Published online by Cambridge University Press: 01 October 2004
Debates over how ideas matter in international relations have come to occupy a key place in the field. Through a reexamination of the thinking of Hans Morgenthau, this article seeks to recover a tradition of classical realism that stressed the role of ideas in both the construction of action and in political and ethical judgment. Locating Morgenthau's understanding of politics against the background of the oppositional “concept of the political” developed by the controversial jurist Carl Schmitt shows how Morgenthau's realism attempts to recognize the centrality of power in politics without reducing politics to violence, and to preserve an open and critical sphere of public political debate. This understanding of Morgenthau's realism challenges many portrayals of his place in the evolution of international relations, and of the foundations of realist thought. However, it is also of direct relevance to current analyses of collective identity formation, linking to—and yet providing fundamental challenges for—both realist and constructivist theories.For helpful and insightful comments on this article in its wide variety of previous incarnations, I would like to thank Michael Barnett, James Der Derian, Randall Germain, Alexandra Gheciu, Stefano Guzzini, Jef Huysmans, Oliver Jutersönke, Jennifer Mitzen, Vibeke Schou Pedersen, and especially Rita Abrahamsen and Richard Wyn Jones. Previous drafts were presented at the 2002 meetings of the British International Studies Association, and at the Department of Political Science and International Studies, University of Birmingham, United Kingdom. My thanks also to the participants at those sessions.
How and why do ideas matter in international relations (IR)? For at least a decade this question has been at the center of IR theory. Constructivists, liberal institutionalists, poststructuralists, Gramscians, structural realists, and neo- or postclassical realists have all debated the importance of ideas, and while there is now some agreement among these competing positions that ideas matter, there is little consensus on precisely why or to what extent they do so.1
This article seeks to contribute to these ongoing discussions by exploring a position that has been notably absent within them: that of classical realism. I argue that a reengagement with classical realism reveals a tradition of thinking that provides a subtle and sophisticated understanding of the role of ideas in IR. Recovering this strand of thought questions many conventional portrayals of the foundations of realism and its place in the evolution of IR, but its implications also go beyond disciplinary history, raising fundamental philosophic, analytic, and normative challenges to contemporary IR theory.To recover this strand of classical realism, I reexamine one of its most significant proponents: Hans Morgenthau. At first glance, this may seem a particularly inauspicious place to start, for while Morgenthau's status in the development of realism remains unquestioned,2
See Donnelly 1995, 2000; Buzan 1996; Grieco 1997; Jervis 1998; Kahler 1997; Bucklin 2001; and Haslam 2002.
Philpott 2001, 62–63.
Morgenthau 1967, 27.
For an excellent discussion of this context, see Hanssen 2000.
One of the clearest illustrations of the continuing relevance of Morgenthau's thinking lies in its relationship to contemporary debates over collective identity formation. It has been argued with increasing frequency that constructivist analyses of collective identity formation provide a potential common ground of engagement between realism and constructivism, extending realist insights into both relations between states and the activities of nonstate groups.6
Jervis 1998, 988, 989.
If turning to Morgenthau seems at first glance an inauspicious place to uncover the role of ideas in classical realism, then in many eyes looking at his concept of politics may seem a doubly unpromising point of departure. Indeed, however diverse the positions in contemporary IR may be, there is almost universal agreement that one of the greatest weaknesses of Morgenthau's thinking (and that of immediately postwar realism in general), lies in its remarkably narrow understanding of politics. While liberal institutionalists,7
social constructivists,8Lapid 1996.
There is little doubt that Morgenthau proposes a very constricted vision of politics. In Politics Among Nations, for example, he argues that “a nation is not normally engaged in international politics when it concludes an extradition treaty with another nation, when it exchanges goods and services with other nations, when it cooperates with another nation in providing relief from natural catastrophes, and when it promotes the distribution of cultural achievements throughout the world.”12
Morgenthau 1967, 26.
Rosenberg 1994, 24.
Explanations of the narrowness of classical realism's understanding of politics abound in discussions of IR, and form a key element in accounts of the evolution of the field. Most commonly, it is traced to the historical conditions of realism's ascendance, particularly to the dominance of “high politics,” diplomacy, and military conflict at the conclusion of World War II and the onset of the Cold War.14
See Holsti 1998, 135; Katzenstein, Keohane, and Krasner 1998, 652; Kegley and Wittkopf 1999, 28–34; and Vasquez 1998, 45–59.
Katzenstein, Keohane, and Krasner 1998, 658.
Rosenberg 1994, 24.
Yet the narrowness of Morgenthau's realist understanding of politics can also be seen as posing a particularly intriguing puzzle. As a series of recent studies have revealed, a closer look at Morgenthau's intellectual biography sits uncomfortably with his adoption of such an obviously naïve and simplistic view of politics. Trained in the complexities of legal and state theory spanning thinkers from Hans Kelsen to Otto Kircheimer, Morgenthau was personally engaged in the highly politicized legal struggles of Weimar Germany and was well aware of the complex relationship between law, institutions, culture, and politics.18
See Amstrup 1978; Frei 2001, 48–49, 114–44; Koskenniemi 2002, 413–509; and Scheuerman 1999, 225–51. On the broader legal context, see Dyzenhaus 1997 and Scheuerman 1994.
See Morgenthau 1933; Frei 2001, 118–19, 160–63; Honig 1996; Huysmans 1998; Koskenniemi 2002; McCormick 1997, 303–5; Pichler 1998; and Scheuerman 1999.
Seen in this light, it hardly seems likely that Morgenthau could have been oblivious to the fact that he proposed an extraordinarily constricted—in fact, largely counterintuitive—view of the political realm; and it seems equally difficult to avoid the view that the conventional explanations of this narrowness seem suspiciously easy. I suggest that rather than being the result of historical constraints, philosophical myopia, or methodological strictures, Morgenthau's narrowing of the political sphere is not an oversight. Rather than ignoring the obvious breadth of political life or the complexity of the concept of “the political,”23
See Ebata, Neufeld, and Beverley 2000; and Edkins 1999, xi.
In unravelling the nature of politics in Morgenthau's realism, it is useful to begin by noting the strong emphasis he places on the importance of the concept of politics, and on the autonomy of politics as a sphere of action and understanding. In what is perhaps the most oft-quoted phrase in the history of IR, Morgenthau's “second principle of political realism” holds that its core lies in the definition of politics as “interest defined in terms of power.” “This concept,” he argues, is crucial if one is to make sense of international politics, for it
provides the link between reason trying to understand international politics and the facts to be understood. It sets politics as an autonomous sphere of action and understanding apart from other spheres, such as economics (understood in terms of interest defined as wealth), ethics, aesthetics, or religion. Without such a concept a theory of politics, domestic or international, would be altogether impossible, for without it we could not distinguish between political and nonpolitical facts, nor could we bring at least a measure of systematic order to the political sphere.24
Morgenthau 1967, 5.
Yet despite the almost iconic status that “interest defined as power” has assumed in presentations of realist theory, a close examination of Morgenthau's discussion quickly reveals that power and interest are actually remarkably flexible and indeterminate concepts. The forms taken by interest and power, and the relationship between them, are fluid and only foundational in the broadest possible sense. In his “third principle of political realism,” for example, Morgenthau discusses this fluidity in terms worth quoting at length. Realism, he argues,
does not endow its key concept of interest defined as power with a meaning that is fixed once and for all. The idea of interest is indeed the essence of politics and is unaffected by the circumstances of time and place….Yet the kind of interest determining political action in a particular period of history depends upon the political and cultural context within which foreign policy is formulated. The goals that might be pursued by nations in their foreign policy can run the whole gamut of objectives any nation has ever pursued or might possibly pursue.25
Ibid., 8–9; emphasis added.
The objects of “interest,” it turns out, are almost limitless. Literally anything could in principle be an interest. A similar indeterminacy applies to power. As he puts it:
The same observations apply to the concept of power. Its content and the manner of its use are determined by the political and cultural environment. Power may comprise anything that establishes and maintains the power of man over man. Thus power covers all social relationships which serve that end, from physical violence to the most subtle psychological ties by which one mind controls another. Power covers the domination of man by man, both when it is disciplined by moral ends and controlled by constitutional safeguards, as in Western democracies, and when it is that untamed and barbaric force which finds its laws in nothing but its own strength and its sole justification in its aggrandizement.26
Ibid., 9.
At this point, a degree of confusion might seem appropriate, for these extremely broad visions of power and interest seem logically to lead not to a narrow conception of politics, but to an extremely broad one.27
For a criticism of this breadth, see Claude 1962, 25–37. For a discussion of how Morgenthau's view of power has been adopted in different ways by different contemporary realists, see Legro and Moravscik 1999, 22–34; and for its significance in the debate over realism and the end of the Cold War, see Wohlforth 1995, 9–10.
A theme suggestively explored by Ashley 1984. Good, critical surveys of “power” in international relations are put forward in Guzzini 1998, 218–22; and Barnett and Duvall forthcoming. More broadly, see Hindess 1996.
Broadly speaking, Morgenthau's definition of politics as “interest defined as power” has been given two interpretations in IR theory, neither of which comes fully to terms with the complex position he stakes out. The first of these interpretations tends to reduce realism to a form of materialism. Here, both interest and power are defined primarily in material—and particularly military—terms, and international politics becomes characterized as a struggle for material power. As Mearsheimer succinctly put it in an oft-quoted statement of this theme: “Realists believe that state behavior is largely shaped by the material structure of the international system.”29
Mearsheimer 1995, 91. For an innovative recasting of materialism, see Deudney 2000. A very useful survey is found in Guzzini 1998, 133–35.
The adequacy of this materialism as the foundation for the study of IR has been a source of continual debate within the field and is often presented as marking a fundamental divide between realists and their critics—particularly social constructivists who stress the importance of ideational phenomena.30
However, as evidenced in the definitions of power and interest cited above, a reduction of “interest defined as power” to predominantly material forms of each clearly does not do full justice to Morgenthau's realist understanding of politics. Confirmation of this point is provided by Morgenthau himself, who felt the need to stress the role of diverse forms of power precisely because of the tendency to reduce power to its material aspects. As he put it in a discussion of his revisions to the fourth edition of Politics Among Nations: “Against the misunderstanding of the central element of power, which, after having been underrated to the point of total neglect, now tends to be equated with material strength, especially of a military nature, I have stressed more than before its immaterial aspects, especially in the form of charismatic power, and have elaborated the discussion of political ideologies.”31Morgenthau 1967, ix.
The question of the specificity of politics is also important when considering the second common interpretation of realism. In this view, the definition of politics as “interest defined as power” is seen in essentially instrumentalist terms: if power is a necessary means for the pursuit of interests, then power becomes an end in itself. As a necessary instrument to the achievement of any given interest, power itself becomes a universal interest and, therefore, as Ruggie summarizes this view, “whatever the ends that leaders may seek to achieve, their doing so is mediated and constrained by all states deploying their power to pursue their own ends, so that power itself becomes the proximate end of any state's foreign policy.”32
Ruggie 1998, 4–5.
On the surface, an instrumentalist interpretation of realism seems more satisfactory; and it certainly captures the open-ended and multiple character of interests and power more fully than does a reductionist materialism. However, in reducing realism to a form of instrumentalism, this view also fails to account for the specificity of politics, and to address the question of why politics constitutes the autonomous sphere that Morgenthau insists it does. If the definition of politics is “interest defined as power,” and power is just an instrument for the achievement of other interests, then what differentiates the political sphere from any other realm of social life in which power is essential to the successful pursuit of a given interest? In the economic sphere, for example, the pursuit of economic power is essential for the acquisition of wealth. But if this is the case, what is unique about the political sphere as opposed to that of the economic, and why does Morgenthau explicitly differentiate the political from the economic sphere? In short, if the pursuit of any interest requires power, and power becomes an end in itself in any sphere of social life, then “interest defined as power” applies equally to all social spheres and ceases to be uniquely useful as a concept for distinguishing political phenomena from other forms of social interaction. Politics, accordingly, would again become an extremely broad sphere, not a conspicuously narrow one. While an instrumentalist definition may tell one something about the realist stress on power as a means to the realization of interests, it fails to specify what is distinctively political about the sphere of politics in realist theory.
On closer examination, the most prevalent understandings of politics in Morgenthau's realism fail to come to terms with either its conceptual specificity, or to explain his remarkably limited definition of the sphere of politics. Similarly, neither explanation provides a satisfactory account of the relationship between power and interest that is at the heart of Morgenthau's realist conception of politics. These considerations seem to leave open two possible options. From one perspective, they might be seen as still further evidence of the inadequacy of realism, and yet another reason to consign it firmly to the theoretical (pre)history of IR. A second position, however, is to take these apparent inconsistencies as inspiration for a deeper investigation of the realist vision of politics. Taking this path requires a broader engagement with philosophical roots, intellectual lineage, and political context underlying Morgenthau's realism. At the heart of this context is Morgenthau's debt to the social theory of Weber, his fundamental engagement (again shared with Weber) with Nietzchean philosophy, and his engagement with the political consequences of this legacy as they were expressed within the tumultuous setting of Weimar Germany. When placed in these contexts, Morgenthau's realist concept of politics and the remarkably narrow definition of political phenomena that he develops emerge as sophisticated and self-conscious attempts to deal with the relationship between politics, power, and violence.
While it has for some time been common to see Morgenthau as standing within a tradition of realpolitik initiated by Weber,33
Smith 1986.
As Morgenthau wrote autobiographically, “Weber's political thought possessed all the intellectual and moral qualities I had looked for in vain in the contemporary literature inside and outside the universities.” Morgenthau 1977, 7. For broader treatments, see Barkawi 1998; and Pichler 1998.
The most straightforward element of this limitation lies in the influence that Weber's philosophy of social science had on Morgenthau. Weber's method of ideal-types had sought to provide a means of classifying different social spheres according to their specific logics. By distinguishing these spheres (as ideal types) the analyst can abstract specific logics of action from the totality of social life and then examine how they struggle, interpenetrate, and fuse in the production of concrete practices, as for example, in Weber's classic analysis of the role of radical Protestant morals and aesthetics in the rise of the economic logic of capitalism.35
Weber 1958.
Part of the narrowness of the concept of politics is, therefore, an analytic device: an attempt to specify politics as an ideal-type as referring particularly to structures of governance. Yet it is clear that this designation alone is not enough to account for conceptual specificity of politics or its delineation as an autonomous sphere. If the focus of the political realist is on how a particular policy increases, for example, the “power of agriculture,” there is no exclusive connection between this and governmental structures. Nor is it clear why this political sphere should be separated from, for example, cultural spheres that support particular interests: for instance, a belief in the importance of rural agriculture in maintaining national identity. Once again, the defining concept of the political realist—interest defined in terms of power—appears strangely amorphous and ill-defined. It seemingly applies to almost any actor, any interest, any form of power, in any given sphere. It either depends on a content that is smuggled in after the definition (interest as the “national” interest, or power as “governmental” power), or to be completely lacking in content.
Coming to terms fully with the specificity of politics requires a further appreciation of how the roots of this concept lie not in Weber's methodology, but in his political philosophy and the Nietzschean aspects of that philosophy.37
The Nietzchean roots of Morgenthau's thinking have been comprehensively documented in Frei 2001. The links between Nietzche and Weber are nicely outlined by Owen 1994; see also Turner and Factor 1984.
Or as Morgenthau phrased the theme in terms of international politics: “Nations meet under an empty sky from which the Gods have departed” Morgenthau 1967, 249.
Viewed negatively, politics is essentially “struggle” … the “striving to share power or striving to influence the distribution of power, either among states or among groups within a state.” … Viewed positively, however, politics involves relating individual value rationalities to group choices, implying that recognition of persons together with processes of discussion, argumentation, and consensus lie behind exercises of power. Political actions are a distinctively human kind of social action: they combine instrumental and value rationality, and thus develop and express what Weber conceives as the human potential for teleological action and self-determination.39
Warren 1988, 35.
Politics is thus identified by its specific duality: an indeterminacy that makes it at one and the same time a realm of power and inevitable struggle and a realm of openness and self-determination. For Weber, the maximization of the positive potential entailed by this value relativity required a differentiation and separation of value spheres at both the conceptual and the social levels. To quote Warren: “Weber does not seek one set of value criteria to ground all others because he sees cultural progress in the differentiation of value spheres, none of which are primary and each of which has its own distinctive kind of rationality and criteria or propriety. This is true for economics, aesthetics, erotic life, language, intellectual life, social life, and so on. Each sphere is necessary for a fully human life, and it would be inappropriate to universalize the standards of one sphere to all others. One does not judge art by logical consistency, love by utility, or righteousness by efficiency.”40
Ibid., 38; Warren here follows Habermas 1984.
Warren 1988, 31.
Seen in light of this Weberian heritage, the specificity of politics in realism becomes clearer. Power and struggle are intrinsic to human life. Politics is the sphere of contest over the determination of values and wills—an undetermined realm in which the struggle for power and domination is pure (without content) and thus potentially limitless. The specificity of the political sphere thus lies in power as an interest in itself. Politics, as an autonomous sphere, has no intrinsic object of interest; it is literally lacking in any concrete “interest” except the pursuit of power. This indeterminacy stands in contrast to other social spheres that possess concrete interests, forms of power, and limits that politics does not; for example, the economic sphere has a specific logic of interest (material gain) and a dominant form of power (control over material resources) that define its operation and give it a particular set of limits. Paradoxically, it is the unlimited nature of politics that is the basis of its conceptual specificity, and the basis of the distinction between the political sphere and other social spheres.42
This point is also stressed by Frei 2001, 126–28 especially; see also Hobson and Seabrooke 2001, 269.
Yet the essential emptiness of politics also represents its promise and positive potential. The quest for power without a fixed interest leaves those interests open to transformation and revision and is, thus, the condition of change and progress. As a realm without a fixed interest, politics becomes the sphere of activity uniquely concerned with the consideration, generation, and transformation of common interests and understandings: the sphere where the fundamental meanings and values of social life are contested and determined. The lack of fixed understandings of the good and the true is the condition of modern politics, and the basis of its distinctiveness as a realm of freedom, creativity, and change.
Morgenthau shares this understanding of politics. Politics, in principle, has no limits—it lacks defined objects of interest or resources of power. Its limits lie only in the confrontation between divergent wills, interests, and the forms of power they can wield. To return to Morgenthau's illustration of “nonpolitical” issues cited at the outset of this article, both legal (extradition) and trade relations are not political because they are conducted within largely shared and settled structures of agreement on the appropriate norms, rules, and procedures. The political struggle for power—the struggle over foundational principles, values, and so on—does not prevail in these relations (unless one actor is explicitly using them to these ends). By contrast, because it has no specific object to govern its interests or its potential forms of power, politics is an almost limitless field of struggle and domination. As Morgenthau repeatedly makes clear, the conceptual specificity of politics applies across all political realms; at this level, there is no fundamental distinction between domestic and international politics. The primary difference between the two lies in the social resources—institutional and ideational—available for the limitation of the negative logic of politics, and the exploitation of its positive capacities. As he puts it, “The essence of international politics is identical with its domestic counterpart,” a symmetry “modified only by the different conditions under which this struggle takes place in the domestic and the international spheres.”43
Morgenthau 1967, 32.
This recognition allows one to make sense of Morgenthau's claim that as an ideal-type purely “political” man would be a “beast”: as a sphere without content or limits, politics is potentially a remarkably destructive dimension of human action.44
Ibid., 13.
The limitless nature of politics is thus the source of both its perils and its possibilities.46
Similarly, history is neither pure continuity, nor pure change. Rather, the enduringly empty nature of politics—its radical indeterminacy that is part of its constant struggle for power—represents both its unchanging nature and its capacity for change. The affinities between Morgenthau's views and Nietzche's conception of history as “eternal return” are striking here. For an insightful analogous discussion, see Der Derian 1998.
Contrast to the positions surveyed in Rosecrance 2001, that lead him to ask, “Has Realism Become Cost-Benefit Analysis?”
In Morgenthau's thinking, this realist strategy of limitation develops along three dimensions. First, he defines politics and political power as separate from other forms of power, particularly physical violence. This provides the basis for a limitation on the legitimate use of violence within the sphere of domestic politics. Second, he seeks to foster the development of other social spheres whose forms of interest and power can balance those of politics, minimizing the attraction of its violent potential and counteracting its capacities. Third, he attempts to insulate these spheres from each other. The spheres of morality, law, and economics must be insulated against the intrusion of the logic of limitless domination characteristic of politics, while the openness of the political sphere must be defended against its subsumption within these other spheres. In actuality, these structures and strategies of limitation will always be partial, and political practice will always involve the interpenetration of different spheres and the struggle between them. But this interpenetration must always take place against the background of their basic separation, a separation that is essential for the operation of an ethical and balanced political order.
The obvious dilemma accompanying Morgenthau's famous claim that “all politics is power politics” is that it risks reducing politics to nothing but a struggle for power, and rendering the application of any and all forms of power and coercion equally legitimate in the struggle. Indeed critics have long claimed that this is the logical conclusion of realist theory: that ultimately might equals right. However, Morgenthau's limitation of the concept of politics represents, in fact, an attempt to respond precisely to this dilemma. In the context of Weimar, these were not abstract questions. The reduction of politics to violence and the assertion of its essential—even defining—role in politics was found across the political spectrum.48
McCormick 1997, 31–82.
As Scheuerman has superbly demonstrated, an engagement with Schmitt's thinking constitutes a continuing “hidden dialogue” within Morgenthau's thought.49
Scheuerman 1999. Morgenthau had confronted Schmitt's arguments explicitly in an early and detailed critique, see Morgenthau 1933. See also the excellent analysis in Koskenniemi 2002, 413–509.
Schmitt [1922] 1985, 32.
Ibid., 13. I have tried to trace dimensions of this legacy within contemporary securitization theory in Williams 2003.
The political, correspondingly, was defined by the social conditions under which such sovereign acts of decision became viable. The essence of this condition lay in the basic division between those who belonged to a political order and those who did not; a distinction that was ultimately one between friend and enemy.52
Schmitt [1932] 1996.
For Schmitt, the politics of the enemy are not normative.53
A key ambiguity must be noted here, for while Schmitt often presents the concept of the political as simply “objective,” it has often been argued that his vision is actually underpinned by a vitalistic commitment to violence and enmity as essential for the preservation of a “full” human life in opposition to the neutralization and depoliticisization of liberal modernity. On Schmitt as an exponent of a conservative vitalism, see Wolin 1992; for an excellent discussion in international relations, see Huysmans 1998.
This is one element of his critique of Weimar liberal-democracy, explored most fully in Schmitt [1926] 1985.
Morgenthau's thinking clearly bears the marks of his engagement with Schmitt. As discussed earlier, his understanding of politics as an undetermined realm of pure will reflects a similar position (and Nietzchean-Weberian heritage) on the specificity of politics, and he shares the view that the essence of sovereignty lies in the capacity for decision.56
Morgenthau 1967, 307–25.
As noted earlier, Morgenthau views democracy as based on the claim that there is no fixed idea of the right or the good, and that this openness is, paradoxically, itself the principle of democracy. Democracy, he asserts outright, is based on a “relativistic philosophy” and a “relativistic ethos” that is paradoxically protected by “certain absolute objective principles which legitimize majority rule but are not subject to change by it.”58
Morgenthau 1970, 40–41.
On some readings this is Schmitt's position as well, but these issues are beyond the scope of this article.
Morgenthau 1967, 490.
These concerns are clearly expressed in Morgenthau's distinction between political power and military power. “When we speak of power” he argues, “we mean man's control over the minds and actions of other men. By political power we refer to the mutual relations of control among the holders of public authority, and between the latter and the people at large.”61
Ibid., 26.
Ibid., 27; see also Frei 2001, 127–28.
The affinities to Arendt's position in particular are clearly illustrated here.
Seen in this light, the narrow definition of politics and its clear delineation from other social spheres is not only analytically or methodologically driven; it is a part of a comprehensive political philosophy. Equating political power with physical violence would violate the autonomy of the political, reducing it solely to one of coercion and thus destroying the autonomy of politics. By defining politics narrowly, Morgenthau seeks to distinguish the forms of power appropriate to politics, to limit their legitimate exercise within the political sphere, to insulate the political sphere to the greatest degree possible from other forms of power, interest, and domination, and to ensure that the openness and capacity for change that is the promise of politics is not foreclosed by the domination of the interests and power structures of other spheres. The conceptual specificity—and thus narrowness—of politics is part of an attempt to justify a political practice in which the indeterminacy of the political sphere is understood in both its positive and negative dimensions.
However, the effectiveness of this strategy requires more than just conceptual clarity concerning the specificity of the political. As Morgenthau was well aware, ideas alone are rarely powerful enough to prevail in social life;64
Morgenthau 1967, 326.
The idea of a balance of power and interest is justifiably recognized as a key theme in realism. In light of the argument above, however, it takes on a significance much broader than the narrow focus on the interstate balance of power that has so dominated discussions in IR. For Morgenthau, the idea of a balance of power and interest is as complex and vital at the domestic level as it is at the international. Indeed the two are closely linked. A balance of power at the domestic level supports a politics of limits that, in turn, supports a limited foreign policy and provides a more solid basis for a balance of power at the international level.
Here the conceptual distinctions find a social expression and a political meaning. Distinct social spheres (economic, legal, moral, aesthetic) operating within their specific logics and forms of power can act as limits on the logic of politics and on the reach of the political sphere. While actors in these spheres may be tempted to further their interests and power by dominating the political field, these actors will also resist attempts by the political sphere to encroach on their autonomy, and vice-versa. What results is a social balance of power and interests in which the existence of nonpolitical spheres provides limits on an interest in politics and generates forms of interest and realms of power with an interest in maintaining politics as a limited sphere. In short, the idea of politics as a distinct sphere is linked to a strategy of balancing social spheres and interests against one another to limit the reach of politics while also limiting the influence of other spheres on the political.65
See also the excellent treatment of Weber in Hobson and Seabrooke 2001, 262–64. Indeed Morgenthau even allows that should these other forces become dominant, they can cause a nation to cease to act “politically,” and a nation's engagement in international “politics” may wane whereby “under the impact of cultural transformations, which may make a nation prefer other pursuits, for instance commerce, to those of power.” Morgenthau 1967, 26.
Yet this strategy of balancing contains a crucial paradox, and a vitally important corollary. In conditions of modernity, the processes of social differentiation must be balanced against their anomic and alienating consequences. In broad historical terms, the capacity for the individual exercise of power through a faith in the ultimate power (and judgment) of God that was a key plank in the moral economy of Christendom, providing even the most oppressed with a feeling of power. The breakdown of this moral economy of interest, along with the corresponding decline of cross-cutting and competing aristocratic hierarchies, destroyed the internal balance of power (and source of limitation) characteristic of feudal and early modern states.66
These (Nietzschean and Tocquevillean, respectively) themes are important in Morgenthau's explanation of the classical balance of power and its breakdown, most fully discussed in Morgenthau 1946. The Nietzchean elements are explored in Frei 2001, 112–20; the Tocquevillian in Ruiz 1995.
Morgenthau 1967, 100. For an insightful recovery of Morgenthau's views on human nature, see Koskenniemi 2002, 445–55.
For Morgenthau, this process was at the core of the rise of fascism. As a philosophy that rejected a politics of limits, which identified the essence of the political with violence, conflict, and the casting of Others as enemies, and which sought to inject this logic as broadly as possible in a process of social mobilization, fascism represents the ultimate social expression of an unbounded politics. In a passage worth quoting at length, he argues:
Thus National Socialism was able to identify in a truly totalitarian fashion the aspirations of the individual German with the power objectives of the German nation. Nowhere in modern history has that identification been more complete. Nowhere has that sphere in which the individual pursues his aspirations for power their own sake been smaller. Nor has the force of the emotional impetus with which that identification transformed itself into aggressiveness on the international scene been equalled in modern civilization.68
Morgenthau 1967, 104.
While the existence of separate spheres and diverse forms of power and interest blunts the possibility of unified social expression of the will to power within the political sphere, it can also be the source of an (unlimited) political logic, giving rise to an international system of endemic and almost irreconcilable conflict. The logic of politics becomes merged with patterns of violence and enmity and extended destructively to all aspects of life, becoming the dominant logic of society as a whole and making its foreign policy wholly one of domination and conflict.
Morgenthau's concern with social balances, with playing off competing interests and limiting the political sphere, has clear affinities with liberal theories of the state, and he makes no attempt to conceal his admiration for liberal and republican systems of checks and balances at both the domestic and the international level.69
Ibid., 164–67. In this way, Morgenthau's thinking has important links to republican traditions of thought explored in Deudney 1995 and Onuf 1998. Morgenthau's realism is also thus subject to sophisticated critiques of liberalism, which would allow for a fuller engagement between realism and other schools of IR and political theory.
A point of considerable relevance to contemporary theories of the “democratic peace” that focus on the importance of institutional checks and balances.
The nation of the “new nationalism,” he argues, has dissolved the tension between morality and power by subsuming both under its own universalizing desires: the “nation, deeming itself intellectually and morally self-sufficient, threatens civilization and the human race with extinction.” Morgenthau 1967, 60.
A position Morgenthau shared with E. H. Carr.
This is also true of the technologization of politics that would lead to a loss of belief and commitment in politics in itself. In this, Morgenthau agrees with Schmitt that the economic realm as one of material calculation and technical manipulation is not the same as the unlimited creative realm of the political. But unlike Schmitt, he does not ascribe to a vitalism in which all other spheres are devalued in contrast to this indeterminacy. Morgenthau's views on the technologization of politics are most clearly found in his first (1946) and last (1977) works in English. On Schmitt's views, see especially McCormick 1997.
Morgenthau's conception of politics is not, therefore, just an analytic device: it is a moral and political project. Long-standing claims that his realism eschews morality, reduces freedom to determinacy, ignores domestic politics, and denies the possibility of progress are badly mistaken. This is not to say that his thinking is without difficulties. Taken in purely analytic terms, for example, his theory of distinct social spheres is certainly susceptible to many of the criticisms commonly levelled at Weberian-inspired methodologies. In particular, his presentation of separate social spheres as defined by specific logics—of economics solely with material gain, or eroticism as wholly with romantic love—risk obscuring rather than clarifying concrete practices. The economic and the romantic, for instance, were rarely far apart in the dynamics of dynastic marriage,74
My thanks to Vibeke Schou Pedersen for this example.
By contrast, claims about processes of “de-differentiation” are, of course, central to many postmodern analyses.
Yet it is also important to note that Morgenthau does not assume that these categories and social spheres are natural or given. On the contrary, he is aware that they have evolved as separate spheres through a series of historical struggles and conflicts. The autonomy of religion, for example, developed as a consequence of the political-religious conflicts of the Thirty Years' War, while the division between politics and economics reflects the class struggle in which the rising bourgeoisie came to supplant the aristocracy.76
Morgenthau 1946. Again, this theme is also pursued in Schmitt [1932] 1996; it is detailed historically in the Schmitt-influenced analysis of Koselleck 1988.
More importantly, however, Morgenthau's commitment to these categorical distinctions is more than just analytic: it is driven by a desire to maintain politics as an ethical principle or regulative ideal, and thereby to judge the extent to which it is capable of performing its role as an autonomous public sphere.77
See Morgenthau 1960; and Goodnight 1996. For a very good analysis of the classical realists' (including Morgenthau) concern with American political culture, see Rosenthal 1991.
Morgenthau 1970, 13–39.
This may also help explain the oft-debated shift from Morgenthau's early work (with its extremely broad conception of politics) to his “American” writings, which advocate an extremely narrow view. On the surface, this seems to mark either a contradiction or a fundamental transformation in his position. In my view, however, it marks a shift in political judgment. The undifferentiated vision of politics as “intensification” (1933) is transformed into a practical judgment seeking to limit the sphere of politics in full consciousness of its intrinsically unlimited (and therefore potentially destructive) nature, and yet to defend a political sphere of (democratic) indeterminacy and limits. For a different, more instrumentalist, reading of Morgenthau's shift, see Wong 2000. My thanks to Oliver Jutersönke for an interesting discussion on this issue.
Placing Morgenthau's thinking in this broader context reveals a philosophic and political lineage often ignored in treatments of realism today, and challenges many—perhaps most—contemporary views about the foundations of realism and Morgenthau's place in the development of IR. Yet a recovery of this strand of realism is of more than just historical interest. It also has important implications for contemporary realism, and for IR theory more broadly. In this section, I explore some of these implications by looking briefly at a question that has come to occupy a prominent place in recent debates, that of collective identity formation. From the perspective of Morgenthau's realism, to open up the issue of collective identity formation is inescapably to open questions of ethics and requires an assessment of the relationship between political analysis, judgment, and action. These convictions sit uncomfortably, to say the least, with contemporary notions of analytic objectivity and social scientific responsibility that continue to stress the strict separation of fact and value, and that tend to dominate the positions of rationalists and many realists, as well as being at the center of debates over and within social constructivism. Indeed one of the most significant challenges arising from a reengagement with Morgenthau's realism lies in its claim that this vision of analytic neutrality is not a mark of scientific responsibility but is potentially a contribution to political irresponsibility.
In recent years, it has become increasingly common to claim that realism has clear affinities with (usually constructivist) theories of collective identity formation. Jervis, for example, holds that “Realism points to the reciprocal relationship between identities and conflict, arguing that conflict both grows out of and stimulates the perception of group differences,” and that “Social psychologists have long known that perceptions—and misperceptions—of what people have in common often grow out of conflicts as internal unity is gained by seeing others as the Other.”80
Jervis 1998, 988–89.
Thayer 2000.
Sterling-Folker 2002, 84. For innovative recent treatments of realism and identity construction, see Mitzen 2003; and Murray 2003.
Mercer 1995, 241.
Ibid., 230.
Yet Mercer's analysis also provides perhaps the clearest illustration of the contemporary importance of Morgenthau's concern with the relationship between conceptual clarity and political judgment. As Mercer acknowledges, the claim that individual-group identity formation processes are prior itself requires explanation. Indeed a careful look at his analysis reveals that the process of identity formation is underpinned by a more basic set of claims about the nature and role of concepts and categorizations in individual identity formation. “Categorization” or the “cognitive requirement for simplication,” he argues, is a “necessity” in social life and action. Categorization in turn involves comparison, and it is this necessary relationship between concepts and categories that ultimately explains the inescapably anarchic nature of intergroup relations. In light of its significance for the argument I have pursued above, this outcome is worth quoting at some length. As Mercer puts it: “Categorization explains comparison. When we categorize, we accentuate similarities within our group and differences between groups. Creating categories demands comparisons. These intergroup comparisons are not evaluatively neutral. Because our social group defines part of our identity, we seek to view our group as different and better than other groups on some relevant dimensions. In short, categorization is a cognitive requirement that demands comparisons; the motivational need for a positive social identity leads to comparisons that favor the in-group.”85
Ibid., 242.
It is precisely these kinds of arguments, however, that motivate Morgenthau's detailed engagement with conceptual analysis and its contribution to political judgment and action, and it is in light of their consequences that his otherwise seemingly abstruse concerns with the concept of politics are clearly revealed. As I have shown, Morgenthau would deny neither the importance of conceptual constructions in action, nor the power of dichotomous or oppositional renditions of them. However, he argues that such understandings are radically and dangerously incomplete, potentially transforming claims about the nature of concepts into a claim about the nature of politics. It is exactly this move that Morgenthau finds in Schmitt, and it was precisely in an attempt to oppose an oppositional logic of identity formation—of politics as defined by the inescapable opposition of friend and enemy—that he develops his concept of politics. For Morgenthau, conceptual clarity is essential because it makes possible the political judgment that this stark form of division is not necessary and underwrites a responsible political opposition to it.
The importance of this issue can be brought out by looking at the question of judging actual political practices and strategies of identity formation. If, for example, the process of collective identity formation is necessarily oppositional, how is one to evaluate political strategies that seek consciously to manipulate and mobilize in-group/out-group animosities in the pursuit of political power? This poses directly the question of what it means to be a realist: if realism is the theory of power politics par excellence, does this mean that the height of political realism lies in the mobilization of social capacities and political power by casting Others—whether they be states or other collectivities—as enemies?
Recent attempts to link realism and collective identity formation have tended to shy away from these considerations in favor of an analytic neutrality. Thus, in Mercer's formulation: “The application of SIT to international politics suggests that we are stuck in a self-help system. It does not show, however, that war, conflict, and misery are natural and inevitable products of international politics. National leaders can pursue policies that increase their neighbours' and their own security…. They can do what they want; their competition can be either cooperative or coercive.”86
Ibid., 252.
Sterling-Folker 2002, 85.
This neutrality and indeterminacy is not without attractions, and these positions insist that division need not yield violent opposition. However, this neutrality is less satisfactory politically, for it begs the question of how (indeed if) such conceptions of realism are able to make judgments about—and take political stances toward—xenophobic political strategies. Morgenthau, by contrast, did not shy from a consideration of these issues. As I have shown, it is scarcely surprising that he did not do so, for his thinking was formed in an historical and political context where extreme formulations of in-group/out-group relations were linked to extremely violent political strategies at both the domestic and international levels, and where the ability to make judgments about those strategies was an essential element of political responsibility.
Morgenthau was well aware of the power of oppositional formations (and conceptual logics) of collective identity, of the need to recognize clearly the different social resources available for exploiting the positive potential of politics in these situations, and of the grim conclusions that might necessarily have to follow in the absence of those resources.88
See, for example, Morgenthau's remarks on the relationship between rules, “social forces,” and the definitional and decision-making role and capacity of the state in a realistic vision of international law. Morgenthau 1962, 303.
As Morgenthau's engagement with Schmitt clearly demonstrates, he did not feel that the analyst could be wholly neutral in regard to the dynamics of collective identity formation and a politics of enmity. While it was essential to recognize objectively the dynamics and power relations involved in collective identity formation, and the intrinsic relationship between politics and power, it was equally essential to develop an ethical and evaluative stance toward these dynamics. If realism was not to descend into a crude realpolitik, and if a recognition of the centrality of power in politics was not to result in the reduction of politics to nothing more than power and violence, critical judgment was essential. To focus solely on an “objective” representation of existing practices in the name of social scientific method and a desire to avoid the intrusion of normative considerations in analysis is not a vision of political objectivity, nor of responsibility, that Morgenthau's realism could support.
Morgenthau's realist analysis of the concept of politics is part of an attempt to generate the “particular types of social practices” that might act to mitigate violent conflict and encourage nonviolent engagement. The idea of politics as a positive value—yoked to a principled commitment to a social balance of power designed to foster that openness and offset its negative potential—is a strategy to defend the positive potential of politics as a practical ethos, and to defend the public sphere as an arena for critical, pluralistic engagement. Power can certainly be generated by enmity and division; indeed this may be one of the most effective tactics of all, and one of the key strategies of power is to foreclose the political sphere and to limit debate through the mobilization of oppositional identities. But, for Morgenthau, one of the core commitments of a realist theory of international politics lies in a resistance to this process,89
See, for example, Ibid., 36–78, and Morgenthau 1970, 13–39.
These issues also speak directly to controversies within contructivist theory, particularly those between “conventional” and “critical” constructivists.90
See Adler 1997; Der Derian 2000, 77–83; Hopf 1998; and Price and Reus-Smit 1998; for links to realist criticisms, see Mearsheimer 1995, 92; and Jervis 1998, 974.
The idea that the world is comprised of nothing but competing constructions, and that the sole task of “objective” analysis is to describe these as best it can, would mean that the question of whether those constructions and conventions are positive or destructive would be by definition unanswerable. There would, for example, be little reason why Schmitt's mythological politics of enmity in all its destructive dimensions would in principle trouble a “positivist” constructivism if a mirroring of the operation of such a politics is all that social constructivism entails. Without a critical, ethical, and evaluative dimension, a focus on the social construction of practices risks becoming politically irresponsible, and stands in stark contrast to the deeply politicized understanding behind Morgenthau's apparently simple definition and delineation of politics.
Seen in this light, the concerns found in Morgenthau's conception of politics resonate (admittedly somewhat paradoxically given his status as a prophet of “power politics”) with a series of important moves to address the political and analytic consequences of a constructivist position. Wendt's stress on the importance of reflective judgment and the transformative potential opened up by the relational nature of identity, for example, could be seen as evoking many of the same concerns with the positive possibilities of the political sphere, and his recent questioning about “what is IR for?”91
Wendt 2001; it also links back to the important analysis in Ashley 1981. On the realist commitment to political criticism, see especially Rosenthal 1991, 141–76.
See Edkins 1999; and Walker 1995. On the ethics of identity, see particularly Campbell 1998; and Neumann 1999. For an interesting overview, see Shapcott 2001. The links between elements of poststructuralism and classical realism have also been noted by Guzzini 1998, 228; and Rengger 2000. For a detailed survey of the connections between important strands in American intellectual history and contemporary thought, see Diggins 1994.
There are certainly many different ways to assess what Gilpin called the “richness of the tradition of political realism,”94
Gilpin 1986.
See, for example, Wæver 1998, and the positions of Copeland 2003, Desch 2003, Glaser 2003, and Little 2003 in a symposium on “American” realism.
To answer the question “is anyone a Realist anymore?”96
Legro and Moravscik 1999. This article brought a raft of replies from self-declared realists (Feaver 2000), but the diversity of these responses was as intriguing as their individual arguments, prompting their collection under the revealing (and perhaps ironic) subtitle: “Was Anyone Ever a Realist?”
Der Derian 1997.
Wæver 1996.
Morgenthau's strongest critique of rationalist social science is, of course, in Morgenthau 1946.
Finally, this analysis also supports recent calls for a deeper engagement between IR and fields of political and normative theory from which it has too often, and often in the name of realism, been severed. Taking seriously Morgenthau's concept of politics and the philosophical and political lineage from which it emerges places realism within the orbit of some of the most vibrant contemporary debates in contemporary political science and social theory, ranging from the shifting nature of “the political” in political theory, to the contribution of historical sociology to IR, to the relationship between the social construction of political action (and its analysis) and the question of political responsibility. One of the most paradoxical outcomes of a deeper engagement with the narrowness of Morgenthau's realist concept of politics may thus lie in its contribution to a broader analytic agenda in IR, and a richer theoretical dialogue between the field and the rest of political science.