English law has long held the principle that religions should be free from interference by the state in certain matters. The original 1215 edition of the Magna Carta proclaimed, as its first article, ‘That We have granted to God, and by this present charter have confirmed for us and our heirs in perpetuity, that the English Church shall be free, and shall have its rights undiminished, and its liberties unimpaired.’Footnote 1 This was intended to protect the established Catholic Church from the powers of the state, specifically from interference in church elections by the executive in the form of the person of the monarch. The notion that religions were institutions with practices and beliefs that were outside the control of the state in certain respects was adopted by the common law and is found in modern times in the principle of non-justiciability on the matter of religion in certain types of civil case.Footnote 2
In recent years, the position has been summarised as ‘the courts will not attempt to rule upon doctrinal issues or intervene in the regulation or governance of religious groups’.Footnote 3 Also:
Religion … is not the business of government or of the secular courts … The starting point of the law is an essentially agnostic view of religious beliefs and a tolerant indulgence to religious and cultural diversity … It is not for a judge to weigh one religion against another. All are entitled to equal respect.Footnote 4
This non-interference has been described as both active, ‘through the express grant and preservation of rights of self-determination, self-governance and self-regulation’, and passive,
through non-interference on the part of organs of State such as national government local or regional government or the secular courts. In the United Kingdom there is no systematic provision made for autonomy of religious organizations and, in the main, a self-denying ordinance of neutrality may be said to predominate.Footnote 5
One area of law where the passive conception has been particularly adopted is in the law of defamation. This is, perhaps, surprising: many religions specifically proscribe libel and particularly slander as forms of wrongdoing. In the Bible, the Psalmist prays, ‘Set a watch, O Lord, before my mouth; and a door round about my lips.’Footnote 6 The Book of Proverbs warns, ‘Lying lips conceal hatred, and whoever utters slander is a fool’ and ‘Do not slander a servant to a master, or the servant will curse you and you will be held guilty.’Footnote 7 St Matthew records Jesus telling his listeners, ‘I tell you, on the day of judgement you will have to give an account for every careless word you utter’.Footnote 8
Despite these injunctions, English law, which has otherwise been so deeply rooted in Christian principle, does not reflect this prohibition when it comes to the matter of religion and libel, as it did until recently with blasphemy and as it does with defamation generally.Footnote 9 This is partly the cultural product of the Reformation. The sectarian violence of the period gradually gave way to the acceptance of religious difference in the liberal state, which had neither the knowledge nor the desire to investigate the truth of what were ultimately profound differences in belief between catholic, Anglican and non-conformist theology.Footnote 10 How could a court decide when a catholic labelled a protestant a heretic, for instance, or when one Methodist described another as schismatic? When the courts did intervene, it was only because of the implied or explicit accusation of another wrong that accompanied a religious libel. It was, for instance, once an actionable libel to call a person a ‘papist’ and allege that he or she went to Mass, because of the imputation of criminality and disloyalty that was implied by the accusation.Footnote 11 However, this must surely no longer be the case.
DEFAMATION ACTIONS IN RELIGIOUS CONTEXTS AND THE SCREENING EFFECT OF DEFAMATION LAW
Defamation law applied to religion is unstable and, as both a cause and a symptom of the cultural shift towards freer speech, this law has itself changed markedly in very recent years. Before the question of non-justiciability is considered by a court, two hurdles must be crossed by any prospective claimant, both of which act to sift out potential religious libels.
First, the claimant must show that what has been published about him or her is defamatory. The test for what is defamatory is a creature of the common law and has adapted to changing social tastes. Gradually, public opinion has changed and it is clearly no longer the case today that, in England, being Catholic carries the same implied sting in the minds of the public.Footnote 12 Currently, a meaning is defamatory of the claimant if it ‘substantially affects in an adverse manner the attitude of other people towards him, or has a tendency to do so’.Footnote 13 The test is objective – what does the ordinary reasonable reader think of the publication being complained of? – and is not dependent on the reactions of a special class of listener, such as a claimant's co-religionists.Footnote 14 In many cases, religious libels would no longer be considered defamatory by the objective test (today represented by the tastes of the judiciary) and thus would fail to be claims at all. Accusations that would harm only in the eyes of adherents to a certain faith, such as the holding of unorthodox doctrinal views, or breaches of rules about diet or sexual conduct which are specific to the community but not shared widely, would not be defamatory by the objective measure.
Second, as part of the pendulum's swing away from the right to reputation and towards free expression, the coming into force of the Defamation Act 2013 introduced the hurdle of proving a statement has caused or is likely to cause ‘serious harm’ to the reputation of the claimant.Footnote 15 The application of this measure is still unsettled, but the burden is on the claimant to show that section 1 has been satisfied on the balance of probabilities, taking into account the defamatory meaning, the harmful tendency of that meaning and ‘all relevant circumstances’, including evidence of what actually happened after publication, proven by evidence or, in cases of obvious harm, inference.Footnote 16
If a published libel or slander is objectively defamatory and causes or tends to cause serious harm, there may be a defence to publication. The 2013 Act has reformulated some of the substantial defences to a claim for libel in the new statutory defences of truth, honest opinion and publication on matter of public interest, has introduced new defences and has extended existing ones.Footnote 17
The question then arises: what if a purportedly religious libel is published, such as an accusation of heresy, that has an implied and pleaded meaning of fraud (which is defamatory and which can be shown to cause or tend to cause serious harm to its subject) and the defendant argues that the accusation of heresy is in fact true, or an honest opinion that he or she holds? Given the filters on defamation claims, such a scenario will be a rare occurrence but not impossible. The court would be faced with determining the truth of the heresy – and thus whether or not competing versions of religious faith are true – in considering the allegation of truth of the allegation of fraud. This is where the claimant has until now faced a third hurdle: the principle of non-justiciability, which relies fundamentally on how the defamatory allegation is linked to the underlying religious matter.
It has been suggested that there are four types of dispute that include a ‘religious dimension’.Footnote 18 The first is general criticism of religions, which, if deemed offensive to followers of the religion, may be caught by group defamation or blasphemy laws. General criticism of a religion does not found an action for libel, however, unless a particular follower can establish that the criticism applies to him or her.Footnote 19 Another type of case is when specific allegations are made against particular individuals alleging that they have failed to meet prescribed standards or expectations of behaviour: for example, that they have sinned against the religion. But individuals impugned in this way are perhaps more likely to use internal dispute resolutions than secular courts, in a bid to stay within the organisation.Footnote 20
There are two further sorts of religious dispute which have historically led to libel actions that invoke the secular law. These are when general criticisms are made of a religion coupled with specific, associated criticism of a particular person such that they can sue, or when criticism of the religion is made without a basis in religious doctrine. These forms are distinguished from each other by asking ‘whether or not the imputations at issue rest upon a doctrinal dispute’.Footnote 21
There are many examples of allegations being made without a basis in religious doctrine, as noted above, almost all of which would not be actionable torts today.Footnote 22 It has been held defamatory to state of an archbishop of the Church of Ireland that he has attempted to convert a Catholic priest to protestantism by an offer of £1,000 in cash and a living of £800 a year,Footnote 23 or to state of a clergyman that he is guilty of immorality or drunkenness,Footnote 24 or that he preaches seditionFootnote 25 or lies,Footnote 26 or that he knows less about his religion than an adolescent,Footnote 27 or that he has used his pulpit to throw out personal invectives against a member of the congregation,Footnote 28 or that he has juggled with the collectionsFootnote 29 or that he has desecrated a part of his church by turning it into a cooking department.Footnote 30 Indeed, the religious context of an accusation has been taken into account, even if the action is without a basis in religious in doctrine.Footnote 31 If the allegation is that a clergyman preached false doctrine it will be defamatory if, in the circumstances, it imputed hypocrisy. But if the defendant belongs to a different church from the claimant and the churches are in disagreement about the doctrine, it will not be an actionable tort.Footnote 32 This key distinction is at the heart of the non-justiciability problem.
The UK Supreme Court decision in Shergill and others v Khaira and others (‘Khaira’) presents a challenge to the principle of non-justiciability in the case of religious defamation, and lowers the third hurdle.Footnote 33 In the unanimous view of the Court, the application of the principle in the case of Blake v Associated Newspapers Ltd Footnote 34 was ‘not … correct’. Courts should not decline jurisdiction purely on the grounds of religion, even if they raise questions of doctrine and ecclesiology, if the claim is grounded in a valid cause of action such as libel: ‘the court will enter into questions of disputed doctrine if it is necessary to do so in reference to civil interests’.Footnote 35 This decision ostensibly gives the court jurisdiction to decide deep questions of religion and opens to claimants the right to vindicate their reputation when previously such an action would have been denied to them. However, this boon for claimants may be countered by an extension of the defence of honest opinion for defendants, as the Supreme Court itself notes.Footnote 36
THE KHAIRA LITIGATION IN THE LOWER COURTS
Khaira was one of a number of suits (along with Baba Jeet v Singh Footnote 37 and Shergill v Purewal Footnote 38) that stemmed from the overspill into the Sikh community in the UK of a dispute in India.Footnote 39 The underlying dispute concerned the declaration of a mahant, or religious superior of a dera (monastery) in the Punjab, known in proceedings as the First Holy Saint, that he was a living guru and so a religious leader of great importance to Sikhs. The order he founded, the Nirmal Kutia Johal, set up three gurdwaras in the UK: in Bradford, Birmingham and High Wycombe. He died in 2001 and was succeeded in short order by the Second and then Third Holy Saint.Footnote 40
In Khaira, eight of the appellants contended that they had been validly appointed as trustees of the three gurdwaras by the Third Holy Saint. They sought declarations that this was done under the relevant trust deeds, which allowed the First Holy Saint ‘and his successor’ to remove and appoint trustees. The respondents, the original trustees of the gurdwaras, argued that the Third Holy Saint had no power to remove and appointed trustees of the gurdwaras.
The judge at first instance dismissed the defendants' application for strike out on the grounds of non-justiciability, considering that the legal question of the construction of the deeds required
not an establishment of the propriety or the validity of a process by which the [Third Holy Saint] may have succeeded to come to be regarded as holding the office of Holy Saint but whether, as a matter of fact, he has become sufficiently recognised as the holder of that office to be considered to be a person described as having a particular power in the English deed, the construction of which is before the court.Footnote 41
If the Third Holy Saint was accepted as de facto ‘successor’ by a sufficient number of adherents of the Nirmal Kutia Johal, even if a minority disagreed, then that would be enough to make appropriate findings of fact and construe the documents accordingly.
The Court of Appeal was invited to reject this approach on a number of bases, including whether the standpoint adopted by the judge, which purported to be objective, from the perspective of English law and without a view on Sikh doctrine or practice, was skewed in accepting that the Third Holy Saint could be de facto ‘successor’ without being de jure ‘successor’ to the First Holy Saint in the eyes of the Sikh religion.Footnote 42
In Mummery LJ's view (giving the sole judgment, joined by Hooper and Pitchford LJJ), the decision in Buttes Gas and Oil v Hammer (No 3) Footnote 43 was sufficient authority for the proposition that, if a purportedly secular dispute on the construction of a deed in English law turned fundamentally on a dispute on religious doctrine, the absence of ‘judicial or manageable standards by which to judge these issues’ put the matter outside the jurisdiction of the courts.Footnote 44 Contrary to the claimants' plea that there was a ‘bond of union’ (a contract or agreement) between the parties that provided sufficient objective standards, this was a case where ‘judicial self-restraint’ was required, as the subject matter of the religious dispute defied resolution by ‘analysing evidence, or by finding facts on the balance of probability, or by counting heads, or by ascertaining the wishes of a voting majority’.Footnote 45 The deeds themselves did not provide any way to consider the meaning of ‘successor’ without delving into the religious dispute, ‘essentially a matter of professed subjective belief and faith on which secular municipal courts cannot possibly reach a decision, either as a matter of law or fact … This court should put a halt to this case now.’Footnote 46
KHAIRA IN THE SUPREME COURT
The single judgment in the Supreme Court differed from Mummery LJ's understanding of Buttes Gas. That case was non-justiciable because it was inherently political and involved the transactions of foreign sovereign states: ‘it trespassed on the proper province of the executive, as the organ of the state charged with the conduct of foreign relations’, as well as the lack of ‘judicial or manageable standards’ as Mummery LJ identified, making it ‘difficult to imagine that such a conclusion could have been reached in any other context than the policy acts of sovereign states, for the acts of private parties, however political, are subject to law’.Footnote 47 The implication here is that, although religious matters may fall under the second quality of political matters, they do not fall under the first, and thus there is no inherent non-justiciability in matters of religion.
A case is non-justiciable ‘where an issue is said to be inherently unsuitable for judicial determination by reason only of its subject matter’, for two reasons.Footnote 48 First, there was a ‘rare’ class of disputes where the issue was beyond the ‘constitutional competence assigned to the courts under our conception of the separation of powers’; once the ‘forbidden’ area was identified, including certain transactions of foreign states and of proceedings in Parliament, the court could not adjudicate on matters within it, even if necessary to decide some other justiciable issue (if it ‘inhibits the defence of a claim, this may make it necessary to strike out an otherwise justiciable claim on the ground that it cannot be fairly tried’).Footnote 49 The court also proposed a second, ‘quite different’ basis for non-justiciability: ‘claims or defences which are based neither on private legal rights or obligations, nor on reviewable matters of public law’, such as ‘domestic disputes, transactions not intended by the participants to affect their legal relations, and [certain] issues of international law’. Disputes in this category may, however, be entertained by ‘reluctant’ courts if a legal right is engaged.Footnote 50
The Court cited a Canadian Supreme Court case, where a promise to obtain a Jewish religious divorce made by a husband to his wife was enforceable as a civil contract and was not merely a religious and moral obligation, in support of the proposition that the court is ‘not barred from considering a question of a religious nature, provided that the claim is based on the violation of a rule recognized in positive law’.Footnote 51 The Court then set out the limited instances in which this might happen. A line of English and Scots law cases shows how, ‘where a claimant asks the court to enforce private rights and obligations which depend on religious issues, the judge may have to determine such religious issues as are capable of objective ascertainment’.Footnote 52 These include questions of religious belief and practice where the court's jurisdiction is invoked either (a) to enforce the contractual rights of members of a community against other members or its governing body or (b) to ensure that property held on trust is used for the purposes of the trust.
Examples given of (a) include unincorporated religious communities treated as voluntary associations bound by contracts, or where religious associations act ultra vires their constitution or an Act of Parliament (for instance in joining with another church), otherwise breaching ‘in a fundamental way the rules of procedures’, or in dismissing or disciplining their members.Footnote 53 Examples of (b) include a series of property cases, from 1813 to 2011, in which the courts exercised jurisdiction in disputes caused by religious disagreements over the ownership of property, particularly where, as a result of schisms, parties disputed who had the beneficial interest in property held in trust for the community.Footnote 54 This required the ascertainment of the ‘foundational and essential tenets of a faith in order to identify who was entitled to the property’, superseding the previous rule, found at least in Scotland, that the courts would ‘simply give effect to the majority rule within the religious community’.Footnote 55 English courts have not resiled from assessing Islamic and Hindu doctrine in similar cases.Footnote 56 The limit of the court's inquiry was emphasised in Overtoun as restricted to determining ‘whether the trusts imposed upon property by the founders of the trust are being duly observed’ and not assessing ‘the truth or reasonableness of any of the doctrines’ of the faith.Footnote 57
The Supreme Court also rejected two bases of non-justiciability of religious disputes. The first related to public law. The well-known decision in ex parte Wachmann,Footnote 58 that the Chief Rabbi's decision that the applicant was not religiously and morally fit to hold office as a rabbi did not raise an issue of public law which was amenable to judicial review, was ‘not an authority for a proposition that the legality of such disciplinary proceedings is not justiciable’.Footnote 59
In Wachmann the court declined jurisdiction because the respondent was not a reviewable body, exercising functions ‘essentially intimate, spiritual, and religious – functions which the government could not and would not seek to discharge in his place were he to abdicate his regulatory responsibility’, and the decision was not reviewable as to do so would ‘inevitably’ draw the court into ‘adjudicating upon matters intimate to a religious community’.Footnote 60 The appellant had anticipated this objection and was ‘prepared to rely solely upon the common law concept of natural justice’ in his appeal, without relying on Jewish law. Simon Brown J rejected this on the grounds that ‘it would not always be easy to separate out procedural complaints from consideration of substantive principles of Jewish law which may underlie them’, and concluded, ‘The court must inevitably be wary of entering so self-evidently sensitive an area, straying across the well-recognised divide between church and state.’Footnote 61
The implication in the Supreme Court's consideration of Wachmann is that it was the absence of any cause of action on the ‘government function’ test in public law that defeated the claim – the first reason given by Simon Brown J – and not the second, which alone would not have been enough to defeat a claim ‘presented as a challenge to the contractual jurisdiction of a voluntary association’, where the court had jurisdiction to consider questions of ultra vires and allegations of breaches of natural justice.Footnote 62
THE COURT‘S TREATMENT OF BLAKE
The second basis rejected by the Supreme Court was that found in the grounds of Blake v Associated Newspapers Limited,Footnote 63 a case concerning a former Anglican clergyman who purported to conduct a same-sex marriage on a TV programme. Two pieces in the Daily Mail commented on the programme and described him variously as a ‘self-styled’ and ‘imitation’ bishop with a ‘costume mitre’.Footnote 64 In his claim for libel, Mr Blake pleaded that the articles alleged he was not validly consecrated nor entitled to call himself a bishop, although he ‘masqueraded’ as one, and that he was ‘publicly and dishonestly’ imitating a bishop, thereby setting out to deceive the public.Footnote 65
The publishers of the Mail disagreed with the precise meanings borne by the articles, but pleaded that ‘in all the circumstances C is an imitation bishop’. It sought to defend the articles using the defences of justification and/or fair comment.Footnote 66 After the exchange of pleadings and witness statements – the statements of the claimant and his witnesses were ‘redolent with doctrinal, procedural, jurisdictional and historical arguments in favour of validity of his consecration’Footnote 67 – the judge decided that the pleaded issues were within the ‘territory which the courts, by self-denying ordinance, will not enter’.Footnote 68
Gray J then moved on to consider whether the action should be stayed or proceed to trial, with perhaps some ‘adaptation of the issues as they stand at present’.Footnote 69 The claimant argued that underlying the doctrinal issue as to the validity of his consecration was a ‘secular issue’ that could be appropriately determined by the courts: whether the claimant had ‘in historical fact’ been consecrated as a bishop.Footnote 70 The claimant's expert opined that the claimant had been ‘clearly’ consecrated as a matter of historical fact, and that this was within ‘a valid historical succession’, albeit one that might not be recognised by other churches. The complained-of articles wholly neglected this context, generating the misleading impression that he was an impostor.Footnote 71 The defendant countered that non-justiciable religious issues were so ‘fundamental’ that the action could not be fairly tried.Footnote 72 Gray J, who acknowledged that a stay should only be granted in the most extreme circumstances as it would deny the claimant the opportunity of establishing his good name in the courts, concluded that the issues in the action could not be adapted to ‘circumvent the insuperable obstacle placed in the way of a fair trial’.Footnote 73 He suggested that the claimant, whom he found ‘understandably somewhat reluctant to abandon his claim to have been validly consecrated’, should make a ‘modified version of the secular issue’ the basis of the claim, before noting the sheer quantity and depth of issues in the case that came within the ‘forbidden’ territory of non-justiciability:
