Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-5r2nc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-11T15:01:53.238Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A call for comparing theories of consciousness and data sharing

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 March 2022

Sarah L. Eagleman
Affiliation:
Department of Neurology and Neurological Sciences, School of Medicine, Stanford University, Stanford, CA94304, USAsaraheagleman@stanford.edu; https://profiles.stanford.edu/sarah-eagleman
David M. Eagleman
Affiliation:
Department of Psychiatry and Behavioral Sciences, School of Medicine, Stanford University, Stanford, CA94304, USAdavideagleman@stanford.edu; https://deagle.people.stanford.edu/ Wu Tsai Neurosciences Institute, Stanford University, Stanford, CA94305, USA. menon@stanford.edu; https://profiles.stanford.edu/vinod-menonkmeador@stanford.edu; https://profiles.stanford.edu/kimford-meador
Vinod Menon
Affiliation:
Department of Neurology and Neurological Sciences, School of Medicine, Stanford University, Stanford, CA94304, USAsaraheagleman@stanford.edu; https://profiles.stanford.edu/sarah-eagleman Department of Psychiatry and Behavioral Sciences, School of Medicine, Stanford University, Stanford, CA94304, USAdavideagleman@stanford.edu; https://deagle.people.stanford.edu/ Wu Tsai Neurosciences Institute, Stanford University, Stanford, CA94305, USA. menon@stanford.edu; https://profiles.stanford.edu/vinod-menonkmeador@stanford.edu; https://profiles.stanford.edu/kimford-meador
Kimford J. Meador
Affiliation:
Department of Neurology and Neurological Sciences, School of Medicine, Stanford University, Stanford, CA94304, USAsaraheagleman@stanford.edu; https://profiles.stanford.edu/sarah-eagleman Wu Tsai Neurosciences Institute, Stanford University, Stanford, CA94305, USA. menon@stanford.edu; https://profiles.stanford.edu/vinod-menonkmeador@stanford.edu; https://profiles.stanford.edu/kimford-meador

Abstract

Merker, Williford, and Rudrauf make several arguments against the integrated information theory of consciousness; whereas some have merit, their conclusion that the theory should be discarded is premature. Coming years promise advances in the empirical study of consciousness, and only after theories are independently tested with shared data can they be ruled in or out. We propose future research directions.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

Merker, Williford, and Rudrauf argue that the many unanswered aspects of integrated information theory (IIT) condemn it as a failed theory of consciousness. They make several important points about the ways in which IIT is underspecified – for example, how first-person phenomenology is missing in the IIT formalism, or more generally how integrated information alone could be synonymous with consciousness. These are important concerns.

However, at this young stage of understanding the neuroscience of consciousness, under-specification does not equal incorrectness. For example, the authors argue that IIT is computationally challenging, preventing it from being currently tested on brain data. But computational difficulty does not by itself reflect on the legitimacy of a hypothesis. Another criticism asserts that if IIT were correct, that could imply consciousness in other complex systems. But the authors leverage no data to establish why consciousness in other biological systems is impossible. In sum, their criticisms can only be taken as suggestions for digging in, rather than a definitive ruling out.

As the authors correctly highlight, the field needs more experimentation to directly test theories against one another. We argue that synthesis and open sharing of data, along with multiple comparative studies, are needed to facilitate this. We make a plea for sharing relevant neurophysiological and neuroimaging data to propel the field forward and resolve the kind of issues raised by the authors.

