1. Introduction
On 7 March 2014, Trial Chamber II of the International Criminal Court (ICC) convicted Germain Katanga for war crimes and crimes against humanity, sentencing him to 12 years of imprisonment.Footnote 1 A few months later, both Katanga and the Prosecutor dropped their appeals against the verdict and the Trial Chamber judgment became final.Footnote 2 Katanga's conviction is based on common purpose liability as stipulated in Article 25(3)(d) of the Rome Statute. Broadly speaking, common purpose liability establishes responsibility for wilfully or knowingly contributing to the crimes of a group of persons acting with a common purpose.Footnote 3
According to the ICC, common purpose liability establishes ‘the lowest objective threshold for participation according to article 25’.Footnote 4 Furthermore, it is not required that ‘the accused shared the group's intentions to commit the crime’.Footnote 5 Considering these lenient objective and subjective standards, the Court regards common purpose liability as a residual mode of liability that constitutes a lower level of blameworthiness than other liability theories, such as joint perpetration.Footnote 6 Indeed, the requirements of common purpose liability in theory set a relatively low threshold of criminal responsibility. However, when we analyze how the ICC has applied common purpose liability in practice, it appears that the Court takes a flexible, context-dependent approach, which takes account of the specific facts of individual cases. This raises the question of whether common purpose liability by definition creates a residual type of criminal responsibility and whether the persons contributing to a common purpose are necessarily less blameworthy than other participants.
In this article, I examine the meaning and status of common purpose liability by comparing this liability theory to joint perpetration. The comparison between common purpose liability and joint perpetration is particularly useful, since joint perpetration constitutes the counterpart of common purpose liability – it is viewed as a principal liability theory that captures the responsibility of senior political and military figures who mastermind international crimes.Footnote 7 Rather than characterizing common purpose liability and joint perpetration exclusively in terms of abstract legal standards, I assess how the ICC has applied these standards to the facts of individual cases. This allows me to ascertain whether the actus reus and mens rea requirements of common purpose liability are employed in such a lenient way that common purpose liability can be deemed to establish a lower degree of criminal responsibility than joint perpetration.
The article is structured as follows. In Section 2, I set out the debate on the ICC's hierarchical construction of liability theories based on the notion of ‘control over the crime’. In Section 3, I analyze the law in theory, in particular the ICC's interpretation of the actus reus and mens rea requirements of common purpose liability and joint perpetration. Section 4 reflects upon this analysis by assessing the law in practice, i.e., the way in which the ICC has applied the requirements of common purpose liability and joint perpetration in individual cases. In Section 5, I conclude that the ICC has applied common purpose liability and joint perpetration in a context-dependent way in interplay with case-specific facts. Accordingly, it cannot be maintained that common purpose liability by definition establishes a lower degree of blameworthiness than joint perpetration. Moreover, the Court's practice does not support the conclusion that the liability theories in Article 25(3) are structured in a hierarchical way according to their level of responsibility.
2. Hierarchy of liability theories
Article 25(3) of the Rome Statute lists a number of liability theories, which stipulate different ways of committing and participating in the commission of international crimes.Footnote 8 The provision specifies that individuals can be held responsible for perpetrating a crime, either directly, indirectly, or jointly with another (subparagraph a); ordering, soliciting, or inducing the commission of a crime (subparagraph b); aiding, abetting, or otherwise assisting the commission of a crime (subparagraph c); and – finally – for contributing to a group acting with a common purpose (subparagraph d).
The ICC divides these liability theories into principal forms of perpetration (subparagraph a) and accessorial forms of participation (subparagraph (b)-(d)). According to the Court, the distinction between principal and accessorial liability is not merely terminological,Footnote 9 but also entails ‘a value-oriented hierarchy’.Footnote 10 This means that ‘the forms of perpetration in subparagraph (a) prevail over the other forms of (secondary) participation (subparagraphs (b)-(d)) in terms of the level of responsibility of the perpetrators and the blame to be imposed on them’.Footnote 11 The Lubanga Appeals Chamber has accordingly held that:
[g]enerally speaking and all other things being equal, a person who is found to commit a crime him- or herself [under subparagraph (a)] bears more blameworthiness than a person who contributes to the crime of another person or persons [under subparagraph (b)-(d)].Footnote 12
Moreover, the ICC maintains that the different forms of accessorial liability are hierarchically structured inter se.Footnote 13 This means that common purpose liability will only be used when the accused cannot be held responsible for ordering, soliciting, or aiding and abetting crimes.Footnote 14 Hence, common purpose liability ‘is triggered only when subparagraphs (a)-(c) are not satisfied’.Footnote 15
The hierarchical ordering of liability theories requires the formulation of a guiding principle that differentiates perpetrators from accessories. According to the ICC, this principle must entail a normative assessment of the accused's role.Footnote 16 On this account, the Court has found that only persons who have control over crimes by exercising the power to decide whether and how a crime is committed, can be qualified as principal perpetrators -- all others are ‘mere’ accessories.Footnote 17 Thus, the level of control (implicitly) becomes the decisive factor for determining the accused's degree of responsibility:
[c]harging defendants . . . under 25(3)(a) means that they played a central role, that they had “control of the crime”. This is contrasted to liability under subparagraphs 25(3)(b–d) where control plays no role and accessories are regarded as less responsible and less blameworthy.Footnote 18
The ICC's linkage between the accused's level of control and his degree of blameworthiness has generated extensive legal debate. In this respect, practitioners and commentators generally concede the conceptual distinction between principals who commit a crime and accessories who contribute to the crimes of others:Footnote 19 whilst principals are responsible in their own right, the responsibility of accessories is derivative of – i.e., dependent on – the commission of a crime by a principal. The majority of the Katanga Trial Chamber has accordingly clarified that the principals’ conduct constitutes the commission of crimes, whereas the contribution of accessories is only connected to the commission of crimes by others.Footnote 20
Having said that, it is not self-evident that the distinction between the commission of crimes and the contribution to crimes of others carries normative weight in the sense that the former connotes a more serious degree of liability than the latter. Various commentators have raised critique against equating accessorial liability to lesser liability.Footnote 21 For example, Ohlin, Van Sliedregt and Weigend have argued that there is no rule or theory stipulating that accessorial liability automatically constitutes a mitigated form of criminal responsibility.Footnote 22 Likewise, the majority of the Katanga Trial Chamber has dismissed prior ICC case law in which Article 25(3) was interpreted in a hierarchical way. According to the majority,
the distinction between perpetrator of and accessory to a crime inheres in the Statute but does not, nonetheless, entail a hierarchy, whether in respect of guilt or penalty. Each mode of liability has different characteristics and legal ramifications which reflect various forms of involvement in criminality. However, this does not necessarily signify that accused persons will be found less culpable or will incur a lesser penalty.Footnote 23
By reasoning in this way, the majority in Katanga has endorsed the minority views that were previously expressed by Judges Fulford and Van den Wyngaert in the Lubanga and Ngudjolo cases, respectively. In her concurring opinion to the Ngudjolo Trial Chamber judgment, Judge Van den Wyngaert has stressed that the conceptual difference between principal and accessorial responsibility does not necessarily entail a different level of blameworthiness: ‘[t]he fact that principals are connected more directly to the bringing about of the material elements of the crime than accessories does not imply that the role of the former should be regarded as inherently more blameworthy’.Footnote 24
Similarly, Judge Fulford has asserted in his separate opinion to the Lubanga Trial Chamber judgment that it is impossible and unhelpful ‘to establish a hierarchy of seriousness that is dependent on creating rigorous distinctions between the modes of liability within Article 25(3)’.Footnote 25 He has therefore argued that persons who contribute to the common purpose of a group are not necessarily less responsible than aiders and abettors, especially ‘since many of history's most serious crimes occurred as the result of the coordinated action of groups of individuals, who jointly pursued a common goal’.Footnote 26 However, as of yet, this remains the minority view. The majority of ICC judges continues to embrace the hierarchical construction of liability theories.Footnote 27
3. Common purpose liability and joint perpetration in theory
Common purpose liability and joint perpetration entail three analogous requirements. Both liability theories stipulate that the accused: (i) made a contribution; (ii) to a common plan; (iii) with a criminal state of mind. In interpreting these requirements, the ICC has made an effort to clearly distinguish joint perpetration from common purpose liability by emphasizing that the former sets significantly higher thresholds than the latter.
3.1. Contribution to Crimes
Taking as a starting point that the joint perpetrator is a principal who controls the commission of crimes, ICC case law requires that joint perpetrators made an ‘essential contribution’ to the commission of crimes, which resulted in the realization of the objective elements of the crimes charged. The essential contribution standard is met when the accused had the power to frustrate the commission of crimes by withholding his assigned tasks.Footnote 28 As Weigend explains, the negative formulation of this criterion entails a ‘hypothetical judgment about how things would have turned out without the actor's contribution, and in that respect necessarily contains a speculative element’.Footnote 29
The accused's essential contribution does not have to be committed at the execution stage, nor must there be a direct physical link between the accused's contribution and the commission of crimes.Footnote 30 Instead, a joint perpetrator may ‘compensate’ for his absence at the crime scene by contributing to the planning of crimes, by supplying weapons or ammunition, or by directing and coordinating troops from a distance.Footnote 31 The contributions of joint perpetrators can thus be quite remote in time and place from the actual physical perpetration of crimes. By interpreting the actus reus element of joint perpetration in such a broad way, the ICC allows for qualifying senior political and military figures who operate from a distant position as principal perpetrators.Footnote 32 Whilst this practice gives apt expression to the central role of those in leadership positions, it raises questions as to what room remains for other forms of criminal responsibility, such as common purpose liability.Footnote 33
In relation to common purpose liability, Article 25(3)(d) of the Rome Statute stipulates that the accused contributed to the commission of crimes by a group of persons ‘in any other way’.Footnote 34 At first sight, this use of terms reflects a low standard, which is even met by small, immaterial and indirect contributions. Ohlin has therefore warned that whilst many persons may contribute to group crimes – for example, by selling food, water and clothing to criminals – qualifying all these contributions as a basis for criminal responsibility constitutes ‘a significant example of legislative over-reaching’.Footnote 35
Arguing along similar lines, the Mbarushimana Pre-Trial Chamber (PTC) has conceded that common purpose liability will be overextended if any infinitesimal contribution of a grocer, utility provider, or janitor satisfies the contribution requirement of Article 25(3)(d).Footnote 36 The PTC has therefore required that the accused makes a significant contribution to crimes.Footnote 37 The significant contribution standard allegedly sets as a lower threshold of participation than the essential contribution standard of joint perpetration.Footnote 38 It entails that the accused was able to influence the occurrence of crimes, without demanding that the commission of crimes depended on the accused's contribution. Footnote 39
The question of whether an accused influenced the commission of crimes must be answered on a case-by-case basis in light of the specific circumstances of the case under consideration.Footnote 40 According to the majority in Katanga, this assessment should focus on the effect of the accused's conduct, rather than on the direct nexus between the accused and the crimes committed.Footnote 41 Furthermore, the majority has stressed that the accused's contribution needs to relate to the commission of crimes specifically and that the accused can only be held responsible for crimes to which he contributed.Footnote 42 In her separate opinion to the Katanga judgment, Judge Van den Wyngaert has added to this finding that:
when assessing the significance of someone's contribution, there are good reasons for analyzing whether someone's assistance is specifically directed to the criminal or noncriminal part of a group's activities. Indeed, this may be particularly useful to determine whether particular generic contributions – i.e. contributions that, by their nature, could equally have contributed to a legitimate purpose – are criminal or not.Footnote 43
3.2. Criminal Intent
ICC case law defines the mental elements of joint perpetration in a rather complex way. Basically, proof is required that the accused carried out the subjective elements of the crimes with which he is charged and that he knew that the implementation of his plans would result in the commission of the indicted crimes.Footnote 44 Furthermore, the accused must have been aware that he made an essential contribution to the crimes for which he stands trial.Footnote 45 The threshold for these subjective elements is specified in Article 30 of the Rome Statute, which stipulates that – unless otherwise provided – the accused must either mean to commit the crimes or be at least aware that his actions will lead to the commission of crimes in the ordinary course of events.Footnote 46
The Lubanga PTC has initially considered that Article 30 does not only encompass situations in which the accused meant to bring about the objective elements of the crimes charged (dolus directus of the first degree) or knew that the commission of these crimes would be the necessary outcome of his acts (dolus directus of the second degree).Footnote 47 Rather, the PTC decided that Article 30 also includes situations in which the accused was aware of the risk that his actions may or could lead to the commission of crimes (dolus eventualis).Footnote 48 This broad interpretation has been rejected in later judgments and decisions.Footnote 49 It is now generally accepted that joint perpetrators must have known that crimes would occur in the ordinary course of events as a result of their actions.Footnote 50 This requires that the commission of crimes was a virtual certainty or an ‘almost inevitable outcome’.Footnote 51
In contrast to joint perpetration, common purpose liability does not require that the accused intended to commit crimes or fulfilled the mental elements of the crimes charged. Instead, it suffices to establish that: (i) the accused made an intentional contribution to a group crime; (ii) whilst knowing of the group's criminal intentions or seeking to contribute to the group's criminal purpose.Footnote 52 According to the majority in Katanga, the first mens rea prong only relates to the accused's contribution, not to the plan or criminal intent of the group.Footnote 53 It suffices to establish that the accused made a deliberate and conscious contribution and was aware that his actions contributed to the group's activities.Footnote 54
The second prong includes two alternative mens rea standards: the accused should either (i) have known of the group's criminal intentions; or (ii) seek to contribute to the group's criminal purpose.Footnote 55 So far, case law has been limited to the first alternative. The majority in Katanga has emphasized that knowledge should be demonstrated in relation to each of the specific crimes that the group intended to commit.Footnote 56 This means that there must be a direct subjective link between the accused and the crimes for which he stands trial.
3.3. Common Purpose/Plan
Joint perpetration and common purpose liability establish liability for group crimes in which multiple persons worked together towards a joint criminal endeavour. Both liability theories accordingly entail a ‘collective element’ – the common plan or common purpose element – which ties the participants together and justifies the mutual attribution of contributing acts.Footnote 57 ICC case law clarifies that the common plan and common purpose element are ‘functionally identical’ and can be construed in an analogous way.Footnote 58 The Court interprets the common plan/purpose as an ‘agreement or common plan between two or more persons’.Footnote 59 The common plan/purpose does not have to be embedded in a military, political, or administrative organization, nor should it be previously arranged or formulated. Rather, the agreement may materialize extemporaneously and can be inferred from circumstantial evidence, which demonstrates a group's concerted action.Footnote 60
ICC case law is still divided as to the scope of the common plan. In some cases, the ICC has held that the common purpose ‘does not need to be specifically directed at the commission of a crime’.Footnote 61 Rather, it suffices that the common plan includes ‘an element of criminality’,Footnote 62 which means that the implementation of the common plan entailed the risk that ‘if events follow the ordinary course, a crime will be committed’.Footnote 63 However, in other cases, the Court seems to have formulated a stricter standard by requiring that the common purpose was to commit a crime, or at least involved the commission of crimes.Footnote 64 This restrictive interpretation precludes the possibility that the accused is held responsible for crimes committed in excess of the common plan.Footnote 65 It ascertains that criminal conduct following from opportunistic actions of individuals cannot be attributed to other group members.Footnote 66
Because the common purpose element under Article 25(3)(d) and the common plan element under Article 25(3)(a) have a similar meaning, the finding of a group acting with a common purpose is linked to the notion of joint perpetration. According to the majority in Katanga, the finding that joint perpetrators acted pursuant to a common plan may help to establish the existence of a group acting with common purpose, although it is not required that this group consisted exclusively of joint perpetrators.Footnote 67 In her minority opinion, Judge Van den Wyngaert has presented a more restrictive view by arguing that the group acting with a common purpose is by definition a group of joint perpetrators.Footnote 68 At first sight, Judge Van den Wyngaert's equation is logically convincing,Footnote 69 since the commission of crimes by a group acting with a shared intent is tantamount to joint perpetration. Having said that, we should bear in mind that joint perpetration and common purpose liability differ on the actus reus level. Joint perpetration – at least in theory – sets a higher contribution threshold (‘essential contribution’) than common purpose liability (‘significant contribution’). Therefore, whilst joint perpetrators automatically form a group of persons acting with a common purpose, the group of persons acting with a common purpose does not necessarily consist of joint perpetrators exclusively.
Moreover, we should be mindful that common purpose liability applies irrespective of whether the accused was a member of the group acting with a common purpose or not.Footnote 70 Also persons who contributed to a group's common purpose from an outside position – i.e., without sharing the group's criminal intent – can be held responsible under Article 25(3)(d).Footnote 71 This does not apply to joint perpetration, which requires that the perpetrators acted with a common intention to commit crimes.Footnote 72
4. Common purpose liability and joint perpetration in practice
After having clarified the differences and similarities in the ICC's interpretation of joint perpetration and common purpose, this section continues to discuss how the Court has applied these liability theories in practice. Here, the focus is on the ICC's application of the contribution requirement and the mens rea elements, since this is where joint perpetration and common purpose liability differ in theory and where joint perpetration in abstracto sets a higher standard than common purpose liability.
4.1. Contribution to Crimes
4.1.1. Significant Contribution Test
In theory, common purpose liability requires that the accused: (i) made a significant contribution; (ii) to the specific crimes for which he stands trial. In the Sang and Mbarushimana cases, the ICC has applied this standard in a restrictive way.
In the case against Joshua Sang – a radio broadcaster before and during the 2007/2008 post-election violence in Kenya – the PTC construed a relatively close normative-causal relation between the acts of the accused and the criminal conduct for which he stood trial. In particular, the PTC held there were substantial grounds to believe that the accused: (i) fanned the commission of crimes by spreading hate messages; (ii) broadcasted false news messages that inflamed the violent atmosphere; and (iii) broadcasted instructions in which he directed the physical perpetrators to specific areas of attack.Footnote 73 In addition, there was evidence that Sang made violent statements in which he encouraged the criminal actions of the physical perpetrators. Most significantly, Sang allegedly urged people to ‘get their weapons from where they were kept and, if necessary, to use any arm at their disposal to evict the Kikuyus’.Footnote 74 In this way, he directly influenced the eruption of post-election violence. As one witness pointed out, ‘after listening to Mr. Sang's words, he had no choice’ but to join the fighters.Footnote 75
Similarly, in the Mbarushimana case, the PTC required a direct influence of the accused's actions on the commission of crimes. Callixte Mbarushimana was the Executive Secretary of the Democratic Forces for the Liberation of Rwanda (FDLR) in the Democratic Republic of Congo (DRC). In this capacity, Mbarushimana formed part of the FDLR's senior leadership and represented the FDLR in the media and during peace negotiations.Footnote 76 Whilst the PTC held that Mbarushimana thus contributed to the FDLR's general policy,Footnote 77 it was unable to establish that the accused's actions had an impact on the commission of crimes by FDLR forces.Footnote 78 Furthermore, there was insufficient evidence that Mbarushimana exercised any authority over the commanders and soldiers committing crimes on the ground. In fact, most of them had never heard of Mbarushimana – who resided in Paris, far removed from the scene of the crimes – and were unaware of his position within the FDLR.Footnote 79 The PTC therefore concluded that Mbarushimana's conduct did not meet the significant contribution threshold.
The ICC's observations in the Sang and Mbarushimana cases signify a strict interpretation of common purpose liability, which is based on a clear causal connection between the acts of the accused and the crimes charged. The Court essentially required that the accused's conduct had a direct effect on the commission of crimes specifically rather than on the common purpose in general. In other cases, however, the Court has adopted a much more lenient approach. For example, in the case against Ahmed Harun – the former Minister of State for the Interior of the Government of SudanFootnote 80 – the PTC determined that Harun managed the Darfur Security Desk and oversaw the activities of the government bodies that coordinated the counter-insurgency in Darfur.Footnote 81 Harun also personally participated in key activities of the counter-insurgency campaign, such as the recruitment, armament, and funding of Janjaweed militia.Footnote 82 According to the PTC, Harun thus made a significant contribution to the commission of war crimes and crimes against humanity against the ‘African tribes’ in Darfur.Footnote 83 This finding is based on a broad inference. The accused's involvement in specific crimes is deduced from actions that relate to his authoritative position and general role within the Sudanese government.
A comparably broad approach was adopted by the majority of the Katanga Trial Chamber. In assessing Katanga's contribution to the attack against the civilian population of Bogoro, the majority paid particular heed to Katanga's distribution of arms and ammunition to local combatants.Footnote 84 According to the majority, the weapons and ammunition delivered by Katanga ascertained the military superiority of the combatants, enabled them to continue their purpose of eliminating the Hema population of Bogoro, and thus secured the success of the attack.Footnote 85 By reasoning in this way, the majority in Katanga linked the accused's contribution first and foremost to the attack on Bogoro in general, whilst his involvement in the commission of specific (categories of) crimes remained indirect. Hence, the accused could be held responsible for contributing to a (legitimate) military operation, which he knew entailed a risk of crimes.Footnote 86
The previous analysis demonstrates that the ICC makes different factual appraisals of the significant contribution standard. Yet, this does not necessarily mean that the Court applies the contribution standard in an inconsistent way. Possibly, the variations in ICC case law can be explained by the different (organizational) positions of the accused. As the Mbarushimana PTC made clear, each contribution must be appraised in light of the accused's (perceived) role within a group/organization.Footnote 87 This means that the significance of a contribution is influenced by the accused's (organizational) function, which colours his conduct and determines the importance of his actions. Considering this context-dependent evaluation, it may be easier to establish the significant contribution threshold in cases against senior military figures, such as Germain Katanga, than in relation to persons who played a more marginal, political role, like Callixte Mbarushimana.
4.1.2. Essential Contribution Test
In relation to the ICC's use of the essential contribution standard for joint perpetration, we also witness a varied and context-dependent practice in which some cases display a stricter approach than others. For example, the Lubanga Trial and Appeals Chamber applied the essential contribution standard in a rather lenient way. The Chambers inferred the essentiality of Thomas Lubanga's contribution to the recruitment of child soldiers from inter alia: (i) his function as commander-in-chief and political leader of the UPC/FPLC; (ii) his overall coordinating role; (iii) the fact that he was informed on UPC/FPLC operations; (iv) the fact that he was involved in the planning of military operations and provided logistical support; and (v) Lubanga's close involvement in the UPC/FPLC's recruitment policy and his active support for recruitment initiatives.Footnote 88 Notably, these circumstances primarily concern the accused's senior role within a military and political organization and his involvement in the organization's activities, rather than his contribution to the recruitment of child soldiers specifically. This suggests that the accused's position of authority and his support for a (hazardous) organizational policy serve as a proxy for assessing the essential character of his contribution.Footnote 89
Like the Lubanga Trial and Appeals Chamber judgments, the ICC's findings in the case against Laurent Gbagbo can also generate a broad application of the essential contribution standard. The PTC in this case concluded that the accused contributed to the commission of crimes by inter alia: (i) designing and implementing a common plan to retain power by all means; (ii) creating a structure for the implementation of the common plan; (iii) arming the forces loyal to him; and (iv) co-ordinating the implementation of the common plan.Footnote 90 By reasoning in this way, the PTC seems to evaluate the essentiality of the accused's contribution primarily in relation to the common plan, instead of the commission of crimes. The link between the accused and the crimes for which he stands trial consequently depends on the nature and scope of the joint endeavour to which the accused contributed. This approach can yield a broad application of the essential contribution standard, in particular when the common plan is not criminal in itself, but refers to a lawful organizational policy.Footnote 91 To prevent that the causal link between the accused's conduct and the crimes for which he stands trial becomes too diluted, it is important that the ICC pays careful attention to the relation between the general common plan and the commission of specific crimes.
