Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-s22k5 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-11T05:08:18.735Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The non-existence of private self-regulation in the transnational sphere and its implications for the responsibility to procure legitimacy: The case of the lex sportiva

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 September 2014

KLAUS DIETER WOLF*
Affiliation:
Peace Research Institute Frankfurt (PRIF), Baseler Strasse 27–31, 60329 Frankfurt am Main, Germany
*
*Email: wolf@hsfk.de
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article is a critical examination of the claim that the emergence of private self-regulatory regimes in the transnational sphere signals a new trend of self-constitutionalization outside the limits of nation-state based or intergovernmental control. It deals with the question to what extent the diffusion of public authority in the sphere beyond the state affects the responsibility of the state(s) to procure the legitimacy of such private self-regulation. First, a conceptual argument is developed which identifies private self-regulatory regimes as rule systems nested in a specific constitutional order of the international society, here described as ‘neo-Westphalian’ (Section I). Second, implications for the responsibility to procure the legitimacy of collectively binding regulatory functions performed by private actors in the sphere beyond the state are considered (Section II). Often cited as a model example of autonomous societal self-regulation, the lex sportiva renders particularly strong plausibility for the claimed non-existence of purely private self-regulation. The regulation of performance-enhancing substances can serve to demonstrate the complex interactions between multiple public and private sites of constitutional authority (Section III). In conclusion (Section IV), I argue that, although the ultimate responsibility for providing legitimacy continues to lie with the state/world of states, the political order of the international society as construed in neo-Westphalian terms provides a dispersed and fragmented constitutional-style legal framework with few reliable guarantees that states are capable or willing to enact their background role. Therefore, a substantial part of the burden of – initial – legitimation must be carried by those directly involved in private self-regulation by constituting and exercising public authority.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2014 

Introduction: Global governance as ‘retreat of the state’?

This article is a critical examination of the claim that the emergence of private self-regulatory regimes in the transnational sphere signals a new trend of constitutionalization, located ‘outside the institutionalized political sector, in the “private” sectors of global society’ (Teubner Reference Teubner2012: 2) and outside the limits of nation-state based or intergovernmental control. This claim is a cornerstone of the project of a ‘transnational societal constitutionalism’ (see Teubner Reference Teubner and Teubner1997, 2010, 2011 and 2012) which aims at the reconceptualization of constitutional sociology and can be understood as a particularly far-reaching representation of constitutional pluralism.Footnote 1 It relates to the observation that the ongoing transnationalization of regulatory functions, such as rule-making, implementation and monitoring, is taking place within a global institutional architecture which lacks any centralized equivalent to the constitutionalizing state at the domestic level. The spontaneous and barely coordinated mushrooming of transnational private regulatory regimes is interpreted as a process of the self-constitutionalization of the transnational private sphere, decoupled from state-based constitutionalization, and adding up to a global, albeit fragmented constitutional order in its own right (Teubner Reference Teubner2011: 192). The merits of this view clearly lie in extending the notion of social control to the exercise of public authority by private organizations and institutions (Sciulli Reference Sciulli1992: 2001). While I do agree with Teubner that ‘transnational spheres are not constitution-free’, although ‘an equivalent of the constitutional subject of the national state is not so easily recognizable at the transnational level’, and that states have always ‘respected a certain autonomy of social sub-constitutions’ (2012: 6, 8–9), his claim of an ‘independent constitutionalization of autonomous social orders’ (2012: 17–18) does, however, over-emphasize the internal dynamics of transnational societal constitutionalization and tends to downplay the degree to which it is embedded in a political order of the international system in which state-based institutions have the ultimate authority to determine the scope of their own powers, to allocate constitutional functions to other bodies and to guarantee that acts of transnational private self-regulation ‘are justifiable in light of the constitutional norms recognized as playing a constitutive role for the establishment and exercise of public authority’ (Kumm et al. Reference Kumm, Lang, Tully and Wiener2014: 2). It sees heterarchy where there is hierarchy, and it does so because it mistakes lack of capability and willingness for lack of sovereignty.

Whether transnational private self-regulation takes on constitutional functions within or beyond the reach of an (inter-)state-based international order is not a purely academic question. It is of crucial importance for the extent to which the responsibility to procure the legitimacy of public authority exercised by private self-regulatory regimes can be shifted off to the private regulators themselves or still can be guaranteed by some kind of state involvement (Wiener et al. Reference Wiener, Lang, Tully, Poiares Maduro and Kumm2012: 3). To answer this question, I will proceed in two steps. First, a conceptual argument is developed which qualifies the idea of constitutional pluralism by identifying the emerging self-constitutionalization of private self-regulatory regimes in the transnational sphere as rule systems nested in a specific constitutional order of the international society, here described as ‘neo-Westphalian’. This concept differs from the idea of a global constitutional state as well as from a statist sovereigntist conception of global constitutionalism (Loughlin Reference Loughlin2014). Second, the implications of this ‘neo-Westphalian’ understanding for the responsibility to procure the legitimacy of the exercise of authority is discussed based on the claim that private transnational governance is not so private after all, but, in principle, taking place under the omnipresent shadow of public regulation which gives ultimate validity to private self-regulatory regimes (see Abbott and Snidal Reference Abbott, Snidal, Mattli and Woods2009; Börzel Reference Börzel2010). Here I will argue that, although the ultimate responsibility for providing democratic legitimacy continues to lie with the state/world of states, in practice the involvement of state actors and state-based international institutions does not guarantee a sufficient standard of legitimacy. Therefore, a substantial part of the burden of – initial – legitimation must be carried by those directly involved in private self-regulation by constituting and exercising public authority.

The governance perspective on international relations highlights the ‘explosion of transnational regulation outside the intergovernmental realm’ (Papadopoulos Reference Papadopoulos2013: 1) and the ensuing need to recalibrate the relationship between the state and non-state actors.Footnote 2 The concept of global governance is a persistent reminder of the fact that politics has long since ‘migrated away’ from the political institutions of the state and is now also happening elsewhere, for example, in highly diverse forms of transnational private self-regulation. During the past 20 years we have witnessed a growing transnationalization of global governance arrangements and, going along with that, a rise of ‘private authority’ in the sphere beyond the state (see Mathews Reference Mathews1997; Cutler, Haufler and Porter Reference Cutler, Haufler and Porter1999; Baumgart-Ochse et al. Reference Baumgart-Ochse2012: 1; see also Hall and Biersteker Reference Hall, Biersteker, Hall and Biersteker2002). When states share their regulatory authority with non-governmental organizations, business actors and international organizations, this diffusion of public authority entails a power shift as well as a role shift (Leibfried and Zürn Reference Leibfried and Zürn2005; Wolf Reference Wolf, Scherer and Palazzo2008). By the setting, implementation and monitoring of rules governing international affairs, such as exercising public authority through private law-making, non-state actors perform regulatory functions that were traditionally in the responsibility of the state or intergovernmental bodies.Footnote 3 The claim of a complex interplay among public and private forms of ordering, however loosely coupled, has been repeatedly stated, but more systematic research is needed to clarify how exactly they overlap or are interconnected (Knill and Lehmkuhl Reference Knill and Lehmkuhl2002; Wolf Reference Wolf, Scherer and Palazzo2008; Schuppert Reference Schuppert2011a) in order to gain a better understanding of the nature of the ‘neo-Westphalian’ political order.

The governance perspective also draws attention to the normative implications of the diffusion of public authority from the state to private actors (Börzel and Risse Reference Börzel, Risse, Grande and Pauly2005; Dingwerth Reference Dingwerth2007; Wolf Reference Wolf and Niesen2012a). While the pooling of public and private problem-solving resources may promise to increase effectiveness, the legitimacy of non-state actors supporting or – in the form of private self-regulation – even replacing regulation by the state or by intergovernmental institutions is viewed more critically because of the shift away from state-based institutional settings which, at best, can be held accountable by democratic procedures, to private governance arrangements which lack these instruments to hold them accountable (Graz and Nölke Reference Graz and Nölke2007). The legitimacy concerns raised against transnational private self-regulation are accentuated by the responsibility shift that is assumed to go along with the observed role shift and further specifies the normative ‘questions relating to the establishment and exercise of legitimate public authority’ (Kumm et al. Reference Kumm, Lang, Tully and Wiener2014: 3) at stake here. To what extent does the diffusion of authority in the sphere beyond the state affect the responsibility of the state/world of states to procure the legitimacy of private self-regulation? What makes public authority exercised by private actors in the sphere beyond the state legitimate authority? Are transnational private self-regulatory regimes justifiable in the light of the norms that are generated and implemented by way of private self-constitutionalization and that determine the manner in which public authority is to be exercised, or in the light of constitutional(izing) rules provided by a state-based political order of the international system? Seen through this normative lens, the ultimate question is about the direction in which the further development of the international political order should go if certain standards of legitimacy are to be met.

Like power shifts, shifts of responsibility have attracted the attention of IR scholars primarily from a state-centred perspective, as the vast and still growing literature on the responsibility to protect impressively confirms. There is a remarkable discrepancy between the broad debate on the responsibility shift from the state to intergovernmental, or supranational institutions of the international society of states to protect individuals from the human rights violations that are inflicted upon them by individual governments (see among many others: Bellamy Reference Bellamy2009; Ki-moon Reference Ki-moon2013), on the one hand, and the comparatively little research on the diffusion of responsibility that goes along with the shift from the public to the private sphere, on the other. The literature about ‘corporate social responsibility’ (CSR) is a major exception. It sheds light on the increasing number of transnational, cross-company and cross-sector self-regulatory initiatives, by which environmental, employment, human-rights, and anti-corruption norms and standards are being established and enforced by non-governmental actors (see among others Scherer and Palazzo Reference Scherer and Palazzo2008; Flohr et al. Reference Flohr, Rieth, Schwindenhammer and Wolf2010; Ougaard and Leander Reference Ougaard and Leander2010; Deitelhoff and Wolf Reference Deitelhoff, Wolf, Risse, Ropp and Sikkink2013). These initiatives provide a particularly clear illustration of the new interplay between public and private actors in the collaborative execution of public functions. The CSR debate extended the range of corporate responsibilities and raised the bar for defending corporate activities as legitimate (Koenig-Archibugi Reference Koenig-Archibugi2004; Börzel and Risse Reference Börzel, Risse, Grande and Pauly2005; Buchanan and Keohane Reference Buchanan and Keohane2006; Dingwerth Reference Dingwerth2007; Flohr et al. Reference Flohr, Rieth, Schwindenhammer and Wolf2010). While, 40 years ago, the activities of commercial enterprises could readily be justified by reference to Milton Friedman’s tenet that the sole social responsibility of businesses was to make a profit and stay within the law whilst doing so (Friedman Reference Friedman1970), now, as self-regulators rather than mere addressees of public regulation, businesses are expected to assume more extensive responsibilities (Haufler Reference Haufler2001; Ruggie Reference Ruggie2013).

But how far does this responsibility shift actually go? Does it also burden private self-regulators with the responsibility to procure the legitimacy of their contributions to global governance while at the same time unburden the state of this responsibility? Such a ‘retreat of the state’ (Strange Reference Strange1996) could result in undesirable legitimacy gaps. It is the cogency of this shift of the burden of justification onto private actors once they assume functions by which public authority is constituted or exercised, and the simultaneous unburdening of the ‘natural’ addressees of such requirements – namely states – which will be scrutinized in what follows here.

We shall begin by asking whether private self-regulation in the transnational sphere really is private self-regulation in the sense of ‘governance without government(s)’. For only if it is would non-governmental actors be left as sole bearers of responsibility in procuring the legitimacy of the public authority constituted and exercised by them (Section I). A typology will be drawn up of the forms in which the public sphere shadows private regulatory activity to demonstrate that purely private self-regulation, with no state involvement or support, does not exist in the constitutional frame provided by what will be identified as the ‘neo-Westphalian’ political order of the international system. What appears as a ‘retreat of the state’ will be reinterpreted as a new division of labour between public and private norm-setting and norm-implementation. This has implications for the attribution of the responsibility for meeting legitimacy demands on transnational private self-regulation. In order to clarify the substance and extent of this responsibility we shall consider what normative yardsticks, if any, can be called into service to assess these demands (Section II). An empirical case will then demonstrate the embedment of the private constitution and exercise of transnational public authority in a political order in which state-based institutions review constitutional functions fulfilled by private actors. The case of sports law has been selected for two reasons, which follow the article’s main line of argument. As an unlikely case, often cited as a model example of autonomous societal self-regulation, the lex sportiva renders particularly strong plausibility for the claimed non-existence of private self-regulation. Furthermore, and on closer inspection, the regulation of performance-enhancing substances can serve to illustrate the legitimacy procuring potential, but also the limits of the complex sharing of responsibilities between governments, international organizations and a transnational private self-regulatory regime. It shows how dispersed the loci are from which state-based institutions can fulfil their constitutional role in one thematic field alone, and reflects the fragmented setting of the ‘neo-Westphalian’ order, which is not a global constitutional state, but consists of a plurality of political and legal arenas and intergovernmental agreements. From these, a set of central constitutional norms can be derived with reference to which requirements for, and sources of, the legitimacy of the constitution and exercise of public authority by private actors in the transnational sphere can be assessed (Section III). Lastly, more general conclusions are derived from this empirical case regarding ways in which public and private actors can interact to increase the legitimacy of the exercise of public authority constituted by way of private self-regulation (Section IV).

I. How far does constitutionalization via private self-regulation actually go and where does this leave the state? A neo-Westphalian frame of reference

For a better understanding of the implications of the diffusion of authority for the locus of the responsibility to procure legitimacy for private self-regulation in the transnational sphere, we will take a closer look at the change in roles and the new division of labour between public and private norm-setting and norm-implementation. The main argument is that public authority exercised by private actors is always regulated self-regulation because all transnational private self-regulation takes place in the ubiquitous shadow of actual or potential (inter-) state-based regulation. (On this, see Schuppert Reference Schuppert2001; Abbott and Snidal Reference Abbott, Snidal, Mattli and Woods2009; Börzel Reference Börzel2010; Collin Reference Collin and Collin2011). It rests on a neo-Westphalian understanding of the political order of the international society which is fundamentally distinct from the notion of a (world-) societal self-constitutionalization as ‘global law without a state’ (Teubner Reference Teubner and Teubner1997) or ‘governance without government’ (Rosenau and Czempiel Reference Rosenau and Czempiel1992; Reinicke Reference Reinicke1998; Zürn Reference Zürn1998), separate from the world of states, in which ‘private regimes or rule-systems may operate without the state [and] neither emerge from nor rely on conventional forms of public lawmaking’ (Lehmkuhl Reference Lehmkuhl2008: 340, 342; see also Teubner 2012).

To answer the question where to locate the responsibility for providing legitimacy one needs to know the available candidates first. Here, different perspectives on global constitutionalization offer different answers. Seen from the extreme end of constitutional pluralism, self-regulatory normative orders generated by private self-constitutionalization emerge on an equal footing with institutions whose constitutions have been established through state authority while ‘each acknowledge the legitimacy of every other within its own sphere’ and ‘none asserts or acknowledges constitutional superiority over another’ (MacCormick Reference MacCormick1999: 104). The neo-Westphalian perspective differs from this assumption of private and state-based rule systems co-existing in non-hierarchical relationships.Footnote 4 It claims that the transnational rule systems that have been established and enforced by private actors are always embedded in a global political order which is still anchored in the inter-state system but transcending the political sphere of the world of states. The ultimate authority to allocate (and withdraw) constitutional functions to other bodies rests within the world of states rather than with those (i.e. private self-regulators) who constitutionalize ‘their own sphere’.

Although state-based in regard to identifying the bearers of ultimate constitutional authority, the neo-Westphalian frame of analysis is not static. It takes into account developments which have been described as ‘transformations of the state’ or as ‘de-nationalisation’ (Leibfried and Zürn Reference Leibfried and Zürn2005) and which have resulted in the pluralization of loci and levels at which statehood functions can be exercised unilaterally (by nation states) but also collectively (in inter-/supranational bodies). In contrast to the notion of a (global) constitutional state it implies a ‘thin’ concept of constitution, relying on the existence of constitutional(izing) rules which are not embodied in one single document but in a plurality of international agreements. Thus the neo-Westphalian perspective de-links constitutionalization from the idea of a (national or global) constitutional state as its centre and regards the institutions in which states exercise their ultimate constitutional authority as being widely scattered over different levels and sectors of governance. In this regard it is heterarchical.Footnote 5 This political order provides a ‘rudimentary’ constitutional framework for which only the world of states is in charge but which not only regulates inter-state relations via international self-regulation but also constitutes the only locus of competence in regard to the allocation of regulatory competencies to other – e.g. private – actors. In this regard it is hierarchical. Possession of this competence marks a fundamental distinction between the members of the world of states and the members of the world of transnational business or civil society. There may be different – in this case public and private – sites of constitutional authority, but there is also a clear hierarchy among them.Footnote 6

The self-regulation projects of private norm-entrepreneurs have, without a doubt, resulted in a proliferation of loci of norm generation. But even if the establishment of private regulatory regimes in the transnational sphere goes beyond the scope of material regulations, in the sense of Hart’s (Reference Hart1961) primary rules or Kooiman’s (Reference Kooiman and Pierre2000) first-order norm-production, and also includes constitutional(izing) rules (‘rules for rule-making’), these loci lie within the shadow of a higher-order body of regulations/regulatory powers at the inter-state level and do not seriously call into question inter-state competence in the matter of the creation of the conditions for such private norm-production. Hence, what in the broadest sense of constitutional pluralism is alleged to develop ‘naturally’ (Teubner Reference Teubner and Teubner1997) in fact takes shape not in a worldwide pre-constitutional ‘state of nature’ but within the constitutional framework of the political order of the society of states within which the transnational production of norms by private actors is embedded. In this set-up, states are still actors – the only actors – with the ultimate competence to grant or deny authority and regulatory competence to non-state actors (on an essentially unilateral basis internally and multilaterally between each other). Within the ubiquitous shadow of possible (inter-) governmental control states can – at least in principleFootnote 7 – intervene at any moment to determine the conditions governing private norm-production.

This neo-Westphalian understanding, rather than distinguishing between ‘governance by, with and without governments’ (Zürn Reference Zürn1998: 169–71), highlights the way in which the one sphere is embedded in the other, how the two are related, and how they impact upon one another. In this respect, the transnational sphere is much more diverse than the intra-state sphere, where private legal entities may ‘lay down self-determined private rules within a framework delineated by state legislation’ (Mätzler Reference Mätzler2009: 144). The new ways in which public guarantor-responsibilities are discharged – ways that cannot really be comprehended on a narrow view of legal-style leverage – cover a broad spectrum that can range from restrictive pressure (compulsion, prohibition), through background support (acceptance, recognition) to encouragement (de-regulation, initiation). A variety of motives are reflected here, including ‘protection of endangered rights’ (through intervention), ‘protection of exercised rights’ (through recognition) and ‘reducing the burden on the state’ (through approval).

The public ‘shadow of hierarchy’ in which private self-regulation takes place may appear in a variety of roles and manifestations. A distinction can be made here between laissez-faire, reactive and proactive forms of public involvement in, and influence on, private self-regulation. These are set out in Table 1.

Table 1. Variants of state embedment of transnational private self-regulationFootnote 8

This classification of the types of public–private interaction involved in transnational private self-regulation comprises both direct forms of involvement and less visible channels of state influence. In no case, however, do we have a situation where the state disappears completely from governance, or indeed where states/the world of states irreversibly disempower themselves. The following illustrations demonstrate that even in cases where the state, or the institutions of the world of states, keep their own contribution down to a minimum, in the form of tacit acceptance or deliberate inaction, they still cast a shadow of hierarchy – albeit an almost unrecognizably blanched one – over private self-regulation.

Responsible Care, the ‘world’s leading voluntary industry initiative’, may serve as one example of many to illustrate the state’s/the world of states’ laissez-faire role of non-prevention with regard to a transnational private self-regulatory effort. Responsible Care was originally initiated in 1985 by the Canadian Chemical Producers’ Association. Today, it is managed by the International Council of Chemical Associations at the global level. Its members comprise nearly 60 national chemical manufacturing associations who have committed themselves to promote the observance of environmental and work-related standards and who are responsible for monitoring implementation by the chemical companies in their countries.Footnote 9 The initiative has been and still is tolerated by governments as a private self-regulatory rule-system (Conzelmann and Wolf Reference Conzelmann, Wolf, Graz and Nölke2007). The same is true for the Equator Principles, the global private regulatory framework for environmental and social risk management for project finance (Wright Reference Wright, Biermann, Siebenhüner and Schreyögg2009; Flohr Reference Flohr2014). Its standards for due diligence to support responsible risk decision-making have been adopted by 79 financial institutions in 35 countries.Footnote 10 In both cases of voluntary private self-regulation, individual governments or intergovernmental institutions would have had the authority to step in at any time they decided to do so, but refrained from interference.

Examples for the – supportive or prohibitive – reactive role the public sector can play with regard to transnational private self-regulation are equally abundant. In the case of the official adoption of the environmental, social and economical standards set by the Forest Stewardship Council in order to promote the responsible management of forests (Gulbrandsen Reference Gulbrandsen2004; Dingwerth Reference Dingwerth2007 and Reference Dingwerth2008), the standards of this private transnational self-regulatory initiative have been backed up and explicitly recognized by those governments who subsequently adopted them as their own standards for public procurement. Even states’ or intergovernmental organizations’ reactive legal recognition of norms that have originally been set by private actors is a common practice. For instance, the banking sector’s Wolfsberg Principles to combat money-laundering was incorporated into national law (Wolfsberg Group 2002; Flohr Reference Flohr2014), and so were the food-security norms from the food industry’s codex alimentarius, originally a private initiative, into FAO and WHO agreements. Likewise, the so-called lex sportiva, commonly referred to as a prototype of transnational private self-regulation, has received national and international legal recognition and embedment.Footnote 11

Corrective public interventions or even abrogations of private norm-setting initiatives can be exemplified by the Kimberley Process to stop the trade in conflict diamonds, in which states intervened by enforcing what had started as a private certification scheme in order to ensure that diamond purchases were not financing rebel movements (Grant and Taylor Reference Grant and Taylor2004; Haufler Reference Haufler, Potoski and Prakash2009a and Reference Haufler2009b; Grant Reference Grant, Lujala and Rustad2011; Jakobi Reference Jakobi, Jakobi and Wolf2013). A stronger intervention can be exemplified by the directive the EU set in force in 2009, specifying emission standards for new passenger vehicles after the European automobile industry’s implementation efforts fell short of their own voluntary self-commitments to reduce CO2 emissions.Footnote 12

Proactive forms of influence can vary from ‘soft’ invitations to collective private-self commitments, as in the case of the Global Compact initiated by former United Nations General Secretary Kofi Annan (Kell Reference Kell2003; Rasche and Kell Reference Rasche and Kell2010),Footnote 13 to delegating public functions of norm-setting and norm-enforcement to private actors, as in the case of the Chartered Companies which are also a reminder of the remarkably long tradition of transnational private self-regulation in the shadow of the state (Wolf Reference Wolf, Deitelhoff and Wolf2010).

II. The legitimacy demands of transnational private self-regulation

According to this reasoning we can no longer assume that – because states would have not any part at all in the process – the responsibility for procuring that private regulatory activities meet certain legitimacy demands has automatically passed on to the private actors who have assumed state functions. If there is an omnipresent possibility of backup guarantor or supervisory functions to be exercised, the ultimate responsibility of the state/world of states is at no point revoked, irrespective of how it is, or may be, exercised in practice, for example when governments take to deregulation and privatization.

Having said this, and assuming that this ultimate responsibility of the state/world of states also includes the responsibility to procure the legitimacy of transnational private self-regulation, the next question that needs to be addressed refers to the extent to which the public authority exercised by private actors in transnational self-regulations requires legitimation, and the possible ways in which legitimacy might be procured for it. The strongest rejection of the claim that transnational private self-regulation needs justification in terms of legitimate authority at all starts out from the modes of governance involved in transnational private self-regulation and from a fundamental division between public power and private freedom. Despite the misleading talk of a ‘lex mercatoria’, a ‘lex informatica’, or a ‘lex sportiva’, so it is argued, the modes of governance involved in transnational private self-regulation are located below the threshold of sovereign governance in the sense of exercising state-like legislative or executive power. Within the framework of voluntary commitments, there is no exercise of power in the narrow sense; there is simply use of the right to the collective exercise of individual autonomy. Private standard-setting is interpreted as ‘the free exercise of a fundamental right’ (Michael Reference Michael, Bauer, Huber and Sommermann2005: 435) to freedom of association as a constitutionally protected expression of civil liberty. Different from the generation and enforcement of collectively binding decisions based on the mandatory exercise of the sovereign authority of the state – the exercise of this freedom does not have to demonstrate its democratic legitimacy. The need for legitimation in the case of this classical exercise of state power is – it is claimed – fundamentally different from the need for (public) regulation in the case of ‘non-state self-regulation of public affairs’ (Collin Reference Collin and Collin2011: 8) in which there is a risk of private abuse potentially detrimental to the common good.

According to this view, even the kind of private norm-setting that one comes across within the framework of global governance would not, in principle, need to justify itself. As an instance of the exercise of fundamental rights, it would, in theory, qualify for protection and would only require regulation, if at all, in cases where the exercise of private freedoms accorded at (inter-)national level was damaging to the public good or violated basic laws. The problem of private self-regulation’s need for legitimation would dissolve into that of its need for regulation by the public sector. However, as Michael (2005: 444) has rightly pointed out, ‘the fundamental division between public power and private freedom … cannot be maintained in the case of private standard-setters who utilize a putative freedom to exercise power’. In the transnational sphere, in particular, the dividing lines between the public and the private exercise of power and control merge into one another in a multiplicity of hybrid manifestations of norm-setting and norm-enforcement. Within the framework of global governance, intergovernmental and private transnational rule systems are both often characterized by their voluntarism, informal nature, exclusiveness and self-authorization. In the case of transnational private self-regulation, these problems are magnified rather than minimized because, by making and implementing collectively binding decisions that infringe upon individual liberties, regulatory authority is exercised by actors who as a rule are not democratically accountable to those affected by these decisions. All these characteristics have the potential to breach fundamental rights or to fail to satisfy general-interest requirements, and all exercise of power requires constitutional limits (Poiares Maduro Reference Poiares Maduro, Avbelj and Komarek2012: 75). Transnational private self-regulatory mechanisms must therefore be justifiable in the light of the same constitutional norms recognized as playing a constitutive role for legitimate authority that apply to mandatory rule-making and rule-enforcement by the state. Are regulatory objectives of a socially oriented kind being successfully achieved with an appropriate balance of costs and benefits (criterion of public-interest effectiveness and efficiency)? Are matters of public concern being addressed in a sustained and credible manner (responsiveness criterion)? Do the addressees of regulation, and others affected by it, have ways of successfully influencing the regulatory process (self-determination criterion)? Is it possible successfully to control the exercise of regulatory authority and call its agents to account (accountability criterion)? (On this, see Flohr et al. Reference Flohr, Rieth, Schwindenhammer and Wolf2010: 203–8; Dingwerth Reference Dingwerth2007; Take Reference Take2012).

These questions effectively define the major normative preconditions for determining the nature and extent of public ‘shadowing’ required by transnational private governance contributions: the practical need for public intervention or non-intervention will depend on the extent to which such regulation, in its capacity as an exercise of freedom liable to abuse, has already imposed effective limits upon itself to prevent any damage to the public good or violation of fundamental rights.Footnote 14 Although only regulation by the public sector can link transnational private self-regulation with democratic mechanisms of political legitimation, this interrelatedness at the same time points to a joint (initial) private and (backup) public responsibility. Called upon in its capacity as guarantor, the public sector still holds the ultimate responsibility for procuring the legitimacy of authority exercised in global governance arrangements, including those based on transnational private self-regulation. This it can do, for example, by regulatory measures that incorporate private norm-setting into the constitutional set-up in such a way that the norm-setters, in exercising the freedoms granted to them, do not damage the public good or violate fundamental rights.

However, such expectations in the public sector’s actual capacity as guarantor may prove too high: public ‘shadowing’ by governments or intergovernmental organizations may themselves suffer from legitimacy deficits that their involvement would only pass on. This applies to the level of individual governments – which may not be democratic themselves – as well as to the supra- and inter-governmental level. Two of the examples already used to illustrate the forms and instruments of public influence in Table 1 may suffice to point this out: benchmarks set by the European Union in order to guide the self-regulatory activities of the European associations of the automotive industry with the effect of reducing CO2 emissions suffer from the ‘democratic deficit’ of the EU itself (see among many others Majone Reference Majone1998; Scharpf 1999; Wolf Reference Wolf1999; Moravcsik Reference Moravcsik2002); likewise, the Global Compact initiative of the United Nations Secretary General has no mandate from governments (Ruggie Reference Ruggie2013: xxix). In each case, intergovernmental sources of legitimation would, in their turn, suffer from legitimatory deficits (Moravcsik Reference Moravcsik1994; Wolf 1999) which they would only pass on to the exercise of authority they are supposed to legitimate. The discrepancy between the options that theoretically exist for exerting (inter-)national regulatory influence on transnational private self-regulation and the actual implementation of these options is another reason why the contribution to the legitimation of transnational private self-regulation that may be expected from this kind of collective exercise of state power eventually comes up against its limits. Governments may be unable or unwilling to regulate private self-regulation in order to guarantee that the above-mentioned yardsticks of legitimacy are met.

Therefore, in cases where restrictive national or international public regulation of private self-regulation fails, or is not utilized, or has questionable normative credentials as a procurer of legitimation, external (public) and internal (private) sources of legitimacy need to be combined to ‘compensate for one another’s weaknesses, and play mutually reinforcing roles’ (Abbott and Snidal Reference Abbott, Snidal, Mattli and Woods2009: 46; Ruggie Reference Ruggie2013: 78). Against the background of these multiple accountability relationships within and outside the self-regulatory regime (see Black Reference Black2008: 157) the identification of the internal legitimatory potential of transnational private self-regulation once again becomes of interest as a complementary source of legitimation. Not being capable of democratic legitimation themselves,Footnote 15 functional equivalents could consist in the choice of particular, e.g. deliberative modes of governance whose non-mandatory character would entail a lesser requirement in terms of democratic legitimation. In addition to reducing the need for corrective external intervention by relying on ‘soft’ modes of governance, the establishment and exercise of authority by way of transnational private self-regulation could optimize their own resources for procuring (epistemic) legitimacy, based on technical or moral reputation, of the kind that are available to the economic or civil-society actors directly involved in self-regulation initiativesFootnote 16 and which, in conjunction with particular objects of self-regulation, may be capable of procuring some degree of internal legitimacy (Joerges and Neyer Reference Joerges and Neyer1997; Dingwerth Reference Dingwerth2007; Quack Reference Quack2010; Take Reference Take2012; Wolf Reference Wolf2012b;). Thus the participation of actors with practical knowledge can ensure expert legitimacy first and foremost for self-regulation initiatives involving material regulations – for example, technical standardization. By contrast, the involvement of actors who enjoy widely recognized moral authority as ‘commonweal norm-entrepreneurs’ could enhance the legitimacy, in particular, of private norm-setting initiatives whose functions included securing basic agreement on standards of appropriateness for public-interest activity.

III. The lex sportiva: Self-regulation by sports organizations in the WADC Code

Transnational self-regulation by sports organizations is characterized by the high degree of legislative, executive and judicative authority exercised by private regulators. The sports world’s so-called lex sportiva is, alongside the lex mercatoria, regarded as a model example of autonomous societal self-regulation. As an unlikely case, it is a particularly instructive example to illustrate the claimed non-existence of private self-regulation. Moreover, it exemplifies how dispersed and fragmented, in one thematic field alone, the places are from which state-based constitutionalization takes place in the neo-Westphalian setting. Contestation and justification of private self-regulation in terms of legitimate exercise of authority can best be studied by looking at the self-regulatory regime to prevent the use of performance-enhancing substances in light of the ongoing debate about the need for national anti-doping legislation and athletes’ criticism levelled at the self-regulatory mechanisms for violating basic human rights. Moreover, the dealing with these controversies offers insight into how public and private regulators can interact to procure legitimacy.

Long before the current global-governance discussion about the privatization of cross-border governance, the gradual evolution of private law in the world of sports was being cited as proof that a centralized state monopoly on power was not necessary in order to guarantee ‘public order, co-ordination and public goods’ (Burnheim as early as 1986: 221). Within the autonomous bodies of the sports world, state functions are fulfilled by non-state actors who have the power to lay down binding rules and to impose sanctions where these are violated. The non-state institutions in which this takes place enjoy their own authority whose claim to legitimacy is based on general acceptance by both the public and the actual addressees of the regulations, namely the athletes who make up the sports clubs and associations. An extensive privatization of the law, going well beyond a shift of the state’s monopoly on arbitration to the social sphere, therefore appears to have taken place in organized cross-border sports relations.

Contrary to this view, in what follows I will first go into the interaction between self-regulation and its public ‘shadowing’ in order to show that, even in this allegedly autonomous field, transnational private self-regulation takes on constitutional functions only within the reach of an (inter-)state-based international order which can give ultimate validity to it, or refuse to acknowledge its validity. A balance sheet will then be drawn up based on the four criteria mentioned above (public-interest effectiveness and efficiency, responsiveness, self-determination, accountability). Finally, the interaction between different political and legal arenas in order to deal with problems and deficiencies of the particular approach to self-regulation under consideration will be assessed against the background of two recent controversies about its alleged lack of effectiveness and violation of fundamental rights.

Indeed, virtually every sports association has its own national and international system of rules and arbitral bodies, at the head of which stands the Court of Arbitration for Sports (CAS) in Lausanne. The use of performance-enhancing substances has become one of the major regulatory problems facing sports law. In 1999, in an attempt to tackle this, the World Anti-Doping Agency (WADA) was set up, in the form of a foundation in Swiss law.Footnote 17 The World Anti-Doping Code (WADC) adopted at the second World Anti-Doping Conference in Copenhagen in 2003 came into force in 2004 and is an instructive example of private self-constitutionalization in action. Revisions of the code were adopted in 2007Footnote 18 (World Anti-Doping Agency 2009) and, most recently, on 15 November 2013 at the World Conference on Doping in Sport in Johannesburg.Footnote 19 This second full revision will be effective as of 1 January 2015 (World Anti-Doping Agency 2014).

The WADC represents a strong self-regulatory system by sports organizations to co-ordinate anti-doping measures worldwide. It is based on public authority exercised by non-state actors in non-state institutions. The particular self-regulation involved here in very great measure assumes legislative, executive and judicial state functions and replaces state regulation. With its anti-doping code, the system of control associated with this, and the international Court of Arbitration for Sports, WADA, sponsored by sports associations and the Olympic movement, is not only viewed as the ‘international police-force of high-level sports’;Footnote 20 it also gives the appearance of transcending all (sporting) sectors and acting as private lawmaker and judge. Its legitimatory requirements are further amplified by the fact that private self-regulation in sports seeks to achieve compliance primarily through the numerous sanctions listed in Articles 9 to 12 of the WADA Code (World Anti-Doping Agency 2009: 50–78) and only secondarily, for example, through ‘softer’ forms of governance such as exchange of best practices, or learning processes (World Anti-Doping Agency 2009: 13).

At the same time, the basically private and uniformized core part of this regime is supplemented by a fragmented, non-systematic public part which consists of a number of anti-doping laws at the national level and two intergovernmental conventions and one declaration at the international level. As early as 1989, in its Anti-Doping Convention the Council of Europe had already established ‘that public authorities and the voluntary sports organizations have complementary responsibilities to combat doping in sport’.Footnote 21 Several formulations in Article 4 leave no doubt as to the ‘whip in the window’, i.e. the threat of state regulation, which can count as a strong form of public ‘shadowing’ of the sports organizations’ self-regulatory efforts: ‘Parties reserve the right to adopt anti-doping regulations and to organize doping controls on their own initiative and on their own responsibility, provided that they are compatible with the relevant principles of this Convention’, or: ‘the Parties or, where appropriate, the relevant non-governmental organizations shall make it a criterion for the grant of public subsidies to sports organizations that they effectively apply anti-doping regulations’.Footnote 22 Article 7 entails a long list of measures to be taken by national and international sports organizations, among them ‘to introduce, on an effective scale, doping controls not only at, but also without advance warning at any appropriate time outside, competitions’.Footnote 23 In Article 8(2)(a) the state parties agree ‘to encourage their sports organizations to operate in a manner that promotes application of the provisions of this Convention within all the appropriate international sports organizations to which they are affiliated, including the refusal to ratify claims for world or regional records unless accompanied by an authenticated negative doping control report’.Footnote 24 Such ‘encouragements’ are admittedly weak instruments, but they are backed up by the threat of state regulation and the setting up of a monitoring group (Article 10 of the Anti-Doping Convention of the Council of Europe). To a significant degree the tightened rules for ineligibility by doubling the standard ban for serious doping offences from two years to four years in the revised Article 10.2 of the new World Anti-Doping Code which will come into force in 2015 (World Anti-Doping Agency 2014: 60–1) can be ascribed to the threat of mandatory state regulation.

The second intergovernmental convention was adopted at the 33rd session of the UNESCO General Conference in Paris in October 2005. UNESCO’s International Convention against Doping in Sport was the first-ever unified and globally binding international complex of anti-doping regulations. Largely based on the 2003 version of the WADC, it came into force in 2007.Footnote 25 On the one hand, in its preamble, the UNESCO Convention clearly states ‘that public authorities and the organizations responsible for sport have complementary responsibilities to prevent and combat doping in sport’. In Article 2 (‘Definitions’) it is also made clear that ‘in case of conflict the provisions of the Convention will prevail’. At the same time, in Article 4(1), states parties ‘commit themselves to the principles of the Code’ and, in various articles, to ‘facilitating the task of the World Anti-Doping Agency and anti-doping organizations operating in compliance with the Code’.Footnote 26 Moreover, the UNESCO Convention supplements the WADC with a commitment by the signatory states to institute suitable legal or other anti-doping measures within their own area of jurisdiction, for example against athlete support personnel (Article 9).

This indirect commitment on the part of the states, through the incorporation of private standards into international agreements, complements the shadow which state law casts over transnational private sports regulation with a remarkable ‘counter-shadow’ of private self-regulation over the state (Héritier and Lehmkuhl Reference Héritier and Lehmkuhl2008). This intermeshing of shadow and counter-shadow emerges particularly clearly in Article 22 of the WADA Code (‘Involvement of Governments’): ‘Each government’s commitment to the Code will be evidenced by its signing the Copenhagen Declaration on Anti-Doping in Sport of March 3, 2003, and by ratifying, accepting, approving or acceding to the UNESCO Convention’ (World Anti-Doping Agency 2009: 113). In the Copenhagen Declaration, ‘each participant recognises the role of the Code as the foundation in the world wide fight against doping in sport’ (Article 4.1) and ‘seeks to progressively adapt, where appropriate, their anti-doping policies and practices in sport to be in conformity with the provisions of the Code’ (Article 4.2).Footnote 27 The intention is thus that, via the UNESCO Convention and the Copenhagen Declaration, the signatory governments will indirectly pledge themselves to support the provisions of the privately instituted WADA Code and bring all other state-instituted anti-doping measures into line with it.

Siekmann (2012: 314) accurately describes this as a ‘regulatory hybrid’. However, not one of the sporting world’s international associations owes its existence or its scope for action to an international agreement in which the public sector devolves what were originally state competencies to the private sector or transfers state functions to it. There is therefore neither an officially decreed nor a negotiated instance of self-regulation here. In the absence of a mandate by the state or the community of states, the accepted benchmark when it comes to the exertion of influence by these is freedom of association, which generally enjoys constitutional protection. It imposes clear limits on state intervention and restricts the remaining isolated rights of intervention to the protection of basic freedoms and the rectification of any anti-competitive effects of private self-regulation.Footnote 28

The legal status of the WADA as an entity in Swiss law, and the terms providing for half the WADA budget to be financed from the public purse, in themselves constitute a form of state backup of the regulatory initiatives in the anti-doping sphere.Footnote 29 Decisions of WADA’s sports court – the Court on Arbitration for Sport, CAS – are subject to the laws of the country in which the court is based – Switzerland. CAS awards may be challenged before the Swiss Federal Tribunal, for example, by invoking the so-called public policy exception of the Swiss Private International Law Act.Footnote 30 States may not sign up to the Code. Instead, the anti-doping regulations of the various sporting associations are generally incorporated into international agreements. The sporting associations’ codes were first recognized by the world of states in the Copenhagen Declaration on Anti-Doping in Sport, which was adopted in 2003 at the intergovernmental conference of the same name and was ratified by virtually every state in the world.Footnote 31 By means of this declaration of moral and political commitment, the ratifying states affirmed their commitment to the provisions of the WADA code and undertook both to support their national anti-doping organizations in implementing it and to gear their own anti-doping measures to it. Sporting organizations ‘that are not in compliance with the Code or applicable anti-doping rules adopted pursuant to the Code’ will lose all or part of their state funding. This represents not only a recognition, through juridification, of private standard-setting in (international) law but also, conversely, a self-imposed undertaking by states to adhere to regulation created by private actors.

The upshot of all this is a highly complex interplay of private and public co-regulation, with numerous interactions between, on the one hand, the rules generated, executed and monitored by self-regulation and, on the other, the standards set by national and international law. The ‘autonomy of sport’ plainly only operates within the framework accorded to it by (inter-)national law. However, it is not something conferred ex ante by national law, but the space in which it has been able to develop is one afforded by the state, and it is, in addition, underpinned and backed up by explicit ex post recognition in (inter-)national law. The role of the state must thus be described as ‘laissez faire’ and ‘reactive’ in terms of the types of state embedment distinguished for heuristic reasons in Table 1; it is complementing rather than supplanting. Nonetheless, it is a significant one: ‘National and international legal norms guarantee sport a regulatory power that allows it to set its own rules. Sport is not a state with its own decision-making powers or competence-competence. Its regulatory authority is not inherent; it is a competence derived from states or communities of states’ (Nolte Reference Nolte, Bumke and Röthel2012: 116).Footnote 32

Having substantiated that the state/world of states is still in the game as the ultimate authority, it can also be concluded that the responsibility to procure the legitimacy of the public authority exercised by private self-regulatory regimes has not completely shifted to the sports organizations either. In fact, there is a constant need for some kind of state involvement in the lex sportiva in order to compensate for deficiencies in regard to legitimate authority. To make this clear, we will draw on the criteria which were introduced earlier as playing a constitutive role for the establishment and exercise of legitimate authority, i.e. public-interest effectiveness and efficiency, responsiveness, self-determination and accountability.

Public-interest effectiveness and efficiency

The link between the anti-doping campaign and the common good seems a given in the context of health protection, the merit principle, and equality of opportunity. In its preamble, the WADA Code explicitly describes its purpose ‘to protect the Athletes’ fundamental right to participate in doping-free sport and thus promote health, fairness and equality for Athletes worldwide’ (World Anti-Doping Agency 2009: 11). The value of these objectives is also recognized by the state – for example, when the German government, in its 2010 Report on Sports, describes sport as a cornerstone of social life and as one of the major sources of social capital and public health.Footnote 33 The relevance to the common good which the private regulators ascribe to themselves thus acquires added legitimation from the state.

In trying to assess the effectiveness and efficiency of anti-doping measures, one is first struck by the unintelligibility of the regulatory landscape. Existing alongside the CAS are the judicial procedures of the international sporting associations, not all of which are contractually bound to the CAS and which provide for their own courts of final appeal. Some countries have anti-doping laws, others not. The problem of duplicate competencies is further aggravated by the fact that the WADC has to be translated into national codes – compatible in each case with the law of the respective state – and only takes effect when these are applied at the national level. In this process, varying legal standards are used according to the country involved, to the detriment of a unified application of the rules. The results of all this are legal uncertainty and never-ending procedures as participants engage in ‘forum shopping’ (see also Kotzenberg Reference Kotzenberg2007: 30 and 145; Lehmkuhl Reference Lehmkuhl, Zürn and Zangl2004: 179 and 192).