Such a community effort will allow many theories to be more easily pitted against one another. For example, in addition to IIT, prominent theories of consciousness include global ignition (sudden, widespread activation of neuronal processes), global workspace (incoming information becomes globally available across diverse integrated brain systems), and re-entrant processing (signaling along reentrant paths integrates activity from different brain regions). These theories can be tested by measuring neural activity associated with conscious perception, such as alterations in directional flows (causality), dynamic state, connectivity, or information integration (complexity) of brain processing (Cai, Ryali, Pasumarthy, Talasila, & Menon, Reference Cai, Ryali, Pasumarthy, Talasila and Menon2021). Experiments involving the presentation of simple touch stimuli presented near perceptual thresholds, combined with haptic masks or sounds, can be used to identify alterations in network activity associated with conscious processing (Meador et al., Reference Meador, Revill, Epstein, Sathian, Loring and Rorden2017b). If a neural marker related to a theory is proposed to be uniquely associated with conscious processing, but is observed under non-conscious conditions, that theory is undermined.

Analyses of neural data from large-scale, multi-electrode electrophysiological recordings could offer even more insight. For example, the recent detect, pulse, switch, and wave model (Herman et al., Reference Herman, Smith, Kronemer, Watsky, Chen, Gober and Blumenfeld2019), which implies widespread integration and broadcasting across neural networks, is consistent with the global workspace theory (Dehaene & Naccache, Reference Dehaene and Naccache2001; Menon & Uddin, Reference Menon and Uddin2010; Sridharan, Levitin, & Menon, Reference Sridharan, Levitin and Menon2008). As another example, changes in directional processing flows would support theories of re-entrant processing. Changes in brain dynamics or connectivity would support theories of global ignition or global workspace. Changes in complexity would support the IIT. Surprisingly, direct comparison of these theories in the same dataset with sophisticated analyses of networks has never been performed.

Many experimental approaches can be leveraged. First, psychophysical manipulation of conscious perception can lead to measurable changes. For example, masking a touch will redirect changes to the hemisphere contralateral to the mask. A sound presented ipsilaterally to a target touch stimulus will increase detectability of the touch and produce a unique neural signature corresponding to conscious perception. In contrast, a sound opposite the touch will decrease detectability, exerting opposite effects on neural signatures of conscious perception. Extant published data from these studies could be readily shared via several platforms, such as OpenNeuro (Sherif et al., Reference Sherif, Rioux, Rousseau, Kassis, Beck, Adalat and Evans2014; Vogelstein et al., Reference Vogelstein, Perlman, Falk, Baden, Gray Roncal, Chandrashekhar and Burns2018).

Second, pharmacological agents are a powerful tool for disrupting arousal and information processing networks. Such agents can be leveraged with specificity, as anesthesia is not simply an on/off switch for consciousness. Instead, certain anesthetic and adjuvant agents (e.g., ketamine, propofol, nitrous oxide, and barbiturates) selectively disrupt unique neurotransmitter systems, impacting different arousal and sensory processing networks (Bonhomme et al., Reference Bonhomme, Staquet, Montupil, Defresne, Kirsch, Martial and Gosseries2019; Purdon, Sampson, Pavone, & Brown, Reference Purdon, Sampson, Pavone and Brown2015). Administration of different anesthetic agents results in unique electrophysiological signatures both at the single channel (Eagleman, Chander, Reynolds, Ouellette, & Maciver, Reference Eagleman, Chander, Reynolds, Ouellette and Maciver2019; Eagleman, Drover, Drover, Ouellette, & MacIver, Reference Eagleman, Drover, Drover, Ouellette and MacIver2018a; Eagleman et al., Reference Eagleman, Vaughn, Drover, Drover, Cohen, Ouellette and MacIver2018b) and multi-channel network level (Eagleman & Drover, Reference Eagleman and Drover2018; Lee & Mashour, Reference Lee and Mashour2018) when using electroencephalogram (EEG) in humans. A strong contender for a theory of consciousness would have to explain data resulting from different agents (Mashour, Reference Mashour2006). As one example, computational measures used in IIT can significantly discriminate between awake and anesthetized states even when patients are anesthetized with different agents (Casali et al., Reference Casali, Gosseries, Rosanova, Boly, Sarasso, Casali and Massimini2013; Sarasso et al., Reference Sarasso, Boly, Napolitani, Gosseries, Charland-Verville, Casarotto and Rex2015).