In contrast to the previous examples – which display a broad use of the essential contribution test – there are also cases in which the ICC has reinforced the objective connection between the accused and the crimes charged. The Court's findings in the case against Charles Blé Goudé are illustrative in this respect. The PTC in this case determined that the accused was a prominent supporter of Laurent Gbagbo. He particularly tried to keep Gbagbo in power by contributing to the ‘recruitment, training and financing of militias and mercenaries, the distribution of weapons, and, in particular, by way of the mobilisation of the youth for violence against [the opponents of Gbagbo]’.Footnote 92 According to the PTC, these contributions ‘had the effect of strengthening the general capability of the pro-Gbagbo forces to commit all the crimes’.Footnote 93 However, the PTC refused to establish that Blé Goudé in this way made an essential contribution to each of the crimes committed in pursuance of the common plan,Footnote 94 in particular considering that the plan to keep Gbagbo in power was broad in nature and was not implemented in ‘the form of a single, unified and coordinated operation but rather [in] the form of separate, multiple violent operations’.Footnote 95 Thus, the PTC seems to set a high standard, which requires that the accused controlled the occurrence of specific criminal incidents, rather than the common plan more generally.Footnote 96
4.1.3. Interim Conclusion
The previous analysis reveals that the ICC has applied the essential and significant contribution standards in diverse and context-dependent ways. It is therefore difficult to distinguish these standards in terms of a uniform test that clearly demarcates both concepts from each other. Rather than claiming that the essential contribution standard of joint perpetration necessarily constitutes a higher threshold than the significant contribution requirement of common purpose liability, it is more appropriate to adopt a flexible approach that takes account of the different ways in which the ICC has applied these tests to the facts of individual cases. This observation raises the question of whether joint perpetrators are by definition more blameworthy than persons contributing to a common purpose and whether there is sufficient factual ground for categorically classifying common purpose liability as a residual form of criminal responsibility.Footnote 97 More generally, the ICC's context-dependent use of the actus reus elements of joint perpetration and common purpose liability also calls the ICC's hierarchical interpretation of Article 25(3) into question.
4.2. Criminal Intent
4.2.1. Knowledge of Crimes by Others
The assessment of the accused's mens rea was one of the crucial issues in the Katanga case. To hold Katanga responsible under common purpose liability, the Court had to determine whether he knew that the weapons he delivered to the Ngiti militia would be used to attack civilians (as a war crime and crime against humanity), rather than to fight enemy combatants (as a legitimate military purpose). Based on the evidence, the majority concluded that Katanga was indeed aware of the criminal purpose for which his weapons would be used. The majority in this respect specifically referred to Katanga's knowledge of: (i) the preparations of Ngiti militia to attack Bogoro; (ii) the fact that the weapons and ammunition he distributed would be used by combatants during the attack; (iii) the ways in which the war in Ituri was waged, causing suffering to the civilian population; and (iv) previous ethnic-driven violence against the Hema population by Ngiti combatants.Footnote 98 Notably, these facts only link the accused indirectly to the crimes charged. In particular, the Chamber's reference to Katanga's general knowledge of the raging war evidences a broad application of the mens rea elements of common purpose liability.Footnote 99
The findings of the majority in Katanga raise the question of whether current judicial practice complies with the ICC's abstract interpretation of the subjective elements of common purpose liability. At first sight, it seems that whilst the Court in theory emphasizes that common purpose liability requires that the accused was aware of each of the crimes that a group intended to commit, in practice it is willing to infer the accused's knowledge from facts that are not directly linked to specific criminal conduct. Having said that, it is still too early to conclude that the ICC systematically disregards the mens rea standard of common purpose liability. In particular considering that other case law presents a more precise assessment of the accused's knowledge of crimes,Footnote 100 it seems that the findings of the Katanga majority must be appraised in light of the specific facts of the case under consideration. In this respect, it is noteworthy that the majority integrated the commission of crimes within the more general policy of ethnically driven violence in the Ituri region.Footnote 101 It can therefore not be established yet that the ICC will apply the mens rea elements of common purpose liability in a similarly lenient way in future cases.
4.2.2. Intent to Commit Crimes
Looking at the loose application of the mens rea elements of common purpose liability by the Katanga majority, there seems to be a sound basis for distinguishing common purpose liability from joint perpetration. The low mental standard set by the majority in Katanga is clearly unacceptable in relation to joint perpetration, which requires that the accused intended to commit the crimes charged.Footnote 102 This point is supported by the findings of the Lubanga Trial Chamber majority. The majority inferred Lubanga's intent to recruit, conscript and use child soldiers from specific circumstances concerning inter alia: (i) his use of child soldiers as bodyguards; (ii) his participation in rallies where child soldiers were present; and (iii) his visits to training camps where he gave morale-boosting speeches to recruits, including child soldiers.Footnote 103 By reasoning in this way, the majority in Lubanga construed a stronger – more direct – subjective link between the accused and the crimes committed than the Katanga majority.
Still, we should be mindful that – when substantiating Lubanga's intent as joint perpetrator – the Trial Chamber majority also referred to a number of general circumstances, such as the fact that Lubanga was in close contact with other senior figures and that all armed groups in Ituri used child soldiers.Footnote 104 It is not yet clear whether these facts could by themselves have provided a sufficient basis for establishing Lubanga's intent, or whether more precise evidence of his personal use and inspection of child soldiers was essential for meeting the mens rea threshold of joint perpetration. Possibly, the majority's reference to such specific facts can be explained by the unequivocal circumstances of the Lubanga case, which allowed for a confined application of the mens rea requirements. Future Chambers may be willing to adopt a more lenient approach in marginal cases in which the evidence of the accused's intent is less strong.
Consider, for example, the findings of the Kenyatta PTC in relation to the charges of rape against Francis Muthaura and Uhuru Kenyatta. The PTC on this point established that the accused ‘directed a group of armed Mungiki members to revenge against civilian residents of Nakuru and Naivasha, in the knowledge of and exploiting the ethnic hatred of the attackers towards their victims’.Footnote 105 According to the PTC, these circumstances provide sufficient evidence ‘that Mr. Muthaura and Mr. Kenyatta knew that rape was a virtually certain consequence of the implementation of the common plan’.Footnote 106 By reasoning in this way, the PTC draws a broad inference. It is not directly clear why the commission of rape constitutes a virtually certain consequence of a reprisal operation, even when this operation was driven by ethnic hatred.
4.2.3. Interim Conclusion
The findings above suggest that the ICC's application of the mens rea requirements of common purpose liability and joint perpetration is shaped by the facts of individual cases.Footnote 107 The subjective elements acquire a different colour, depending on the specific circumstances to which they are applied. Of course, this does not alter the fact that the mens rea requirements of joint perpetration and common purpose liability have a different basis and set a different standard in abstracto. However, we should bear in mind that practice is often more flexible than theoretical standards suggest. The facts of individual cases cannot always be fully captured in abstract legal standards. This calls for a nuanced understanding of the differences between the subjective elements of joint perpetration and common purpose liability. It also brings back the question of whether the liability theories stipulated in Article 25(3) of the Rome Statute can be structured in a hierarchical way on the basis of abstract categories and general criteria.
5. Concluding observations
The majority of ICC judges reads the liability theories stipulated in Article 25(3) of the Rome Statute in a hierarchical way. Within the hierarchy of liability theories, common purpose liability is regarded as a residual liability theory with low mens rea and actus reus standards, in particular compared to joint perpetration. According to the ICC, this entails that persons contributing to a common purpose are less blameworthy than joint perpetrators.
This article has appraised the distinction between common purpose liability and joint perpetration by assessing how the ICC has applied these liability theories to the facts of individual cases. The article has clarified the differences between common purpose liability and joint perpetration, both in relation to the accused's contribution and criminal intent. At the same time, it has shown that the ICC applies common purpose liability and joint perpetration in interplay with the facts of individual cases, leading to a varied and context-dependent practice. On this account, it is inappropriate to maintain that common purpose liability by definition constitutes a residual type of liability that establishes a low level of blameworthiness compared to joint perpetration. Instead, it is preferable to adopt a nuanced and flexible approach, which recognizes that Article 25(3)(a) and (d) cover a variety of conduct and different levels of responsibility.
By rejecting the ICC's qualification of common purpose liability as a residual and inferior, I do not mean to disqualify the reasons for distinguishing between different liability theories.Footnote 108 Indeed, the formulation of distinctive modes of liability promotes the principle of individual criminal responsibility and has great narrative and expressive value.Footnote 109 Having said that, the foregoing case law analysis shows the weaknesses of the ICC's hierarchical construction of Article 25(3). The Court's varied and context-dependent use of joint perpetration and common purpose liability makes it difficult to conclude in general terms that one liability theory conveys a more serious type of criminal responsibility than the other. Whilst such a hierarchical categorization can be advantageous from a doctrinal point of view – since it creates a clear and well-ordered concept of criminal responsibility – we may need to accept that legal practice is too complex and resilient to be captured in terms of a universal hierarchy. Of course, this does not mean that theoretical distinctions between different modes of liability can be disregarded at will, or that courts are free to establish criminal responsibility according to their personal preferences. Yet, we should acknowledge that we can only understand the meaning and scope of the criminal responsibility and appraise (the relevance of) the differences between liability theories in light of legal practice. Therefore, it is important that future research pays close attention to the ICC's practical use of liability theories in individual cases.