A further problem in regard to efficiency results from WADC’s weak powers of implementation: so far there is no provision for fact-finding instruments over and above the mechanisms for controlling doping amongst athletes. A major gap results from the fact that the Code does not extend to the athletes’ immediate circle – in other words, their trainers, advisors and physicians. The Code has no power to order searches or confiscations. Furthermore, the existing regime’s focus on athletes as the actual addressees of regulation has neither prevented the widespread use of banned substances nor the growing trade of these substances and the increasing role organized crime plays in this market.

In the recent debate about the need for national anti-doping legislation, the lack of effectiveness of the private transnational rule system for the prevention of the use of performance-enhancing substances plays centre stage. Athletes, as the immediately affected victims of cheating competitors, among critical chief representatives of the World anti-Doping Agency itself, sharply criticize the ineffectiveness of the existing regulatory system, accuse certain sports federations of not taking the combat of doping seriously enough, and call on states to play a more active role therein. Driven by similar concerns, WADA Director General, David Howman, describes the regulatory problem as ‘getting too big for sport to manage’. In regard to the failure to prevent the widespread use of banned substances he explicitly refers to a culture of cheating, to the explosion of the trade of these substances and its links to global organized crime. While sports federations are accused by the anti-doping movement of not doing more than the bare minimum, the state is called upon to control the negative externalities which affect public affairs way beyond sport, such as public health, the economic interests of victims of users of banned substances. ‘Unless we make something mandatory, people won’t do it.’Footnote 34 Public prosecutors and the detection methods of the state are called for to summon witnesses, to conduct searching, to tap telephones, or to confiscate drugs.Footnote 35 While self-regulation may be capable of preventing and punishing ‘dirty victories’ by imposing suspensions and the disqualification of results in an event during which an anti-doping rules were violated, no effective punishment and prevention of ‘dirty money’ is considered possible without the help of the state as the only actor who can protect the interests of affected outsiders (Kauerhof Reference Kauerhof2007: 75). Coaches, agents and physiotherapists whose athletes have tested positive for banned substances are beyond the realms of WADA’s punishment and, as WADA President John Fahey pointed out, only national anti-doping are in a position to ‘catch the cheats behind the cheats’.Footnote 36

The defenders of the legitimacy of sport’s claims to self-regulation predict a bleak future with long public lawsuits. Because sports courts can suspend already in cases of reasonable suspicion, whereas public courts cannot (Kauerhof Reference Kauerhof2007: 73), the former could guarantee a much quicker punishment. Furthermore, as an undesired effect, expensive damage suits brought to public courts against sports’ own courts might influence sports’ courts decisions.Footnote 37 A daunting picture is painted of national anti-doping laws ‘that vary from country to country, and sport to sport, which would be a return to the dark ages of anti-doping and a problem which existed during your time as an elite athlete. It would result in athletes in different sports or from different countries receiving different bans for the same offences, and even worse athletes from the same sport receiving different penalties depending on the country they competed for.’Footnote 38 In this regard the turn to national anti-doping laws could in practice rather be a step backwards if measured against the necessary ‘universal harmonisation’ rightly claimed by the WADA Code’s Preamble (World Anti-Doping Agency 2009: 11).

Self-determination, responsiveness and accountability

The responsiveness criterion measures the legitimacy of a particular regulatory approach by asking how sustained and credible it is in dealing with issues that are of public concern. There is no doubt that, with its ban on doping, the lex sportiva has addressed an issue of public concern in a sustained and credible manner. This remains the case even if the primary motivation for the ban on doping was probably to restore a level playing-field – for the sake of athletes, but also for the sake of their sponsors, following the equally relevant commercialization of sporting activity.Footnote 39 However, there is one ‘equity gap’ here, namely that whilst sanctions can be imposed for violations of the WADC rules, there is no provision for compensation for the disadvantaged co-competitors. This gap is highlighted by Haas (Reference Haas2004) under the rubric ‘justice for victims’. The state could step in to solve this problem by national legislation, but this remedy is likely to produce a new divide because states may turn out to be not equally responsive to this need.

When one considers the individual athletes in their capacity as the actual addressees of the private core part of the regime, application of the legitimatory criteria of self-determination and accountability reveals a number of deficiencies – particularly in the case of self-determination. Thus, prior to any Olympic Games, the International Olympic Committee, the various national sports associations, and all the athletes are required to give undertakings that they will not have recourse to any other means of legal redress, including their national jurisdictions. It is exactly this perceived violation of basic human rights which provoked a call on athletes to sign a declaration challenging the jurisdiction of the Court of Arbitration for Sport in doping cases. The ensuing controversy demonstrates the tension between the protection of the individual’s right to self-determination one the one hand, and the protection of the autonomy of the societal sphere, notably the freedom of association, on the other.Footnote 40 In particular, the 2015 Draft Code’s proposition to double the standard ban for serious doping offences to four years met with harsh criticism as a violation of professional freedom. Defenders of the existing private arbitration system concede that it requires athletes to sign agreements with their respective national sports associations in which they waive their basic civil right to have recourse to national courts in existential issues. But they also point to the ‘voluntary’ nature of this waiver and to the fact that this kind of private arbitration mechanisms is explicitly regulated in the respective code of civil procedure. Even if one is ready to regard a waiver of judicial action in civil matters as unproblematic in principle, because otherwise private dispute-settlement would hardly be possible, the monopoly status of sports associations may still raise legitimacy issues in practice, because it questions the ‘voluntary’ nature of such a waiver.Footnote 41

I share Lehmkuhl’s judgement that the capacity of transnational associations to impose obligations on individual athletes contrasts sharply with the minimal extent to which athletes share in the creation of transnational regulations. Hampered by the lack of transparency in the establishment of transnational rules, their opportunities for participation ‘tend to zero’ (Lehmkuhl Reference Lehmkuhl, Zürn and Zangl2004: 183). Even the voluntary nature of individual consent to the sporting associations’ rules is not regarded as a real counter to the imbalance between, on the one hand, the opportunities open to the regulatory subjects to influence the rules that apply to them and, on the other, the grave consequences of decisions made on the basis of those rules, or even simply of a refusal to submit oneself to the relevant regulatory regime.

However, when independent sports organizations violate fundamental rights they still operate under the shadow of public institutions established to protect these rights. This was made particularly clear by the conduct of the European Court of Justice in a number of cases dealing with individual actions against sporting associations. In what has come to be known as the ‘Bosman ruling’, for example, the European Court of Justice directed that ‘The abolition as between Member States of obstacles to freedom of movement for persons would be compromised if the abolition of State barriers could be neutralized by obstacles resulting from the exercise of their legal autonomy by associations or organizations not governed by public law.’Footnote 42 From this it is clear that one of the major demands on public regulation consists in scrutinizing and monitoring private norm-setting and norm-enforcement for abuse. To ensure their compatibility with fundamental rights and freedoms it is expected to apply the yardstick of national and international constitutional criteria to the structures and rulings of sporting bodies.Footnote 43

IV. Summary and generalizing conclusions

The case of the lex sportiva accentuates the need for new forms of checks and balances to assure that private self-constitutionalization meets certain legitimacy demands. The normative criteria applied here to sporting self-regulation demonstrate that although the latter has taken over many functions normally reserved to state-based political authority, and created extensive legitimatory mechanisms to justify these, it nonetheless remains dependent on a governmental/inter-governmental ‘shadowing’ that ensures a link back to the common good and the rule of law – a link only the state/states can provide. The anti-doping measures enshrined in the WADA code reflect complex interconnections between private self-regulation and the (inter-)governmental political structure in which that regulation is embedded. The exercise of private transnational authority operates in a space afforded by national and international law. The lex sportiva shows how the interaction between existing regulatory arenas who share the responsibility to procure the legitimacy of transnational private self-regulation can improve the legitimacy record of sporting self-regulation. In the realm of sports, this framework has produced hybrid links between private self-regulation and the public fabric in which this is embedded. The spheres of public and private regulation are closely intermeshed – in judicial or arbitration proceedings, for example where sport assumes primary responsibility for ‘prohibiting doping by means of its own system of rules, punishes violations via its own sports-based judicial procedures’ while the state ‘assumes a secondary guarantor function’ by providing a legal framework for this (Nolte Reference Nolte, Bumke and Röthel2012: 8). The functional division of labour between public regulation and private self-regulation in this area is based on the autonomy of sporting organizations, assured by international law and operating within the framework of international agreements. This does not exclude the possibility of norms relevant to sport also being incorporated into (inter-)national laws, or of higher-order inputs to governance also taking place via the self-regulation route. Thus, constitutional-style ‘rules for rule-making’ may very well also form part of transnational private self-regulation initiatives and codes of conducts within sport itself. However, such rules remain subject to public monitoring. A key function is thus retained by the state as the ‘ultimate accountable entity’ (Reissinger Reference Reissinger2010: 21 and 30).

The case of private self-regulation in sports confirms the state’s indispensable constitutionalizing function in guaranteeing a minimum of procedural requirements. Transnational private self-regulation invokes such guarantees on several levels here, among others in relation to support in the area of implementation or in regard to safeguarding the security of affected third parties. In this sense, public guarantee functions and private norm-setting and norm-enforcement can indeed be viewed as interdependent ‘two-way safety-nets’ (Röthel Reference Röthel2007: 763). The observations made here about the (inter-)governmental ‘shadowing’ of transnational private self-regulation corroborate the notion that (inter-)national influence is, in principle, both necessary and possible. When private actors assume public functions this does not unburden the state/world of states of their ultimate responsibility to mitigate the problems of legitimation associated with transnational private norm-setting and norm-enforcement by:

  • integrating the rules generated, executed and monitored by private actors into a national/international legal system that can exert a facilitating, corrective, or prohibitive influence on them in cases where fundamental rights may be violated or public-interest objectives may not be attained (‘external legitimation’)

  • at the same time helping to mobilize the sources of legitimation which private self-regulation has available to it in and of itself (‘internal legitimation’), which it does by –

  • guaranteeing space for the politicization, by society, of the deficiencies of private self-regulation and of its (inter-)national regulation.

The question of what actual combination of these core elements of regulated self-regulation is needed to deal with particular deficits of legitimacy can only be answered on a case-by-case basis. Some generalizing conclusions may, however, also be drawn from the sports world’s self-regulation. The state is still in the game and has a wide range of proactive, reactive and laissez-faire instruments available to it in discharging this responsibility, be it unilaterally or collectively. While, in their constitutionalizing function, the state and the international political order constituted by states, remain the ultimate reference points for procuring the legitimacy of global governance arrangements, a substantial part of the burden of – initial –legitimation can and must be carried by those directly involved in private self-regulation. The need for public regulation depends decisively on the extent to which private self-regulation, as a form of exercise of power open to abuse, takes initial regulatory action in regard to itself or, where appropriate, imposes limits on itself in order to satisfy the legitimatory requirements set out here. Vice versa, this initial regulatory action which can provide private self-regulation with a certain internal legitimacy remains equally indispensable when public regulation by the state/world of states fails because public actors are too weak, unwilling or their interferences suffer from legitimacy deficits themselves. External (public) and internal (private) sources of legitimacy need to be combined to compensate for one another’s weaknesses.

The way in which the lex sportiva is embedded not only in national but also in inter-governmental legal systems highlights the fact that, rather than there being one single place from which the shadow of state hierarchy can be cast across transnational private self-regulation, the levels at which the states/world of states can exert influence may be located in the international or the particular national sphere. How far they will actually fulfil the safety-net functions that fall to them, and under which conditions they will make practical use of the leverage theoretically available to them, is another story. The financial crisis has demonstrated how large this gap can be. Even in the world of sports, there remains a considerable gap between responsibility, on the one hand, and capacity and willingness for meaningful and effective involvement according to the guarantee functions listed above, on the other. Thus the case of the lex sportiva does not only illustrate the omnipresence, but also the limits of public ‘shadowing’ in regard to whether public guarantee functions are adequately exercised or not. Identifying an ‘ultimate accountable entity’ is one thing; putting its responsibility into practice is another. The political order of the international society as construed in neo-Westphalian terms provides a dispersed and fragmented constitutional-style legal framework with little reliable guarantees that states are capable or willing to enact their background role.

A basic consensus about the norms (or institutional ‘software’) that are generally recognized as central constitutional principles may still exist. However, the process of global constitutionalization that is currently going on within the neo-Westphalian setting does not yet reveal a realistic blueprint for a less fragmented, integrally connected and more reliable state-based ‘backup’ architecture (or institutional ‘hardware’) than the presently operating constitutional pluralism for monitoring the public authority exercised by way of transnational private self-regulation. In the meantime we have the postulate of private self-constitutionalization as an entity subject to regulation located in the midst of multiple sites of constitutional authority within a state-based patchwork of constitutionalizing rules that carries the ultimate responsibility to procure its legitimacy but suffers from a lack of instruments to make the state(s) live up to their constitutional responsibility in practice. Rather than being able to offer a ‘grand solution’ I join those who are still on the way to improve the ‘foundation on which grander ‘‘how to’’ proposals can be built’ (Black Reference Black2008: 137).

Acknowledgements

This article is a revised and expanded version of a paper presented at the 54th ISA Annual Convention, 3–6 April 2013, San Francisco. It draws in parts on previous German publications (Wolf Reference Wolf and Niesen2012aReference Wolfand b). The author wishes to thank Kenneth Abbott, Annegret Flohr, Dirk Lehmkuhl, Peter Niesen, Thorsten Thiel and the anonymous referees for their valuable comments on earlier versions.

Footnotes

1 By including private self-constitutionalization this notion goes beyond the largely state-centred debate about constitutional pluralism in inter-national relations which focusses on constitutional questions that arise from the interaction and competing claims between processes of constitutionalization at the level of supranational and international organizations, in general, and the EU and its member states, in particular (see MacCormick Reference MacCormick1999; Craig Reference Craig, Hayward and Menon2003; Avbelj and Komarek Reference Avbelj and Komarek2012; Wiener et al. Reference Wiener, Lang, Tully, Poiares Maduro and Kumm2012; for a critical analysis see Loughlin Reference Loughlin2014).

2 In political science, the governance perspective has become a unifying ‘umbrella’ and a common frame of reference for ever more numerous investigations into new forms of co-performance of public functions by the state, the economy and society working together. The less possible it became for political ‘steerage’ to rely solely on the mandatory, ‘command and control’ based law-making and law-enforcing activity of the state, the greater the interest shown in activating non-state potential for regulation and the keener the discussion about the changing significance of the traditional political procedures and institutions through which public functions were discharged (Pierre and Peters Reference Pierre and Peters2000; Kooiman Reference Kooiman2003; Dingwerth and Pattberg Reference Dingwerth and Pattberg2006).

3 I prefer the term ‘public authority exercised by private actors’ over, e.g. ‘private authority’ (Cutler, Haufler and Porter (Reference Cutler, Haufler and Porter1999)) to highlight the public role which private actors play when they organize in order to exercise collectively binding regulatory functions in the sphere beyond the state. See also Ruggie (Reference Ruggie2004), Zürn, Binder and Ecker-Ehrhardt (Reference Zürn, Binder and Ecker-Ehrhardt2012) or Bogdandy et al. (Reference Bogdandy, Dann and Goldmann2008 and Reference Bogdandy, Wolfrum, Bernstorff, Dann and Goldmann2010).

4 In this sense, Loughlin’s (2014: 17) reference to ‘the fallacy of equivalence’ to which constitutional pluralism is vulnerable is magnified by expanding the view to processes of transnational private self-constitutionalization.

5 See Cohen (2014: 130–3) who also discusses the conflicts that may arise from competing constitutional claims to authority in such a setting.

6 The systematic description of this hierarchy is one thing, criticism of its functioning another. The objection that states lack the actual capacity (or willingness) to exercise supremacy over private transnational regimes is therefore not at issue in this neo-Westphalian account of the status quo of the political order of international society. Rather than participating in the competition for the most attractive cosmopolitan, sovereigntist or pluralist architecture for global governance institutions (on this, see e.g. the recent debate between Reference CohenCohen [2014] and Reference ScheuermanScheuerman [2014] in this journal), the argument presented here is normative only in so far as it starts out from a – hopefully convincing– interpretation of the status quo, which allocates certain degrees of responsibility to different types of actors, and then asks how legitimacy demands can be met despite the inadequacies of the existing order.

7 This qualification reflects the fact that governance often takes place in the context of de facto ‘limited statehood’ (Börzel and Risse 2005) where the shadow of statehood is present, but the state (or an intergovernmental political authority) is either unwilling to provide certain governance function or lacks the resources and capacity for meaningful and effective involvement. This distinction between the potential and the will and capacity of states to regulate is also emphasized by Abbott and Snidal (2009: 57).

8 For a more elaborated version of this table see Wolf (2012b: 194–5).

11 This particularly instructive case will be looked into in more detail in Section III because of the complexity of the way in which it is ‘shadowed’ by the states and intergovernmental institutions.

12 Directive 2009/33/EC of the European Parliament and of the Council of 23 April 2009 on the promotion of clean and energy-efficient road transport vehicles, at <http://eur-lex.europa.eu/LexUriServ/LexUriServ.do?uri= CELEX:32009L0033:en:NOT> accessed 23 October 2013.

13 <http://www.unglobalcompact.org> accessed 23 October 2013.

14 The need for external public intervention in order to bridge remaining legitimacy gaps does not only depend on the legitimatory potential which a particular approach to self-regulation itself possesses and/or the extent to which such internal potential is actually used. It is also determined by a) the degree of legitimation required by the modes of governance applied, and b) whether the sources of authority available to the economic, civil-society, or state actors directly involved in a self-regulation initiative make suitable procurers of legitimacy, taking into account in each case c) the nature of the object of self-regulation.

15 In the same context, Michael (2005: 229) states that ‘private standards require legitimation but are not, by their nature, capable of democratic legitimation’.

16 For problems resulting from the rising demands on expertise required from participants see Quack (Reference Quack2010).

17 <http://www.wada-ama.org/en/About-WADA/> accessed 9 March 2013. The founding body is the International Olympic Committee (IOC) and the Foundation Board comes under the jurisdiction of the Swiss Ministry of the Interior.

21 Council of Europe, Anti-Doping Convention, Preamble at <http://conventions.coe.int/Treaty/en/Treaties/Html/135.htm> accessed 2 April 2014.

22 Council of Europe, Anti-Doping Convention, art 4 at <http://conventions.coe.int/Treaty/en/Treaties/Html/135.htm> accessed 2 April 2014.

23 Council of Europe, Anti-Doping Convention, art 7(3)(a) at <http://conventions.coe.int/Treaty/en/Treaties/Html/135.htm> accessed 2 April 2014.

24 Council of Europe, Anti-Doping Convention, art 8(2)(a) at <http://conventions.coe.int/Treaty/en/Treaties/Html/135.htm> accessed 2 April 2014.

26 UNESCO, International Convention against Doping in Sport, Preamble, arts 2, 4 and 16 at <http://www.wada-ama.org/en/World-Anti-Doping-Program/Governments/UNESCO-International-Convention-against-Doping-in-Sport/> accessed 10 March 2013.

27 Copenhagen Declaration on Anti-Doping in Sport, Article 4; at <http://www.wada-ama.org/Documents/World_Anti-Doping_Program/Governments/WADA_Copenhagen_Declaration_EN.pdf> accessed 30 April 2014.

28 See also Haas (Reference Haas2004) and Reissinger (2010: 135).

30 The grounds on which a CAS arbitration award may be set aside by the Swiss Federal Tribunal are formulated in arts 190(2)(a)–(e) of the Swiss Private International Law Act. They include awards that are ‘incompatible with public policy’ (art 190(2)(e)). For the strict approach of the Federal Tribunal as to what actually counts as a violation of public policy in its judicial review see, for example, its decision on the ‘Pechstein’ case in 2010 (Voser and Meier Reference Voser and Meier2010). In its landmark decision on the FIFA vs Matuzalem case in 2012 the Swiss Federal Tribunal for the first time annulled a CAS award on substantive law and not on procedural law (Judgement of the Swiss Federal Tribunal 4A_558, 27 March 2012; Levy Reference Levy2012: 35).

31 <http://www.wada-ama.org/en/World-Anti-Doping-Program/Governments/Copenhagen-Declaration-on-Anti-Doping-in-Sport/List-of-signatories/> accessed 10 March 2013.

32 For a similar assessment see Haas (Reference Haas2004) and Mätzler (2009: 144).

34 <http://www.theguardian.com/sport/2013/feb/15/drugs-wada-organised-crime> accessed 22 August 2013. In this article Howman is also quoted with the following statement in regard to the UK: ‘If you think the mafia and underworld aren’t involved in this country in sport, you’re in fairyland’.

36 WADA President John Fahey (<http://www.independent.co.uk/sport/general/athletics/exclusive-wada-chief-john-fahey-to-target-the-cheats-behind-the-drug-cheats-8729058.html> accessed 20 August 2013); also <http://www.faz.net/aktuell/sport/sportpolitik/dopinggesetzgebung-effektive-dopingbekaempfung-ist-ohne-staat-nicht-moeglich-1146943.html> accessed 20 August 2013. Although, in many countries, doping or the possession of banned substances are not under penalty of law and dopers cannot be punished outside the autonomy of sports, dealers can often be targeted on the grounds of violating public health-related provisions of the law on drugs.

39 I am indebted to Dirk Lehmkuhl for this observation.

40 The immediately addressed sporting association, the International Skating Union, rejected the ‘attacks’ against the CAS as ‘an irresponsible offence against the dedicated work of hundreds of CAS arbitrators from many countries who have proved their professionalism and independence in hundreds, if not thousands of decisions rendered over the last 25 years’ (<http://www.womensportreport.com/women-sport_official-press-release-from-the-isu-claudia-pechstein-case_17249> accessed 3 November 2013).

41 I thank one of my reviewers for this important qualification.

42 <http://eur-lex.europa.eu/legal-content/EN/TXT/?uri=CELEX:61993CJ0415> accessed 7 June 2014. See also Lengauer (2011: 121–36).

References

Abbott, Kenneth W. and Snidal, Duncan. 2009. “The Governance Triangle: Regulatory Standards Institutions and the Shadow of the State.” In The Politics of Global Regulation, edited by Mattli, Walter and Woods, Ngaire, 4488. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Avbelj, Matej and Komarek, Jan, eds. 2012. Constitutional Pluralism in the European Union and Beyond. Oxford: Hart Publishing.Google Scholar
Baumgart-Ochse, Claudia, et al. 2012. The Relevance of Private Actors in the Transnational Sphere for Just Peace Governance. PRIF Working Paper No. 13, Frankfurt am Main, June 2012.Google Scholar
Bellamy, Alex J. 2009. Responsibility to Protect: The Global Effort to End Mass Atrocities. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Black, Julia. 2008. “Constructing and Contesting Legitimacy and Accountability in Polycentric Regulatory Regimes.” Regulation and Governance 2(2):137–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bogdandy, Armin von, Dann, Philipp and Goldmann, Matthias. 2008. “Developing the Publicness of Public International Law: Towards a Legal Framework for Global Governance Activities.” German Law Journal 9(11):1375–400.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bogdandy, Armin von, Wolfrum, Rüdiger, Bernstorff, Jochen von, Dann, Philipp and Goldmann, Matthias, eds. 2010. The Exercise of Public Authority by International Institutions. Berlin and Heidelberg: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Börzel, Tanja. 2010. “Governance with/out Government. False Promises or Flawed Premises?” SFB Governance Working Paper Series, No. 23, March 2010.Google Scholar
Börzel, Tanja and Risse, Thomas. 2005. “Public Private Partnerships: Effective and Legitimate Tools of Transnational Governance?” In Complex Sovereignty. Reconstituting Political Authority in the Twenty-First Century, edited by Grande, Edgar and Pauly, Louis, 195216. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Buchanan, Allen and Keohane, Robert O.. 2006. “The Legitimacy of Global Governance Institutions.” Ethics and International Affairs 20(4):405–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bumke, Christian and Röthel, Anne, eds. 2012. Privates Recht. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.Google Scholar
Burnheim, John. 1986. “Democracy, Nation States and the World System.” In New Forms of Democracy, edited by Held, David and Pollitt, Christopher, 219–39. London: Open University.Google Scholar
Cohen, Jean L. 2014. “Reply to Scheuerman’s review of Globalization and Sovereignty.” Global Constitutionalism 3(1):119–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collin, Peter. 2011. “‘Gesellschaftliche Selbstregulierung’ und ‘regulierte Selbstregulierung’” – ertragversprechende Analysekategorien für eine (rechts-)historische Perspektive?” In Selbstregulierung im 19. Jahrhundert – zwischen Autonomie und staatlichen Steuerungsansprüchen, edited by Collin, Peteret al., 331. Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann.Google Scholar
Conzelmann, Thomas and Wolf, Klaus Dieter. 2007. “The Potential and Limits of Governance by Private Codes of Conduct.” In Transnational Private Governance and its Limits, edited by Graz, Jean–Christophe and Nölke, Andreas, 98114. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Craig, Paul. 2003. “National Courts and Community Law.” In Governing Europe, edited by Hayward, Jack and Menon, Anand, 1535. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cutler, A. Claire, Haufler, Virginia and Porter, Tony, eds. 1999. Private Authority and International Affairs. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Deitelhoff, Nicole and Wolf, Klaus Dieter. 2013. “Business and Human Rights: How Corporate Norm Violaters become Norm-entrepreneurs.” In The Persistent Power of Human Rights. From Commitment to Compliance, edited by Risse, Thomas, Ropp, Stephen and Sikkink, Kathryn, 222–38. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dingwerth, Klaus. 2007. The New Transnationalism: Transnational Governance and Democratic Legitimacy. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dingwerth, Klaus 2008. “North-South Parity in Global Governance: The Affirmative Procedures of the Forest Stewardship Council.” Global Governance: A Review of Multilateralism and International Organizations 14(1):5372.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dingwerth, Klaus and Pattberg, Philipp. 2006. “Global Governance as a Perspective on World Politics.” Global Governance 12(2):185203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flohr, Annegret. 2014. Industry Self-Regulation and International Legalization. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flohr, Annegret, Rieth, Lothar, Schwindenhammer, Sandra and Wolf, Klaus Dieter, eds. 2010. The Role of Business in Global Governance. Corporations as Norm-entrepreneurs. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan 2010.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, Milton. 1970. The Social Responsibility of Business is to Increase its Profits. New York Times Magazine, 13 September 1970.Google Scholar
Grant, J. Andrew. 2011. “The Kimberly Process at Ten: Reflections on a Decade of Efforts to End the Trade in Conflict Diamonds.” In High-Value Natural Resources and Peacebuilding, edited by Lujala, Päivi and Rustad, Siri Aas, 159–80. Milton Park: Earthscan.Google Scholar
Grant, J. Andrew and Taylor, Ian. 2004. “Global Governance and Conflict Diamonds: The Kimberley Process and the Quest for Clean Gems.” The Round Table 93:385401.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Graz, Jean-Christophe and Nölke, Andreas, eds. 2007. Transnational Private Governance and its Limits. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gulbrandsen, Lars H. 2004. “Overlapping Public and Private Governance. Can Forest Certification Fill the Gaps in the Global Forest Regime?Global Environmental Politics 4(2):7599.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haas, Ulrich. 2004. “Effektive Dopingbekämpfung ist ohne Staat nicht möglich. “ Frankfurter Allgemeine Zeitung, 26 February 2004.Google Scholar
Hall, Rodney Bruce, and Biersteker, Thomas J.. 2002. “The Emergence of Private Authority in the International System.” In The Emergence of Private Authority in Global Governance’, edited by Hall, Rodney Bruce and Biersteker, Thomas J., 322. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hart, Herbert L.A. 1961. The Concept of Law. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Haufler, Virginia. 2001. A Public Role for the Private Sector: Industry Self-Regulation in a Global Economy. Washington, DC: Carnegie Endowment for International Peace.Google Scholar
Haufler, Virginia 2009a. “The Kimberley Process, Club Goods, and Public Enforcement of a Private Regime.” In Voluntary Programs: A Club Theory Perspective’, edited by Potoski, Matthew and Prakash, Aseem, 89105. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haufler, Virginia 2009b. “The Kimberley Process Certification Scheme: An Innovation in Global Governance and Conflict Prevention.” Journal of Business Ethics 89(4):403–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Held, David and McGrew, Anthony, eds. 2002. Governing Globalization. Power, Authority and Global Governance. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Héritier, Adrienne and Lehmkuhl, Dirk. 2008. “Introduction: The Shadow of Hierarchy and New Modes of Governance.” Journal of Public Policy 28(1):117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jakobi, Anja P. 2013. “Governing War Economies: Conflict Diamonds and the Kimberley Process.” In The Transnational Governance of Violence and Crime. Non-State Actors in Security, edited by Jakobi, Anja P. and Wolf, Klaus Dieter, 84105. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Joerges, Christian and Neyer, Juergen. 1997. “From Intergovernmental Bargaining to Deliberative Political Processes: The Constitutionalisation of Comitology.” European Law Journal 3(3):273–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kauerhof, Rico. 2007. “Ein Anti-Doping-Gesetz als Garant für den sauberen Sport?HRRS. Onlinezeitschrift für Höchstrichterliche Rechtsprechung im Strafrecht 2(8):71–5, available at <http://hrr-strafrecht.de> accessed 20 August 2013.Google Scholar
Kell, Georg. 2003. “The Global Compact: Origins, Operations, Progress, Challenges.” Journal of Corporate Citizenship 3(11):3549.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ki-moon, Ban. 2013. “Responsibility to Protect: State Responsibility and Prevention. Report of the Secretary-General.” United Nations Document, A /67/929 – S /2013/399, available at <http://www.un.org/ga/search/view_doc.asp?symbol=A/67/929> accessed 25 October 2013.+accessed+25+October+2013.>Google Scholar
Knill, Christoph and Lehmkuhl, Dirk. 2002. “Private Actors and the State: Internationalization and Changing Patterns of Governance.” Governance 15(1):4163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koenig-Archibugi, Matthias. 2004. “Transnational Corporations and Public Accountability.” Government and Opposition 39(2):234–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kooiman, Jan. 2000. “Societal Governance: Levels, Modes, and Orders of Social-Political Interaction.” In Debating Governance – Authority, Steering, and Democracy’, edited by Pierre, Jon, 138–64. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kooiman, Jan 2003. Governing as Governance. London: Sage.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kotzenberg, Jochen. 2007. Die Bindung des Sportlers an private Dopingregeln und private Schiedsgerichte. Schriften zum Sportrecht, vol. 8. Baden-Baden: Nomos.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kumm, Mattias, Lang, Anthony F. Jr., Tully, James and Wiener, Antje. 2014. “Editorial: How Large is the World of Global Constitutionalism?Global Constitutionalism 3(1):18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lehmkuhl, Dirk. 2004. “Verrechtlichung privater Selbstregulierung: der lange Schatten staatlichen Rechts im transnationalen Sport. “ In Vom Nutzen und Elend internationaler Verrechtlichung. Eine Perspektive für Global Governance?, edited by Zürn, Michael and Zangl, Bernhard, 179–97. Bonn: Dietz.Google Scholar
Lehmkuhl, Dirk 2008. “Control Modes in the Age of Transnational Governance.” Law and Policy 30(3):336–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leibfried, Stefan and Zürn, Michael, eds. 2005. Transformations of the State? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lengauer, Alina. 2011. Drittwirkung von Grundfreiheiten. Ein Beitrag zu dem Konzept des Normadressaten im Gemeinschaftsrecht. Wien/New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levy, Roy. 2012. “Swiss Federal Tribunal Overrules CAS Award in a Landmark Decision: FIFA vs Matuzalem.” International Sports Law Journal 34:35–8.Google Scholar
Loughlin, Martin. 2014. “‘Constitutional Pluralism’: An Oxymoron?Global Constitutionalism 3(1):930.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lüer, Christoph. 2006. Dopingstrafen im Sport und der Grundsatz ‘Ne bis in idem’. Unter besonderer Berücksichtigung des WADA-Code und des NADA-Code. Schriften zum Sportrecht, vol. 3. Baden-Baden: Nomos.Google Scholar
MacCormick, Neil. 1999. Questioning Sovereignty: Law, State and Nation in the European Commonwealth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Majone, Giandomenico. 1998. “Europe’s Democratic Deficit.” European Law Journal 4(1):528.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mathews, Jessica Tuchman. 1997. “Power Shift.” Foreign Affairs 76(1):5066.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mätzler, Andreas. 2009. Die internationalen Organisationsstrukturen im Spitzensport und die Regelwerke der Sportverbände. Dissertation: University of Vienna, available at <http://othes.univie.ac.at/7863/1/2009-07-21_9709964.pdf> accessed 21 December 2011.Google Scholar
Michael, Lothar. 2005. “Private Standardsetter und demokratisch legitimierte Rechtsetzung. “In Demokratie in Europa’, edited by Bauer, Hartmut, Huber, Peter M. and Sommermann, Karl-Peter, 431–56. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.Google Scholar
Miller, David. 2007. National Responsibility and Global Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moravcsik, Andrew. 1994. “Why the European Community Strengthens the State: International Co-operation and Domestic Politics.” Center for European Studies Working Paper Series No. 52. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University.Google Scholar
Moravcsik, Andrew 2002. “In Defence of the ‘Democratic Deficit’: Reassessing Legitimacy in the European Union.” Journal of Common Market Studies 40(4):603–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Niesen, Peter, ed. 2012. Transnationale Gerechtigkeit und Demokratie. Frankfurt am Main and New York, NY: Campus.Google Scholar
Nolte, Martin. 2012. “Vereinbartes Recht am Beispiel der lex sportiva. Wechselwirkungen zwischen ‘lex sportiva’ und ‘lex extra sportiva’.” In Privates Recht, edited by Bumke, Christian and Röthel, Anne, 107–18. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.Google Scholar
Ougaard, Morten, and Leander, Anna, eds. 2010. Business and Global Governance. London: Routledge 2010.Google Scholar
Papadopoulos, Yannis. 2013. “The Challenge of Transnational Private Governance: Evaluating Authorization, Representation, and Accountability.” LIEPP Working Paper 8, February 2013, Lausanne.Google Scholar
Peters, Anne, and Armingeon, Klaus. 2009. “Introduction – Global Constitutionalism from an Interdisciplinary Perspective.” Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies 16(2):385–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pierre, Jon and Peters, B. Guy. 2000. Governance, Politics and the State. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Poiares Maduro, Miguel. 2012. “Three Claims of Constitutional Pluralism.” In Constitutional Pluralism in the European Union and Beyond, edited by Avbelj, Matej and Komarek, Jan, 6784. Oxford: Hart Publishing.Google Scholar
Quack, Sigrid. 2010. “Law, Expertise and Legitimacy in Transnational Economic Governance: An Introduction.” Socio-Economic Review 8(1):316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rasche, Andreas and Kell, Georg, eds. 2010. The United Nations Global Compact: Achievements, Trends and Challenges. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reinicke, Wolfgang H. 1998. Global Public Policy. Governing without Government. Washington, DC: The Brookings Institution.Google Scholar
Reissinger, Fabian. 2010. Staatliche Verantwortung zur Bekämpfung des Dopings. Schriften zum Sportrecht, vol. 19. Baden-Baden: Nomos.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Risse, Thomas, ed. 2011. Governance without a State? Policies and Politics in Areas of Limited Statehood. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Risse, Thomas 2013. “Transnational Actors and World Politics.” In Handbook of International Relations, edited by Carlsnaes, Walter, Risse, Thomas and Simmons, Beth A., 426–53. London, Thousand Oaks, New Delhi and Singapore: Sage.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenau, James N. and Czempiel, Ernst-Otto, eds. 1992. Governance without Government: Order and Change in World Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Röthel, Anne. 2007. “Lex mercatoria, lex sportiva, lex technica – Private Rechtsetzung jenseits des Nationalstaates?JuristenZeitung 62(15–16):755–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruggie, John G. 2004. “Reconstituting the Global Public Domain. Issues, Actors, and Practices.” European Journal of International Relations 10(4):499531.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruggie, John. 2013. Just Business. Multinational Corporations and Human Rights. New York, NY: W. W. Norton & Co.Google Scholar
Scharpf, Fritz W. 1999. Governing in Europe: Effective and Democratic? Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Scherer, Andreas Georg and Palazzo, Guido, eds. 2008. Handbook of Research on Global Corporate Citizenship. Cheltenham, UK and Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scheuerman, William E. 2014. “Globalization, Constitutionalism, and Sovereignty.” Global Constitutionalism 3(1): 102–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schimank, Uwe and Glagow, Manfred. 1984. “Formen politischer Steuerung: Etatismus, Subsidiarität, Delegation und Neokorporatismus.” In Gesellschaftssteuerung zwischen Korporatismus und Subsidiarität, edited by Glagow, Manfred, 428. Bielefeld: A. J. Z. Druck & Verlag.Google Scholar
Schuppert, Gunnar Folke. 2001. “Das Konzept der regulierten Selbstregulierung als Bestandteil einer als Regelungswissenschaft verstandenen Rechtswissenschaft.” In Regulierte Selbstregulierung als Steuerungskonzept des Gewährleistungsstaates. Die Verwaltung, suppl. 4, 201–50.Google Scholar
Schuppert, Gunnar Folke 2011a. Governance und Rechtsetzung. Grundfragen einer modernen Regelungswissenschaft. Baden-Baden: Nomos.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schuppert, Gunnar Folke 2011b. “Law without the State? A New Interplay between State and Non-State Actors in Governance by Rule Making.” In Governance without a State? Policies and Politics in Areas of Limited Statehood, edited by Risse, Thomas, 6586. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Schuppert, Gunnar Folken.d. New Modes of Governance and the Rule of Law: The Case of Transnational Rule-Making, MS.Google Scholar
Sciulli, David. 1992 Theory of Societal Constitutionalism: Foundations of a Non-Marxistic Critical Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sciulli, David 2001. Corporate Power in Civil Society. An Application of Societal Constitutionalism. New York, NY: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Siekmann, Robert C. R. 2012. “Anti-Doping Law in Sport: The Hybrid Character of WADA and the Human Rights of Athletes in Doping Cases (Proportionality Principle).” In Introduction to International and European Sports Law’, edited by Siekmann, Robert C. R., 313–33. The Hague: T. M. C. Asser Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stephen, Matthew and Zürn, Michael. 2013. “Contested World Orders: Rising Powers, Non-State Actors, and the Politics of Authority Beyond the Nation-state.” Paper presented at the “Rising Powers and Contested Orders in the Multipolar System” Conference, Pontifical Catholic University of Rio, 19–20 September 2013.Google Scholar
Strange, Susan. 1996. The Retreat of the State: The Diffusion of Power in the World Economy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Take, Ingo. 2012. “Regulating the Internet Infrastructure: A Comparative Appraisal of the Legitimacy of ICANN, ITU, and the WSIS.” Regulation and Governance 6(4):499523.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Teubner, Gunther. 1997. “Foreword: Legal Regimes of Global Non-state Actors.” In Global Law without a State, edited by Teubner, Gunther, xiii–xvii. Aldershot: Dartmouth.Google Scholar
Teubner, Gunther 2010. “Selbst-Konstitutionalisierung transnationaler Unternehmen? Zur Verknüpfung ‘privater‘ und ‘staatlicher‘ Corporate Codes of Conduct.” In Unternehmen, Markt und Verantwortung: Festschrift für Klaus Hopt, edited by Grundmann, Stephanet al., 1449–70. Berlin: de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Teubner, Gunther 2011. “The Project of Constitutional Sociology: Irritating Nation State Constitutionalism.” Zeitschrift für Rechtssoziologie 32(2):189204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Teubner, Gunther 2012. Constitutional Fragments: Societal Constitutionalism and Globalization. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
UNESCO. 2005. “International Convention against Doping in Sport.” ED.2005/CONVENTION ANTI-DOPING Rev, Paris, 19 October 2005, available at <http://www.wada-ama.org/en/World-Anti-Doping-Program/Governments/UNESCO-International-Convention-against-Doping-in-Sport> accessed 10 March 2013.+accessed+10+March+2013.>Google Scholar
Voser, Nathalie, and Meier, Philipp. 2010. “Swiss Federal Tribunal’s reasoning in the ‘Pechstein’ case confirms its strict approach to petitions to set aside arbitral awards.” Practical Law, 2 June 2010, available at <http://us.practicallaw.com/5-502-4343?q=&qp=&qo=&qe=> accessed 1 April 2014.+accessed+1+April+2014.>Google Scholar
Wiener, Antje, Lang, Anthony F., Tully, James, Poiares Maduro, Miguel, and Kumm, Mattias. 2012. “Global Constitutionalism: Human Rights, Democracy and the Rule of Law.” Global Constitutionalism 1(1):115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolf, Klaus Dieter. 1999. “The New Raison d’État as a Problem for Democracy in World Society.” European Journal of International Relations 5(3):333–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolf, Klaus Dieter 2008. “Emerging Patterns of Global Governance: The New Interplay between the State, Business and Civil Society.” In Handbook of Research on Global Corporate Citizenship, edited by Scherer, Andreas Georg and Palazzo, Guido, 225–48. Cheltenham, UK and Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar.Google Scholar
Wolf, Klaus Dieter 2010. “Chartered Companies: Linking Private Security Governance in Early and Post Modernity.” In Corporate Security Responsibility? Private Governance Contributions to Peace and Security in Zones of Conflict’, edited by Deitelhoff, Nicole and Wolf, Klaus Dieter, 154–76. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Wolf, Klaus Dieter 2012a. “Legitimitätsbedarf und Legitimation privater Selbstregulierung im Fall der lex sportiva.” In Transnationale Gerechtigkeit und Demokratie, edited by Niesen, Peter, 189214. Frankfurt am Main and New York, NY: Campus.Google Scholar
Wolf, Klaus Dieter 2012b. “Private Akteure als Normsetzer – Politikwissenschaftliche Fragestellungen und Perspektiven.” In Privates Recht, edited Christian Bumke and Anne Röthel, 187205. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.Google Scholar
Wolfsberg Group. 2002. The Wolfsberg Anti-Money Laundering Principles for Correspondent Banking, available at <http://www.wolfsberg-principles.com/pdf/standards/Wolfsberg_Correspondent_Banking_Guidelines_(2002).pdf> accessed 30 April 2014.+accessed+30+April+2014.>Google Scholar
World Anti-Doping Agency. 2009. World-Anti-Doping-Code 2009, Canada available at <http://www.wada-ama.org/Documents/World_Anti-Doping_Program/WADP-The-Code/WADA_Anti-Doping_CODE_2009_EN.pdf> accessed 30 April 2013.+accessed+30+April+2013.>Google Scholar
World Conference on Doping in Sport. 2003. Copenhagen Declaration on Anti-Doping in Sport 2003, available at <http://www.wada-ama.org/en/World-Anti-Doping-Program/Governments/Copenhagen-Declaration-on-Anti-Doping-in-Sport> accessed 7 March 2013.+accessed+7+March+2013.>Google Scholar
Wright, Christopher. 2009. “Setting Standards for Responsible Banking: Examining the Role of the International Finance Corporation in the Emergence of the Equator Principles.” In International Organizations in Global Environmental Governance, edited by Biermann, Frank, Siebenhüner, Bernd and Schreyögg, Anna, 5170. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Zürn, Michael. 1998. Regieren jenseits des Nationalstaates. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Zürn, Michael, Binder, Martin and Ecker-Ehrhardt, Matthias. 2012. “International Political Authority and Its Politicization.” International Theory 4(1):69106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1. Variants of state embedment of transnational private self-regulation8