Finally, patient populations with unique sensory abilities or cognitive challenges present opportunities to compare theories of consciousness; we discuss four examples. First, conditions such as synesthesia (in which a person's senses are blended) are increasingly being subjected to neuroimaging and genetic analysis to understand the subtle differences that lead to slightly different states of consciousness (Cytowic & Eagleman, Reference Cytowic and Eagleman2011; Tomson, Narayan, Allen, & Eagleman, Reference Tomson, Narayan, Allen and Eagleman2013). Second, people with neglect syndrome cannot consciously perceive real-time stimuli or even spatial memories from the hemispace contralateral to a brain lesion (Meador, Loring, Bowers, & Heilman, Reference Meador, Loring, Bowers and Heilman1987, Reference Meador, Ray, Day and Loring2000). Third, corpus callosotomies in people with epilepsy give an opportunity to witness information processed independently by each hemisphere. Perceptions requiring high-level, hemisphere-specific cortical functions (e.g., language) may not access conscious perception for stimuli ipsilateral to that hemisphere, but simple stimuli may access conscious perception irrespective of hemispace, suggesting that simple stimuli are integrated subcortically (Meador, Loring, & Sathian, Reference Meador, Loring and Sathian2017a). Fourth, psychiatric disorders including dissociation syndromes offer a way to probe altered consciousness states and evaluate whether changes in IIT or brain network integration, more broadly, predict clinical symptoms (Menon, Reference Menon2021).

In summary, there are a growing number of approaches to refine, and possibly rule-out, different theories of consciousness. We are entering a golden age of measurement, analysis, and data sharing that make this endeavor possible in the coming years. However, progress will require independent testing of different theories and keeping an open mind until science can rule theories out.

Financial support

This study was supported by the NIH NIGMS (SE, grant number 1K99GM140215).

Conflict of interest

None.

References

Bonhomme, V., Staquet, C., Montupil, J., Defresne, A., Kirsch, M., Martial, C., … Gosseries, O. (2019). General anesthesia: A probe to explore consciousness. Frontiers in Systems Neuroscience, 13. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnsys.2019.00036CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cai, W., Ryali, S., Pasumarthy, R., Talasila, V., & Menon, V. (2021). Dynamic causal brain circuits during working memory and their functional controllability. Nature Communications, 12(1), 3314. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41467-021-23509-xCrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Casali, A. G., Gosseries, O., Rosanova, M., Boly, M., Sarasso, S., Casali, K. R., … Massimini, M. (2013). A theoretically based index of consciousness independent of sensory processing and behavior. Science Translational Medicine, 5(198). https://doi.org/10.1126/scitranslmed.3006294CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cytowic, R. E., & Eagleman, D. (2011). Wednesday is indigo blue: Discovering the brain of synesthesia. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dehaene, S., & Naccache, L. (2001). Towards a cognitive neuroscience of consciousness: Basic evidence and a workspace framework. Cognition, 79(1), 137. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0010-0277(00)00123-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eagleman, S. L., Chander, D., Reynolds, C., Ouellette, N. T., & Maciver, M. B. (2019). Nonlinear dynamics captures brain states at different levels of consciousness in patients anesthetized with propofol. PLoS ONE, 14(10), e0223921. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0223921CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Eagleman, S. L., Drover, C. M., Drover, D. R., Ouellette, N. T., & MacIver, M. B. (2018a). Remifentanil and nitrous oxide anesthesia produces a unique pattern of EEG activity during loss and recovery of response. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 12. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2018.00173CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eagleman, S. L., & Drover, D. R. (2018). Calculations of consciousness. Current Opinion in Anaesthesiology, 31(4), 431438. https://doi.org/10.1097/ACO.0000000000000618CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eagleman, S. L., Vaughn, D. A., Drover, D. R., Drover, C. M., Cohen, M. S., Ouellette, N. T., & MacIver, M. B. (2018b). Do complexity measures of frontal EEG distinguish loss of consciousness in geriatric patients under anesthesia? Frontiers in Neuroscience, 12, 645. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnins.2018.00645CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Herman, W. X., Smith, R. E., Kronemer, S. I., Watsky, R. E., Chen, W. C., Gober, L. M., … Blumenfeld, H. (2019). A switch and wave of neuronal activity in the cerebral cortex during the first second of conscious perception. Cerebral Cortex 29(2), 461474. https://doi.org/10.1093/cercor/bhx327CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lee, U., & Mashour, G. A. (2018). Role of network science in the study of anesthetic state transitions. Anesthesiology, 129(5), 10291044. https://doi.org/10.1097/ALN.0000000000002228CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mashour, G. A. (2006). Integrating the science of consciousness and anesthesia. Anesthesia & Analgesia, 103(4), 975982. https://doi.org/10.1213/01.ane.0000232442.69757.4aCrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Meador, K. J., Loring, D. W., Bowers, D., & Heilman, K. M. (1987). Remote memory and neglect syndrome. Neurology, 37(3), 522522. https://doi.org/10.1212/WNL.37.3.522CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Meador, K. J., Loring, D. W., & Sathian, K. (2017a). Consciousness post corpus callosotomy. Brain, 140(7), e38e38. https://doi.org/10.1093/brain/awx106CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meador, K. J., Ray, P. G., Day, L. J., & Loring, D. W. (2000). Train duration effects on perception: Sensory deficit, neglect, and cerebral lateralization. Journal of Clinical Neurophysiology, 17(4), 406413.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Meador, K. J., Revill, K. P., Epstein, C. M., Sathian, K., Loring, D. W., & Rorden, C. (2017b). Neuroimaging somatosensory perception and masking. Neuropsychologia, 94, 4451.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Menon, V. (2021). Dissociation by network integration. The American Journal of Psychiatry, 178(2), 110112. https://doi.org/10.1176/appi.ajp.2020.20121728CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Menon, V., & Uddin, L. Q. (2010). Saliency, switching, attention and control: A network model of insula function. Brain Structure & Function, 214(5–6), 655667. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00429-010-0262-0CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Purdon, P. L., Sampson, A., Pavone, K. J., & Brown, E. N. (2015). Clinical electroencephalography for anesthesiologists: Part I: Background and basic signatures. Anesthesiology, 123(4), 937960. https://doi.org/10.1097/ALN.0000000000000841CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sarasso, S., Boly, M., Napolitani, M., Gosseries, O., Charland-Verville, V., Casarotto, S., … Rex, S. (2015). Consciousness and complexity during unresponsiveness induced by propofol, xenon, and ketamine. Current Biology, 25(23), 30993105. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cub.2015.10.014CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sherif, T., Rioux, P., Rousseau, M.-E., Kassis, N., Beck, N., Adalat, R., … Evans, A. C. (2014). CBRAIN: A web-based, distributed computing platform for collaborative neuroimaging research. Frontiers in Neuroinformatics, 8, 54. https://doi.org/10.3389/fninf.2014.00054CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sridharan, D., Levitin, D. J., & Menon, V. (2008). A critical role for the right fronto-insular cortex in switching between central-executive and default-mode networks. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 105(34), 1256912574. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.0800005105CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tomson, S. N., Narayan, M., Allen, G. I., & Eagleman, D. M. (2013). Neural networks of colored sequence synesthesia. Journal of Neuroscience, 33(35), 1409814106. https://doi.org/10.1523/JNEUROSCI.5131-12.2013CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Vogelstein, J. T., Perlman, E., Falk, B., Baden, A., Gray Roncal, W., Chandrashekhar, V., … Burns, R. (2018). A community-developed open-source computational ecosystem for big neuro data. Nature Methods, 15(11), 846847. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41592-018-0181-1CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed