Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-hvd4g Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-12T00:07:53.892Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Contempt, like any other social affect, can be an emotion as well as a sentiment

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 October 2017

Roger Giner-Sorolla
Affiliation:
School of Psychology, University of Kent, Canterbury, Kent, CT2 7NP, United Kingdom. R.S.Giner-Sorolla@kent.ac.ukhttps://www.kent.ac.uk/psychology/people/ginerr/
Agneta H. Fischer
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology University of Amsterdam, 1001 NK Amsterdam, The Netherlands. a.h.fischer@uva.nlhttp://home.medewerker.uva.nl/a.h.fischer/

Abstract

Gervais & Fessler assert that contempt is (a) not an emotion (or an attitude) but (b) a sentiment. Here, we challenge the validity and empirical basis of these two assertions, arguing that contempt, like many other emotions, can be both an emotion and a sentiment.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2017 

The debate about how to define emotions and demarcate them from related phenomena like affect, feelings, attitudes, and sentiments is an everlasting discussion in the social and life sciences, starting with ancient philosophers and continuing until the present day (see Kleinginna & Kleinginna [Reference Kleinginna and Kleinginna1981] for an overview). Gervais & Fessler's (G&F's) article is a new attempt to clarify these different concepts, focusing on one emotion: contempt. The authors rightly argue that contempt is a relatively neglected phenomenon (see also our review, Fischer & Giner-Sorolla Reference Fischer and Giner-Sorolla2016), but they also conclude that “the contempt-as-emotion literature has provided inconclusive, even perplexing results” (sect. 1, para. 3). They therefore assert that contempt is (a) not an emotion (or an attitude), but (b) a sentiment. Here, we challenge the validity and empirical basis of these two assertions.

Contempt as non-prototypical emotion

G&F find support for eight different and coherent features of contempt from the literature, but still conclude that contempt cannot be considered a (basic) emotion. We do not see this literature on contempt as perplexing or inconsistent. Our review took as its basis a prototype view (Russell Reference Russell1991b) in which non-prototypical emotions lack one or more key traits. For example, we argued that contempt may lack hot physiology and a clear term in English, but its appraisals, action tendencies, and expressions are distinctive. Contempt thus can be seen as a non-prototypical emotion (similar to other non-prototypical emotions like guilt or worry). This more parsimonious account shows that the literature does not lead inevitably to the model proposed by G&F.

Contempt as a sentiment, not an emotion

In our review, we argue that contempt can be both emotion and sentiment, based on Frijda et al.'s (Reference Frijda, Mesquita, Sonnemans, Van Goozen and Strongman1991) definition of sentiment as an enduring object–emotion association, that is, a disposition to respond emotionally to a certain object. G&F assume that contempt can only be seen as an enduring sentiment, organizing more momentary related emotions such as anger and disgust around “a common attitudinal core” (sect. 3.3, para. 3). However, many other emotions can become enduring object-linked emotional sentiments, such as anger (e.g., Giner-Sorolla Reference Giner-Sorolla2012; Halperin & Gross Reference Halperin and Gross2011), disgust (Ortony et al. Reference Ortony, Clore and Collins1990; Olatunji et al. Reference Olatunji, Forsyth and Cherian2007), envy, or admiration (Fiske et al. Reference Fiske, Cuddy, Glick and Xu2002; Harris & Fiske Reference Harris and Fiske2007). In other words, any emotion can become a sentiment when it becomes temporally extended, characterized by enduring changes in one's relation with others. There is no evidence that one of these is a “master sentiment” leading the other mere emotions along.

According to G&F, because contempt is a sentiment, it cannot also be an emotion, elicited by a single action of a person. We think that this assumption makes a category error: yes, contempt represents negative traits in others, but need not itself arise from an enduring attitude; one action can suffice. For example, a son who has a very good relationship with his parents hears that they have decided to divorce because his father betrayed his mother by sleeping with another woman, and he feels contempt towards his father. No pre-existing negative attitude is required to feel contempt for his father. On the contrary, the experience of contempt may lead to an attitude change towards his father, and he may not have the same relationship with his father ever again. This story, as reported by a respondent in one of our studies (Fischer & Roseman Reference Fischer and Roseman2007), clearly illustrates that contempt can be an immediate response.

Although it is true that various studies have shown that contempt is more likely to endure than anger, this is plausibly because its eliciting factors are more likely to endure (a single act versus a character), and not a reason to deny contempt's manifestation as an emotion. In fact, it is hard to see how evidence that contempt has distinctive expressions (e.g., the unilateral lip curl [Matsumoto & Ekman Reference Matsumoto and Ekman2004], or clucking or tutting noises [Hawk et al. Reference Hawk, van Kleef, Fischer and van der Schalk2009]) fits the view of contempt as a recruiter of diverse, context-sensitive feelings and expressions. What transitory emotion is recruited, if not contempt itself, when the contempt sentiment leads to such displays?

The Attitude–Scenario–Emotion model of sentiments

While Frijda and colleagues' definition of sentiment is easy to operationalize – does an object elicit the same emotion at different times or when presented out of context – G&F propose an Attitude–Scenario–Emotion model of sentiments. This model's components have many hard-to-verify, hard-to-falsify or overlapping features (see G&F's Table 2 in the target article), for example, “diverse motives, behaviors, and expressions across scenarios” (said of sentiments in their Table 2, but also potentially true of emotions or attitudes). In fact, the authors assert that sentiments are “higher-level functional networks of attitudes and emotion; each sentiment is an attitude state and the various emotions disposed by that representation” (sect. 4.2, para. 6). The interrelatedness and fuzzy boundaries of three core concepts of this model stand in sharp contrast with the authors' aim to disentangle folk concepts and the neurobiological basis of affect systems.

Conclusion

We agree on many functional points about contempt, but don't see the usefulness of an overly complicated model that blurs established usages of the terms “emotion” and “sentiment.” Of the eight features of folk “contempt” presented as evidence of deep structure (target article, Table 1), none of them supports the structural model exclusively. Anger and disgust, the latter in particular, can also be (1) object focused and (2) enduring. A prototype view of contempt as emotion also characterizes contempt with the perception (feature 3) and reinforcement (feature 4) of low social value, and with related action tendencies (feature 8). Contempt's “coldness” (feature 5) is a non-prototypical feature, and its negative association with empathy and positive association with anger and disgust (feature 6) can be explained by related negative appraisals of social value. Finally, there is no comparative evidence that contempt has more or fewer expressions than other emotions (feature 7), for example, disgust and anger too can be expressed through variations of a facial expression, sounds, verbal expression, or gestures. We encourage the study of the social and evolutionary functions of contempt using a more parsimonious and better-supported conceptual model.

References

Fischer, A. & Giner-Sorolla, R. (2016) Contempt: Derogating others while keeping calm. Emotion Review 8(4):346–57. doi:10.1177/1754073915610439. Available at: http://journals.sagepub.com/doi/full/10.1177/1754073915610439.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fischer, A. H. & Roseman, I. J. (2007) Beat them or ban them: The characteristics and social functions of anger and contempt. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 93(1):103–15. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.93.1.103.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fiske, S. T., Cuddy, A. J. C., Glick, P. & Xu, J. (2002) A model of (often mixed) stereotype content: Competence and warmth respectively follow from perceived status and competition. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 82(6):878902. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.82.6.878.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frijda, N. H., Mesquita, B., Sonnemans, J. & Van Goozen, S. (1991) The duration of affective phenomena or emotions, sentiments and passions. In: International review of studies on emotion, vol. 1, ed. Strongman, K. T., pp. 187225. Wiley.Google Scholar
Giner-Sorolla, R. (2012) Judging passions: Moral emotions in persons and groups. European Monographs in Social Psychology. Psychology Press.Google Scholar
Halperin, E. & Gross, J. J. (2011) Intergroup anger in intractable conflict: Long-term sentiments predict anger responses during the Gaza War. Group Processes & Intergroup Relations 14(4):477–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harris, L. T. & Fiske, S. T. (2007) Social groups that elicit disgust are differentially processed in mPFC. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience 2:4551. Available at: http://doi.org/10.1093/scan/nsl037.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hawk, S. T., van Kleef, G. A., Fischer, A. H. & van der Schalk, J. (2009) “Worth a thousand words”: Absolute and relative decoding of nonlinguistic affect vocalizations. Emotion 9:293305. doi: 10.1037/a0015178.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kleinginna, P. R. Jr., & Kleinginna, A. M. (1981) A categorized list of motivation definitions, with a suggestion for a consensual definition. Motivation and Emotion 5(3):263–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Matsumoto, D. & Ekman, P. (2004) The relationship among expressions, labels, and descriptions of contempt. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 87(4):529–40. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.87.4.529.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Olatunji, B. O., Forsyth, J. P. & Cherian, A. (2007) Evaluative differential conditioning of disgust: A sticky form of relational learning that is resistant to extinction. Journal of Anxiety Disorders 21:820–34.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ortony, A., Clore, G. L. & Collins, A. (1990) The cognitive structure of emotions. Cambridge University Press. (Paperback edition, reprint).Google Scholar
Russell, J. A. (1991b) In defense of a prototype approach to emotion concepts. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 60:3747. http://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.60.1.37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar