermodynamically unsound: if so, any argument Hemmo and Shenker make in this context may be disregarded.
The upshot: I agree with Hemmo and Shenker that correspondence fails for the single-particle case, but I do not agree about why it fails. It is not because the process they described is already thermodynamically consistent without taking S VN into account. Rather, it is because the process is already thermodynamically inconsistent anyway.
In recent work, John Norton argued that thermodynamically reversible processes for single-particle systems are impossible in principle, which might explain why the process described by Hemmo and Shenker (Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006) is thermodynamically unsound: it was not justified to assume the process was reversible for a single-particle system. For Norton, a reversible process is “loosely speaking, one whose driving forces are so delicately balanced around equilibrium that only a very slight disturbance to them can lead the process to reverse direction. Because such processes are arbitrarily close to a perfect balance of driving forces, they proceed arbitrarily slowly while their states remain arbitrarily close to equilibrium states” (Reference Norton2017, 135). Norton notes that these thermodynamic equilibrium states are balanced not because there are no fluctuations but because these fluctuations are negligible for macroscopic systems. However, fluctuations relative to single-particle systems are large and generally prevent these systems from being in equilibrium states at any point of the process, rendering reversible processes impossible in the single-particle case (135). If reversible processes are impossible for single-particle systems in general, then it should come as no surprise that the particular single-particle reversible process used by Hemmo and Shenker is likewise thermodynamically unsound, as my analysis above suggests. If so, their claim that correspondence fails in this process is simply beside the point, since this process is not thermodynamic at all.
Since any reversible process cannot be realized for single-particle systems in general, the issue seems not to be with any particular process per se but with the single-particle case simpliciter. To my knowledge, no one before Hemmo and Shenker (Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006) discussed von Neumann’s experiment in terms of a single particle; von Neumann (Reference von Neumann1955), Peres (Reference Peres and Zurek1990, Reference Peres2002), Shenker (Reference Shenker1999), and Henderson (Reference Henderson2003) all explicitly or implicitly assume a large (or infinite) number of particles. This is for good reason. As Hemmo and Shenker acknowledge, and as we have seen: “The case of a single particle is known to be problematic as far as arguments in thermodynamics are concerned” (Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006, 158). Matter in phenomenological thermodynamics is assumed to be continuous.Footnote 14 A ‘gas’ composed of one particle can be many things, but it is surely not continuous in any commonly accepted sense. In other words, it is just not clear whether the domain of thermodynamics should apply to the single-particle case at all.
As Myrvold (Reference Myrvold2011) notes, Maxwell also made a similar claim with regard to phenomenological thermodynamics in general; it does not and should not hold in the single-particle case. On his view, the laws of phenomenological thermodynamics, notably the Second Law, must be continually violated on small scales:
If we restrict our attention to any one molecule of the system, we shall find its motion changing at every encounter in a most irregular manner. … If we go on to consider a finite number of molecules, even if the system to which they belong contains an infinite number, the average properties of this group, though subject to smaller variations than those of a single molecule, are still every now and then deviating very considerably from the theoretical mean of the whole system, because the molecules which form the group do not submit their procedure as individuals to the laws which prescribe the behaviour of the average or mean molecule. … Hence the second law of thermodynamics is continually being violated, and that to a considerable extent, in any sufficiently small group of molecules belonging to a real body. As the number of molecules in the group is increased, the deviations from the mean of the whole become smaller and less frequent.
(Maxwell Reference Maxwell1878, 280)The Second Law, and hence phenomenological thermodynamics, should not be expected to hold true universally in small-scale cases, especially not in the single-particle case. Von Neumann and everyone else in the debate should have recognized this point. Why, then, should it matter that the thought experiment succeeds or fails in this case? Phenomenological thermodynamics does not apply to single-particle cases. There is thus no profit in trying to establish correspondence between S VN and S TD in this case. Indeed, if we took seriously Maxwell’s claim that the Second Law fails at small scales, a failure of thermodynamic entropic accounting might even be expected; it does not rule out the possible thermodynamic nature of S VN even though the sum of S VN and S TD might be inconsistent with the Second Law. In short, it is not clear why the single-particle case is relevant to the discussion at hand.
Hemmo and Shenker’s reasoning is untenable, because they fail to respect the context of phenomenological thermodynamics by bringing it into a context in which it is not expected to hold. Instead, it seems more appropriate that the single-particle case is precisely beyond the purview of classical thermodynamics, requiring an analogue that only corresponds to classical thermodynamics at the appropriate scales and limits. We may then take S VN to be the analogue of S TD in this case, only approximating S TD as the system in question approaches the context suitable for traditional thermodynamic analysis. If so, we may see von Neumann as merely demonstrating that S VN corresponds, not at all domains but in the domain where thermodynamics is taken to hold, to S TD.
4.2. Single-Particle Case Redux: Statistical Mechanics and Information
Given the foregoing discussion, Hemmo and Shenker might insist that S VN fails to correspond to S TD even when taking into account a more relevant domain for single particles—statistical mechanics. After directly arguing that S VN does not correspond to S TD (Hemmo and Shenker Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006, 162–65), they further argue that S VN does not correspond to information entropy (more on this below) in the single-particle case. Prima facie, this should seem irrelevant to von Neumann’s argument, which was to establish the correspondence of the thermodynamic S TD and quantum S VN: Why should information entropy’s failure to correspond with S VN be a worry at all?
Here is one plausible worry, on a charitable reading. If information entropy corresponds to S TD, and Hemmo and Shenker show that S VN fails to correspond to information entropy, then we might conclude, indirectly, that S VN does not correspond to S TD after all.Footnote 15 This argument assumes that information entropy does correspond to S TD, an assumption Hemmo and Shenker seem to hold as well: this is in line with the so-called subjectivist view of statistical mechanics (notably, see Jaynes Reference Jaynes1957). Furthermore, my above argument against the misapplication of phenomenological thermodynamics does not seem to apply here, since this argument is being made in the context of statistical mechanics and its particle picture, with no commitment to phenomenological thermodynamics.
However, Hemmo and Shenker do not do much to motivate the linkage between information entropy and S TD; indeed, in their words, “a linkage between the Shannon information and thermodynamic entropy has not been established” (Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006, 164). Without this link, the failure of correspondence between the information entropy and S VN appears, at best, irrelevant to the correspondence between S TD and S VN. Nevertheless, I will take a charitable view here and assume that there is a correspondence between information entropy and S TD, for the sake of assessing their argument. Here is a plausible (if arguable) sketch: if one were a subjectivist like Jaynes (Reference Jaynes1957), one might take the Gibbs entropy in statistical mechanics to be a special case of the information entropy. After all, both have the following form:

with i being the number of possible states with associated probabilities of occurring pi and the Gibbs entropy being multiplied by an additional Boltzmann’s constant k.Footnote 16 We know that statistical mechanics corresponds to phenomenological thermodynamics at the thermodynamic limit, so we can think of the Gibbs entropy, and hence information entropy, as corresponding to S TD. I take this to be in line with what Hemmo and Shenker have in mind: “to the extent that the Shannon information underwrites the thermodynamic entropy, it does so via statistical mechanics” (Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006, 165). Assuming that the above picture is plausible, a failure of correspondence between S VN and the information entropy provides evidence against the correspondence between S VN and S TD.
Their argument comes into two parts. Ignoring S TD for the time being (which does not change throughout the cycle for the single-particle case—see sec. 4.1), they claim that we can consider the stage 5 location measurement to be a decrease in information entropy of ln 2, as a result of learning information about which one of two parts of the box the particle is in. On first glance, this seems to resolve the arithmetic inconsistency in entropic accounting: ln 2 is exactly the increase in S VN as a result of the spin state changing from a pure state
to the mixed state ρspin in stage 2. In other words, for both the information and von Neumann entropies’ accounting to be correct (i.e., net change of zero across the cycle), we must consider S VN as corresponding to information entropy. Now, since information entropy also corresponds, ex hypothesi, to S TD, we have an indirect argument for the correspondence of S VN to S TD.
However, Hemmo and Shenker claim that this argument fails for collapse interpretations, that is, interpretations of quantum mechanics on which a superposed quantum state ontologically collapses into a pure state upon measurement (either precisely or approximately).Footnote 17 They allow that, on no-collapse interpretations (e.g., Bohmian or many-worlds interpretations), the location measurement in stage 5 does not decrease S VN, since the state of the system never changes in light of measurements, and so the above argument goes through.
Let us see what they could mean by this claim by following the state of the particle through the cycle. At stage 2, everyone agrees that the state of the system is ρspin following the z-spin measurement; S VN increases by ln 2. At this point, the particle’s position degrees of freedom remain independent from its spin degrees of freedom, as per our ideal gas assumption, although we might assume the particle starts out on the left half of the box, with the mixture of position states ρpos(L) with ‘L’ representing the left side. (Consider fig. 1 but with only one particle.) Following the semipermeable wall’s filtering at stages 3 and 4, the location of the particle becomes classically correlated with the spin. Let us say that the semipermeable wall sends
particles to the left, represented by ρpos(L), and
particles to the right, represented by ρpos(R). As such, the (mixed) state of the particle is now

For no-collapse interpretations, Hemmo and Shenker agree that the state of the particle stays the same as above after the location measurement in stage 5. We perform the compression in stage 5 and remove the partition at the end of stage 6, thereby removing the classical correlations between position and spin. No further change in either information entropy or S VN occurs, and hence the correspondence goes through (Hemmo and Shenker Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006, 164). The spin state remains mixed until unitarily transformed into a pure state and completing the cycle.
For collapse interpretations, they claim that the location measurement decreases S VN by ln 2, because, on collapse interpretations, the state of the particle upon the measurement, depending on which side the particle is found, becomes

The spin state of the system here effectively goes from being a mixed state to a pure state as a result of this measurement: S VN decreases by ln 2. Summing up the entropy changes, there was a decrease of ln 2 in information entropy and a net change of zero for S VN as a result of the increase in stage 2 and the decrease in stage 5. Overall, then, the change is not zero but −ln 2; our accounting has gone awry, and there is a failure of correspondence between S VN and information entropy. If this is right, S VN does not correspond to S TD.
However, I think that Hemmo and Shenker are wrong to claim that S VN decreases following the location measurement for collapse interpretations. As Prunkl (Reference Prunkl2020, 272) notes, there is an inconsistency here. Everyone, including Hemmo and Shenker, agrees that the spin state of the particle is mixed—not pure—after stage 2’s spin measurement, even on collapse interpretations (Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006, 160). In that case, why does the particle’s spin become pure after the location measurement?
I think this results from a confusion over the nature of mixed states. In particular, they seem to have adopted what Hughes (Reference Hughes1992, secs. 5.4, 5.8) calls the “ignorance interpretation” of mixed states, confusing what I call classical and quantum ignorance. They seem to be assuming that mixed states simply represents classical ignorance (i.e., the lack of knowledge about a particular system): a system represented by a mixed state really is in a pure state, but we know not which. This is why the location measurement is supposed to reveal to us the pure state of this system (by revealing which side it is on and hence the correlated spin state) and hence ‘wash away’ our classical ignorance of the real state of the system. Postmeasurement, we know exactly which pure state this system is in, unlike premeasurement; hence, S VN decreases.
However, as Hughes (Reference Hughes1992, 144–50) argues, this interpretation of mixed states—as representing classical ignorance about which pure state a particular system is in—cannot be the right interpretation of all mixed states. To begin, a mixed state can be decomposed in nonunique ways in general. Here is a simple example: a mixed state representing a mixture of
and
can also represent a mixture of
and
, and so on. If we insist that a mixed state represent our classical ignorance about the real state of a particular system, then we end up having to say that a system’s state is really both either
or
and either
or
. Of course, this is impossible given quantum mechanics. The defender of the classical ignorance interpretation might insist that we simply pick one pair of possible pure states but not both at once. In general, however, there is no way to do that nonarbitrarily given some density matrix. Furthermore, this problem only worsens when we consider that there are usually more than just two ways to decompose a density matrix—a principled choice based on the mixed state alone is not feasible. The mixed state cannot be a representation of classical ignorance.
Instead, to paraphrase Hughes (Reference Hughes1992, 144–45), mixed states should be (minimally) interpreted as such. If we prepared in the same way an ensemble of systems, each described with the same mixed state (i.e., a mixture of pure states with certain weights), then the relative frequency of any given measurement outcome from the ensemble is exactly what we would get if the ensemble were composed of various ‘subensembles’ each in one of the pure states in the mixture, with the relative frequency of each subensemble in the ensemble given by the corresponding weights.
In other words, the sort of quantum ignorance relevant in the right interpretation of mixed states is not whether we are ignorant about the real state of this particular system but whether we are ignorant about the measured states of an ensemble of identically prepared systems like this one. If this is right, quantum ignorance cannot be ‘washed away’ upon measurement of a single system unlike the sort of ignorance Hemmo and Shenker were implicitly assuming, and it seems like this quantum ignorance is precisely what remains after the location measurement.
This was roughly Henderson’s (Reference Henderson2003) criticism against Shenker (Reference Shenker1999), which is why it is puzzling that Hemmo and Shenker (Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006) commit the same mistake:
This preparation produces the pure states [
] and [
] with equal probabilities. In a particular trial, the observer may take note of the measurement result, and he therefore discovers that he has say a [
]. If he applies a projective measurement in the
basis, he could predict that he will measure [
]. However, this does not mean that, if someone handed him another state prepared in the same way, he could again predict that the outcome of his measurement would be [
]. In this sense the observer does not know the state of the system which is being prepared, and it is because of this ignorance that the state is mixed. Looking at the measurement result does not remove the fact that there is a probability distribution over the possible outcomes.
This applies to the location measurement in stage 5 too: measuring the location of the particle in this case does not change the state of the particle from a mixed one to a pure one even on collapse interpretations. First, it seems quite irrelevant whether we adopt a collapse or no-collapse interpretation, because the collapse mechanism applies to superposed pure states, not statistical mixtures. If anything, collapse had already happened in the stage 2 measurement procedure, yet everyone including Hemmo and Shenker (Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006, 160) accept that the system is in a mixed state after stage 2 even for collapse interpretations. More importantly, there remains a probability distribution over the states of the particle as a result of stage 2’s spin measurement, even after the location measurement. Given an ensemble of particles prepared from stages 1 to 5 in the same way, we are still not be able to predict with certainty whether an ensemble of particles would all be measured on the left or right sides of the box (and hence all spin-up or spin-down) as a result of the mixed state resulting from stage 2, only that half of the ensembles will be on the left and the other half will be on the right. Quantum ignorance remains—the system remains in a mixed state even after the location measurement, as

This is exactly the state of the system in no-collapse interpretations; that is, quantum ignorance does not discern between collapse and no-collapse interpretations. What has gone away is the classical ignorance that Hemmo and Shenker (mistakenly) assumed was relevant for mixed states, ignorance about this particular system’s state. By measuring the system’s location, we come to learn of the correlations between location measurement and the particle’s spin. This ignorance does not change the mixed state to a pure state: instead, this loss of classical ignorance—gain in information—is represented as a decrease in information entropy just as before, and this information is what we use to perform the compression in stage 5.
As a result, there is no additional decrease in S VN in stage 5 for collapse interpretations; the entropy accounting lines up after all, as with no-collapse interpretations. The decrease in information entropy does correspond to the increase in S VN, and so information entropy does correspond to S VN after all. Hemmo and Shenker’s argument does not establish the failure of correspondence between S VN and S TD via the failure of S VN and information entropy to correspond.
To sum up, their arguments in the single-particle case are either ill motivated and irrelevant to von Neumann and our discussion of correspondence when considered in terms of phenomenological thermodynamics or outright fail when considered in the more relevant domain of (informational approaches to) statistical mechanics. Either way, their argument does not support the failure of correspondence between S VN and S TD.Footnote 18
4.3. Finitely Many Particles
Hemmo and Shenker’s argument in the case of finitely many particles rests on the assumption of equidistribution; that is, that the particles will be equally distributed across the left and right sides of the box after separation by the semipermeable wall. Assuming equidistribution, the increase in S VN given the spin measurement in stage 2 is N ln 2 (Hemmo and Shenker Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006, 169). Furthermore, the decrease in thermodynamic entropy in the fourth stage is N ln 2 as well. The entropic accounting therefore seems to work out.
However, Hemmo and Shenker press further on the ‘rough’ nature of equidistribution when N is large but finite: they claim that the change in S VN will only be N ln 2 when N is infinite, since equidistribution only truly holds when
. In other cases, S VN will strictly only approximate S TD, and hence S VN and S TD combined will never be exactly zero. Hence, “Von Neumann’s argument goes through as an approximation” (Hemmo and Shenker Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006, 169). However, they claim that this state of affairs suggests, instead, that von Neumann’s argument strictly fails: “since Von Neumann’s argument is meant to establish a conceptual identity between the quantum mechanical entropy and thermodynamic entropy, we think that such an implication is mistaken. … No matter how large N may be, as long as it is finite, the net change of entropy throughout the experiment will not be exactly zero” (169). As I have already discussed in section 4.1, it is not clear to me that von Neumann’s goal really was to establish strict identity (what they call “conceptual identity”), that is, correspondence between S VN and S TD in all domains. Rather, it seems to be the establishing of correspondence only in domains where S TD is taken to hold. If so, their argument here simply misses the point.
Furthermore, as is well known, the particle analogue of thermodynamics, statistical mechanics, becomes equivalent to phenomenological thermodynamics only when
, that is, when N arrives at the thermodynamic limit. As such, to complain that S VN does not match up to S TD outside of this domain is to demand the unreasonable, since it is not clear that even statistical mechanics, the bona fide particle analogue of thermodynamics, can satisfy this demand. Since S VN approximates S TD the same way statistical mechanical entropies approximate S TD (and becomes equivalent at
), and physicists generally accept that statistical mechanics corresponds to thermodynamics nevertheless, why should this approximation be particularly problematic for S VN? I think Hemmo and Shenker take too seriously the notion of conceptual identity involved in von Neumann’s thought experiment to be strict equality, although I suspect a better way to understand von Neumann’s strategy is to understand S VN as an approximation to S TD that is more fundamental than S TD in small N cases but becomes part of the S TD calculus in domains where S TD applies.
To have a case against S VN as a quantum analogue of S TD in the case of finitely many particles, Hemmo and Shenker must explain what exactly the problem is with approximations in this case, if it has worked out so well for the case of statistical mechanics and thermodynamics. If not, they might just be “taking thermodynamics too seriously” (see Callender Reference Callender2001).
One might say something stronger: unless they can justify why we cannot use approximations at all in science, they do not have a case at all. As they note themselves, S TD is itself only on average approximately −N ln 2 (Hemmo and Shenker Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006, 169), only being equal to −N ln 2 when
. So, in fact, the approximate quantity of S VN, ∼N ln 2, exactly matches the approximate quantity of S TD, ∼−N ln 2, in the case of finitely many particles. Unless there is something wrong with approximations in physics in general, this, then, is in fact a case of S VN corresponding to S TD, contrary to their argument.
4.4. Infinitely Many Particles
Hemmo and Shenker consider von Neumann’s argument in the infinite-particles case in two different ways: one as
and one as
. As they rightly point out, the two cases are very different for calculations of physical quantities.
Consider stages 2 and 5 in this context. Hemmo and Shenker emphasize that a spin measurement is “a physical operation which takes place in time” (Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006, 170), which constrains what is physically possible. For the case in which
, stage 2 is to be understood as a succession of physical measurements in which “we measure individual quantities of each of the particles separately and only then count the relative frequencies” (170), before coming up with a density matrix describing this state. In this case, as with the case described in section 4.3, S VN approaches N ln 2 as
. Their complaint here consists of two premises: one, that, as with section 4.3, S VN never reaches N ln 2 unless
and, two, that since measurements are physical measurements, we can never perform an infinite series of these measurements, and so we can never measure infinite particles. A fortiori the measurable S VN can never arrive at N ln 2, and so the entropic accounting is again supposed to be inconsistent if we consider both S VN and S TD.
However, it is clear that their argument is moot given an understanding of the sort of thermodynamics we are interested in (see sec. 4.3). While it is true that S VN will never reach N ln 2, recall that S TD (or, more likely, one of its statistical mechanical analogues, given the domain of finitely many particles merely approaching ∞ rather than
) will likewise never reach N ln 2. In other words, it does not matter that we can never perform an infinite series of these measurements and, hence, never come to know of S VN at the thermodynamic limit, since we can likewise never have a thermodynamic entropy equivalent to N ln 2 unless we are at the thermodynamic limit. The two entropies, then, in fact correspond in this case.
What of the second case? Here, Hemmo and Shenker concede that “arithmetically Von Neumann’s argument goes through at the infinite limit” (Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006, 172), which makes sense because, as I have insisted so far, von Neumann’s strategy was never to demonstrate the strict identity of S VN and S TD, that is, the correspondence of S VN and S TD in all domains. Instead, it was to show that S VN corresponds to S TD only in the domain where phenomenological thermodynamics hold, in all other cases merely approximating S TD in large N cases or replacing it altogether (in, e.g., single-particle cases). I maintain that Hemmo and Shenker’s main mistake was to confuse the domain where phenomenological thermodynamics hold with domains where they do not hold.
Hemmo and Shenker complain that “real physical systems are finite. This means that Von Neumann’s argument does not establish a conceptual identity between the Von Neumann entropy and thermodynamic entropy of physical systems. Identities of physical properties mean that the two quantities refer to the same magnitude in the world” (Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006, 172). In line with what I have said in section 4.1, it seems that there was no physically meaningful theoretical term in phenomenological thermodynamics that could refer to some quantity in the single-particle case, which was why von Neumann needed to come up with a new measure of entropy to begin with. Furthermore, extending a concept to a new domain does not require strict identity, as we have seen and understood for a long time in the case of statistical mechanics and phenomenological thermodynamics.
As Peres summarizes: “There should be no doubt that von Neumann’s entropy… is equivalent to the entropy of classical thermodynamics. (This statement must be understood with the same vague meaning as when we say that the quantum notions of energy, momentum, angular momentum, etc., are equivalent to the classical notions bearing the same names)” (Reference Peres2002, 174). ‘Equivalence’ here should not be understood in terms of strict (or conceptual) identity, that is, correspondence at all domains. Rather, we should understand equivalence loosely as correspondence in the suitable domains of application and successful extension of old concepts in these domains to new domains. As Peres noted above, ‘equivalence’ should be understood in the context of discovery, where one is trying to develop new concepts that are analogous to old ones in different domains. For von Neumann, we have a theory (phenomenological thermodynamics) that is well understood but also another theory (quantum mechanics) that we want to understand in light of the former theory. Finding correspondence provides us with ways to extend concepts from the original theory to the new theory: for example, with S VN we may now define ‘something like’ S TD, whereas before there was no way to talk about these cases. The same goes for statistical mechanics: by finding a correspondence between, for example, temperature and mean kinetic energy in the thermodynamic limit, we can extend the notion of ‘something like’ temperature beyond its original domain into systems with small numbers of particles, whereas before there was, again, no way to talk about these cases.
I see nothing wrong in these cases in the context of discovery. We should give up a strong and untenable notion of conceptual identity in this context. If so, Hemmo and Shenker’s objection loses much bite.
They further claim that “the fact that the behavior of the two quantities coincides approximately for a very large number of particles is not enough, because in any ensemble of finite gases there are systems in which the identity will not be true. This means that in a real experiment the Von Neumann entropy is not identical with the thermodynamic entropy” (Hemmo and Shenker Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006, 172). This again reveals a confusion between phenomenological and statistical thermodynamics. If they want to talk about particles at all, it seems they must adopt some form of statistical mechanical picture with microscopic variables, given phenomenological thermodynamics’ emphasis on purely macroscopic variables like volume or temperature. Yet, if so, they must recognize that thermodynamic entropy S TD is in general not strictly identical to statistical mechanical entropy, for example, the Gibbs entropy or information entropy (briefly discussed in sec. 4.2) either. Their complaint about approximate coincidences not being enough for (the relevant sort of) equivalence thus weakens significantly, especially since they must assume some such equivalence (which cannot be strict identity) to even talk about particles within the context of phenomenological thermodynamics to begin with. Furthermore, statistical mechanics is evidently empirically successful in explaining and predicting traditionally thermodynamic phenomena despite this ‘nonequivalence’—it is not clear why this ‘nonequivalence’ should matter if, for all practical purposes, statistical mechanics is the conceptual successor of thermodynamics. Of course, if they could come up with a principled reason why approximations should not be allowed period, while accounting for statistical mechanics’ empirical success in accounting for thermodynamic behavior, then this could change. As of now, I see no such argument forthcoming.
5. Conclusion and Some Open Questions
I hope to have shown that Hemmo and Shenker’s (Reference Hemmo and Shenker2006) argument against the correspondence of S VN and S TD—to my knowledge the only one in the philosophical literature—fails to hold in all three cases considered (secs. 4.1–4.4), as a result of their misunderstanding about domains where phenomenological thermodynamics should hold and domains where it should not. This is compounded with misunderstandings about the role of approximations and the relevant interpretation of density matrices and ignorance in quantum mechanics. I conclude that their argument fails on the whole; the correspondence holds for now.
Of course, even if Hemmo and Shenker’s claims were debunked, this does not yet amount to a positive argument for the equivalence between von Neumann entropy and thermodynamic entropy. Even assuming correspondence, correspondence does not entail equivalence. However, the former does provide good prima facie reasons to believe the latter, especially given the novel take on correspondence I provided in the end of section 3: we can accept the correspondence because of thermodynamic considerations about the Second Law and S TD accounting but also because of quantum mechanical considerations about S VN accounting. The correspondence supports a ‘two-way street’—equivalence—between S TD and S VN.
While I hope to have conclusively refuted Hemmo and Shenker’s argument, this is but the beginning of further inquiry into questions arising from this supposed correspondence. Amid the tangle of entropies, there remains much more housekeeping to be done for philosophers of physics.