Such questions include, by way of example only, substantive doctrinal questions including the canon law of catholic apostolic churches, questions of ecclesiastic procedure such as the authority and entitlement of Richard Palmer to consecrate the Claimant and the validity (in the absence at the time of any denomination or established church) of the consecration of the Claimant; questions whether the consecration of the Claimant was in conformity with the customs and practices of any established Christian denomination or criteria independently of POEM [the claimant's order] and finally questions as to the moral standing and fitness of both Richard Palmer and the Claimant for episcopal office.Footnote 74
THE IMPACT OF KHAIRA ON DEFAMATION CASES
The Supreme Court does not in Khaira explain precisely why the decision in Blake was incorrect; the thrust of its criticism is that, because a private right was engaged, the claim should have proceeded to trial, even if that required the determination of religious doctrine, in order to give legal effect to the claimant's private rights. This is indicated by the fact that the Court was happy to remit a number of difficult questions about the dispute back for trial by the lower courts, including on the fundamental tenets of the First Holy Saint and the Nirmal sect, the nature of the institution at Nirmal Kutia in India, the steps or formalities that were needed for a person to become the successor of the First Holy Saint, and whether the teachings and personal qualities of the Third Holy Saint complied with the fundamental religious aims and purposes of the trust.Footnote 75
On this basis, the Court could have criticised other recent decisions applying the ‘fundamental and inseparable’ test to religious doctrine. Similar matters arose in the parallel defamation proceedings in Baba Jeet v Singh and Shergill v Purewal. In Baba Jeet, the Third Holy Saint claimed that an article in the Sikh Times about the Nirmal Sikh faith damaged his reputation in the UK because it alleged that he was the leader of a ‘cult’ and an impostor who disturbed the peace in the Sikh community generally and in High Wycombe, that he had dishonestly produced counterfeit trust deeds to remove the gurdwara trustees and management committee there and that he promoted blasphemy and the sexual exploitation and abuse of women.Footnote 76 In Purewal, the first claimant in Khaira brought a libel action against another Sikh newspaper, the Punjab Times, and against a journalist for three articles that attacked the Third Holy Saint and his followers, including some of the trustee appointees. The articles claimed that the Third Holy Saint had abandoned Sikh principles, that he and his supporters were a ‘sham’ and that the claimant had sought to instigate violence.Footnote 77
Both actions were stayed at preliminary issues hearings because issues of religion and doctrine permeated the pleadings and the courts did not consider it within their jurisdiction to determine the religious questions. For instance, the issue in Baba Jeet of whether the claimant was an ‘impostor’ could not be isolated and resolved without reference to Sikh doctrines and traditions.Footnote 78 And the issues in Purewal, such as whether the Third Holy Saint was the legitimate successor to the sainthood, were ‘fundamental’ to the case, making it ‘impossible to adapt the issues in such a way as to circumvent the insuperable obstacle placed in the way of a fair trial of the action by the fact that the court is bound to abstain from determining questions which lie at the heart of the case’.Footnote 79 Applying Khaira, it is likely that both cases should have gone to trial given the engagement of the claimants’ private law rights. Nothing distinguishes either from Blake.
The same is true of Otuo, where all three prior defamation cases were considered alongside the Court of Appeal judgment in Khaira (HHJ Moloney was ‘cautious’ of Wachmann and thought that the defamation cases were ‘taken on their particular facts’Footnote 80). Otuo was a Jehovah's Witness who, after an internal inquiry into allegations of misconduct, was ‘dis-fellowshipped’ from the membership, with an announcement made to the congregation that he was ‘no longer one of Jehovah's Witnesses’.Footnote 81 The judge did not find this to have a defamatory meaning naturally and ordinarily, but deferred the question of innuendo.Footnote 82
The claimant argued that the allegations would be decided on a secular basis by the court, on the question of whether he was guilty of fraud and whether the defendant's elders were actuated by express malice towards him.Footnote 83 Unlike other cases, the parties were
in agreement on the creed of their religion, on what is or is not forbidden to its members, and even on what procedures should be adopted to inquire into misconduct and what steps it is proper to take in respect of those found guilty. There may be doctrinal issues involved … but if there are they have not yet been clearly pleaded or put into evidence.Footnote 84
The parties differed in whether the defendant's procedures were applied honestly and fairly to the claimant. The judge concluded that the action lay on the ‘borderline’ between justiciability and non-justiciability, and the application to strike out had been brought ‘prematurely and should be dismissed on that sole ground’.Footnote 85
It seems that the Supreme Court has subverted the basis for these decisions. Being founded on a religious dispute does not disqualify a legal dispute as non-justiciable per se, whether or not the claim can be reframed in secular terms (it does if it is purely a religious dispute, however). This potentially makes matters fairer for both sides. On the one hand, this will be an advantage for claimants, making it more likely that they obtain vindication of their reputation at the end of a trial. On the other hand, it allows defendants more room to fight the case, for, as the judge said in Blake, had the case proceeded
the newspaper would still wish to advance the case that the consecration service had no religious or ecclesiastic validity, so that it was in effect a charade, and that to prevent the newspaper from advancing this case would be manifestly unfair and a serious invasion of its Article 10 right.Footnote 86
Awkwardly, the Court, through its support for Lord Davey's prohibition in Overtoun, appears not to permit courts to decide the ‘truth’ of religious doctrines.Footnote 87 It seems doubly unfair on the defendant if defamation claims underlain by religious disputes are justiciable but the truth of the religious dispute cannot be contemplated in its own terms nor re-pleaded in wholly non-doctrinal ones. It will be interesting to see whether, following Khaira, there is still a domain of religious dispute where the defendant cannot justify his comments as true because courts will recoil from attempting to decide what objective truth is in relation to religion.
A solution (or at least a ‘preferable means of accommodating religion in the law of libel’Footnote 88) may lie in the defence of honest opinion. The Supreme Court alluded in Khaira to the previous formulation of the defence in Spiller v Joseph.Footnote 89 If a statement can show that it is an expression of opinion which indicates its factual basis and could be held by an honest person on the basis of any fact that existed at the time, it will be honest opinion. If breadth is given to the class of facts which underpins the factual basis of the opinion, it may include allusion to or representation of the very dispute which lies at the heart of, say, an allegation of heresy. This would not give the defendant the same protection as a strike-out of the claim on the basis of non-justiciability, ‘an absolute privilege which has never been recognised and could easily be abused’,Footnote 90 but it would provide critics and commentators with a safer defence, provided that they refer to the doctrinal dispute in their publication. It would, in effect, extended the concept of privilege, already acknowledged in the honest opinion defence, beyond its established domains of absolute and qualified privilege, and re-balance the scales of justice between the parties in religious defamation disputes.
CONCLUSION
Khaira does more than ‘shift … the boundary slightly and enlarge the circumstances in which the court will feel able to intervene’Footnote 91 or merely ‘push the door of non-justiciability open by a crack’.Footnote 92 It potentially heralds a return to what has been described as the ‘nineteenth-century’ concept of non-justiciability, where judges sought ‘neutrality’ and detachedness by ‘pointing out that it was no role of a court of law to act as a religious insider delivering “correct” answers to the underlying substantive theological or ecclesiological dispute between the parties’ but would ‘regularly proceed to point out that questions of doctrine and discipline might well be relevant as questions of fact to determine the outcome of the case’ through the use of evidence.Footnote 93
Particularly given the willingness of courts to widen the legal definition of a religion, for instance to the Church of Scientology,Footnote 94 it is hard to disagree with Singh that there is likely to be a rise in defamation cases involving religion, more of which will be deemed justiciable.Footnote 95 There has even been an attempt at a private prosecution on the basis of the ‘untruth’ of the Mormon faith.Footnote 96 More cases will involve religions other than Christianity, as new religious movements use threats of libel to silence critics.Footnote 97 Many will welcome the decision in Khaira.