Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-mzp66 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T00:54:14.109Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Reconceptualising world order: Chinese political thought and its challenge to International Relations theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 February 2014

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

At the outset of the twenty-first century, the world is facing a range of problems, including environmental, economic, and security risks, that increasingly challenge the logic of nation-state governance. While American and European models of International Relations and global governance, such as the Westphalian system of states and the Washington Consensus, have come under attack from poststructuralist thinkers, political philosophers from China and Taiwan have tried to reconceptualise the world of the twenty-first century from their own perspectives. This article examines current streams of Chinese International Relations theorising and confronts them with the case of territorial disputes in the East China Sea. The article analyses the arguments by Chinese realists, ‘worldists’, and procedural constructivists, showing how Chinese scholars creatively revive pre-modern Chinese political theory in attempts to provide new ways in which International Relations scholars might view the world, or: ‘all-under-heaven’. I argue that these contributions will progressively challenge conventional theories of International Relations, while at the same time contending that so-called non-Western theorising, if it is to contribute to IRT, will require additional rigorous empirical grounding, a critical perspective on its entanglement with nationalist political discourses in East Asian societies, and the willingness to incorporate existing theories.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © British International Studies Association 2014 

Introduction

With the end of the Cold War and the onset of the information age, mainstream International Relations theory (IRT) has increasingly come under fire from poststructuralist theorists for promoting outdated and misleading frameworks of thought.Footnote 1 Contemporary problems like the US War on Terror, the recent global financial crisis, the political crisis in the EU, or global warming, raise the question whether models of International Relations (IR) such as neorealism, neoliberal institutionalism, or social constructivism are anachronistic and, in the worst of cases, pose part of the problem that they set out to solve.

A particular challenge has come from postcolonial scholars, who criticise conventional IR theorising for being informed by vested American and European geopolitical interests, and who argue that ‘even the historically sensitive elements in mainstream IR [for example, English School scholarship] offer a mistakenly Eurocentric account of history’.Footnote 2 Such arguments have resonated with scholars whose critical endeavours fall outside of the mainstream, both within American and European academia, as well as in other geographical locations. The works of this latter group have been tentatively subsumed under the title of ‘Non-Western IRT’.Footnote 3 In Asia, this includes academics from Australia, India, Japan, Korea, and the Association of Southeast Asian Nations (ASEAN), but also prominently from China and Taiwan, who contend that no IRT ‘can be built only upon the narrow confines of the European historical experience’ if it is meant to remain credible.Footnote 4

The purpose of this article is to survey Chinese and Taiwanese theorising on IR. I understand ‘theories’ to be conceptual frameworks through which human beings make sense of the world they experience. Such a view owes much to evolutionary and cognitive science, and to the pragmatic, critically-realist view that human beings make sense of their environment through a sophisticated albeit flawed sensory and cognitive architecture, derived through evolutionary processes.Footnote 5 This sentiment is summarised in the quote famously attributed to Einstein that ‘reality is merely an illusion, albeit a very persistent one’. Theorising in academia thus does not mean explaining the world as it is a priori to human experience, like structuralists generally do, but instead explaining how human agents (re)construct, make sense of, and behave in the structures they populate. In that sense, academic theorists need to be conscious that their theories are roadmaps to a reality they can never have unfettered access to, but that this does not relieve them from the burden of grounding their ideas in empirical evidence and revising their understanding in line with observations.Footnote 6 In this vein, I do not distinguish between explaining and understanding, or analysis and interpretation, as is commonly done, particularly in debates between positivist and hermeneutically-oriented academics.Footnote 7 Instead I view the supposed dichotomy between these approaches as a false one, which is arguably entrenched in the conventions and institutions of academic disciplines, but which does not reflect how human beings engage with their environments.

In the following, I aim to identify strands of what Acharya and Buzan have called a ‘pre-theory’ of IR, that is, ‘elements of thinking that do not necessarily add up to theory in their own right, but which provide possible starting points for doing so’,Footnote 8 and to assess what the contributions and limitations of such IR theorising might be. My point is that so-called ‘non-Western’ theorising is valuable because it has the potential to provide fresh roadmaps to a territory that has been misrepresented by the established maps of mainstream IRT. The relevance of conceptual frameworks from China or Taiwan is thus not that they represent the views of a perceived rising Great Power, but that they draw from rich and diverse cultural traditions that can offer insights into the workings of international politics.

The first section of this article discusses prominent attempts to use pre-modern Chinese political thought to explain present-day problems, and outlines the central risks that these attempts face. I then turn to particular strands of Chinese International Relations scholarship that aim to (re)conceptualise ideas such as relationality, process, and identity from Chinese perspectives. After outlining the main conceptual ideas of such approaches, I examine how useful they are when confronted with a particular issue in international relations: the territorial disputes in the East China Sea. To do so, I first review how the existing literature makes sense of this dispute before then asking what contribution a procedural, relational account that draws from Chinese theorists can provide. I conclude by arguing that such an account indeed vindicates some of the criticism that Chinese scholars have levelled against mainstream IRT, but that the shortcomings in this nascent conceptual framework necessitate a revision and careful expansion if it is to deliver on its promise to provide fresh perspectives to IRT.

Contemporary Chinese political theorising and its risks

Chinese political theories are today generally informed by two specific concerns. The first concern is how to address the geopolitical bias in existing theoretical paradigms. The dissatisfaction with these paradigms has generally produced two strategic moves: firstly attempts to improve the explanatory power of IRT through recourse to Chinese concepts, secondly endeavours to reform actual political practice by replacing perceived geopolitical biases with alternative ideologies. In other words, Chinese political theories are located on a continuum of analytical and normative enterprises.

The second concern is the scope of such projects. They range across a spectrum from claims to universality, such as arguments that pertain to politics everywhere and at all times, to claims that seek validity only in a discrete, indigenous context, like the specific sociocultural situation of present-day China. I have mapped these two concerns, that is normative/analytical focus and discrete/universal scope, onto the axes in the diagram below, and have tentatively placed several prominent examples into this figure.Footnote 9

Figure 1. Contemporary Chinese political theorising.

In this article, I am concerned with conceptual work that aims to explain and understand IR, and my focus therefore lies with arguments that fall primarily into the lower right quadrant of the diagram.Footnote 10 This includes in particular the procedural, relational approach, performance-focused ideas, and the concerns of world theory scholars (or ‘worldists’). These approaches do not exist in isolation. They are juxtaposed with the discourse of other political philosophy projects, and consequently need to overcome the shortcomings that these other endeavours face. This includes two particular risks: firstly, the uncritically ahistorical reproduction of concepts, and secondly the implicit or explicit promotion of nationalist political projects.

To illustrate these shortcomings, it is useful to review some of the works that fall into the other quadrants of the diagram, particularly since such approaches are rooted in a long tradition of Chinese historiography. An overarching theme of this tradition is to comment on the past from a contemporary position, and pre-modern works like Sima Qian's Records of the Historian (Shiji 史记) or the various commentaries to the Spring and Autumn Annals (Chunqiu 春秋) are arguably early testament to this practice. It is important to acknowledge this tradition since it partially explains the strong programmatic focus of Chinese political philosophy: attempts to utilise the past are often less preoccupied with the accuracy of historical events than with morally assessing how historical events might serve as templates for contemporary political behaviour.Footnote 11

The diverse heritage of pre-modern Chinese political thought provides a treasure-trove of concepts from often competing ideological schools, dating as far back as the Western Zhou Dynasty (c. 1040–771 BC) and the philosophical currents of the subsequent periods known as Spring-and-Autumn (chunqiu 春秋: 722–481 BC) and Warring States (zhanguo 战国: 403–221 BC).Footnote 12 Most Chinese scholars draw their material from these periods. Attempts to revive perceived ‘Confucian’ values are particularly en vogue, although most such attempts actually amalgamate ideas from different Confucian sources (particularly the Annalects, the Mengzi, and the Xunzi) with concepts from Daoism and Legalism.Footnote 13 Ling et al., for instance, lift the concept of benevolence (ren 仁) from the Mengzi and reinterpret it as ‘sociality’, stressing that benevolence only works through the conduct of one person to another – a sentiment believed to be engrained in the composition of the Chinese character 仁, which combines the signifier for person 人with the signifier for the number two 二.Footnote 14 In this line of interpretation, benevolence becomes a moral imperative to ‘love all men’ (ai ren 爱人)Footnote 15 and by extension a form of humanism that enables the world to be in harmony (hexie 和谐) by emphasising human relations.

Another example of scholarly work interested in this period of Chinese history is the volume Thoughts on World Leadership and Implications,Footnote 16 edited by prominent realist Yan Xuetong 阎学通 and his student Xu Jin 徐进. The editors provide a survey of pre-modern Chinese political thought from a contemporary IR perspective, dedicating chapters to the Guanzi 管子, the Laozi 老子, the various works attributed to Confucius 孔子, the Mozi 墨子, the Mengzi 孟子, the Xunzi 荀子, the Hanfeizi 韩非子, the Commentary of Zuo (Zuozhuan 左传), the Book of Rites (Liji 礼记), the Strategems of the Warring States (Zhanguo ce 战国策), and Lü's Spring and Autumn Annals (Lüshi chunqiu 吕氏春秋). Throughout the book, the common theme is the question of how states can achieve ‘hegemonic rule over all-under-heaven’ (wangba tianxia 王霸天下). To this end, the authors examine original textual materials, attempting to define what concepts such as righteousness (yi 义), benefit (li 利), harmony (he 和), virtue (de 德), power (quan 权), or force (li 力) might mean, and then mapping the relations between these concepts in order to explore how and in what fashion Chinese pre-modern states achieved supremacy rather than suffering annihilation (miewang 灭亡).

This collection of essays has correctly been criticised for conflating ancient Chinese thought with actual historical practice.Footnote 17 Indeed, it is telling that Yan hopes that his analysis will both ‘contribute to the development of existing IR theories’ and ‘help consummate the strategy of China's rise’.Footnote 18 Judging by Yan's later writings, the academic motivation seems to take the backseat behind the intention of offering policy advice in the service of China's ‘rise’.Footnote 19 Yan's use of pre-modern philosophy thus mainly turns into a search for ideas that help legitimise his realist perspective. In the tradition of Chinese historiography, Yan liberally draws from historical discourses to pass moral judgement and, in this case, promote realist foreign policy in the People's Republic of China (PRC).

Realists are not the only scholars mining Chinese intellectual history for useful ideas. A similar theme runs through contemporary neo-Confucianism and ‘worldisms’. A prominent example of the former is the political Confucian scholar Jiang Qing 蒋庆, whose philosophy falls into the upper left quadrant of the diagram provided above: his approach is aimed specifically at improving Chinese domestic politics by reviving the Confucian meritocratic system of rule and Confucian social relations.Footnote 20 Theories of worldism are often grounded in similar Confucian concerns. However, they aim to rethink world order and consequently fall into the upper right quadrant. A central concept in these frameworks is the idea of tianxia 天下. Tianxia, that is, ‘all-under-heaven’, today serves as shorthand for a holistic Chinese view of the world that is conceived of as distinct from other world views. Qin Yaqing 秦亚青 summarises the concept as follows: ‘The Chinese world referred to everything under heaven and on the earth …. It was a complete whole where no dichotomous opposites existed.’Footnote 21 This idea of ‘all-under-heaven’ serves its advocates as a framework to study (and possibly revitalise) the institutions and processes of the Western Zhou Dynasty, the legendary Golden Age in which the relatively small state of Zhou was able to govern a large territorial expanse and a significant number of foreign states with allegedly little recourse to military violence.

A driving force behind this interest in ‘all-under-heaven’ has been the political philosopher Zhao Tingyang 赵汀阳, whose aim is to replace the anarchical system of nation-states with a utopian cosmological order in which all relations, whether at the level of the world, the state, or the family, are transitively governed by the same moral rationale. This, according to Zhao, allows for a harmonious world that unites people, nature, and politics as ‘all-under-heaven’, under the benevolent rule of a supreme ‘son of heaven’ (tianzi 天子) – a virtuous ruler, or group of virtuous rulers, who lead by example and consequently inspire loyalty in their subjects.Footnote 22 Callahan has provided a thorough critique of Zhao's arguments, so I will not rehearse them here.Footnote 23 Suffice to say that Zhao's tianxia system is a deeply conservative political programme that is strongly informed by anti-Western sentiment, nationalist indignation at the Bush administration's ‘American Empire’ (Meiguo diguo 美国帝国), and a strong scepticism towards forms of mass participation.Footnote 24 While Zhao's tone has arguably become more conciliatory in his latest writings, he overall nevertheless retains his opinion that ‘Western’ philosophy is flawed, and that electoral democracy is useless, constructing Chinese traditional order as an alternative.Footnote 25

As Callahan has argued, Zhao's discussion of tianxia, as idiosyncratic as it may be, has placed the concept on the agenda and has effectively set ‘the boundaries of how people think about China's past, present, and future’.Footnote 26 Chinese IR scholarship indeed often conceptualises world order with reference to tianxia, though not always in similarly utopian terms as Zhao Tingyang. One institution that has received particular attention in this context is the tributary system of the Zhou, which was elevated to mythical status in Chinese historiography and was taken as a model for foreign policy throughout most of China's imperial history.Footnote 27 Authors like Qin interpret the tributary system as follows:

It was not ‘inter’-national, because there was no legal equality among units and therefore there were no ‘like units’ …. Thus, the tributary system, spatially and conceptually, was like concentric squares, with only differences in distance and without difference in ontology. The periphery was the radiation of the centre and therefore the dualistic positioning between the ego and the alter did not exist at all.Footnote 28

Such interpretations are again to some extent politically motivated, since they frame Chinese foreign policy as traditionally benevolent and tolerant. Through its tribute system, so the argument would have it, the Chinese empire not only ‘saw more benefits going from China to the tribute states rather than the other way round’, but also cast the centre in the ‘role of balancer, intervening wherever invasion by one state occurred against another’.Footnote 29 Callahan has criticised such romanticism for its lack of engagement with China's imperial past, and historically-minded scholars like Zhang have stressed that utopian visions of Confucian harmony and order have ‘exercised a greater hold on the Chinese imagination than the actual record of belligerency, discord and enforced unification which are characteristic of many periods of Chinese history’.Footnote 30 It is indeed not hard to see how the Zhou system of ‘world rule’ could fit the current attempts in China to conceptualise a peaceful rise of the PRC to Great Power status and legitimise the ‘harmonious society’ ideology of the political leadership.Footnote 31

Callahan is correct to note that such projects to reinterpret pre-modern history and philosophy often play ‘fast and loose’ with their sources.Footnote 32 To give an example, contemporary interpretations that equate the classic use of the character ai 爱 with modern-day ‘love’ bypass the fact that Confucian sources conceptualise ai as hierarchical relationships, governed by strictness – hardly the meaning we would give to the word ‘love’ today.Footnote 33 Another example is the interpretation of the Chinese character shi 势 as the supposed ‘general tendency’ of international politics to move towards ‘peace, cooperation, and development’Footnote 34 in a teleological fashion, which omits that works like The Art of War or the Strategems of the Warring States deploy the same character to advise leaders how to utilise the potential of a situation to crush their enemies. Similarly, the concept tianxia 天下 (literally ‘under-heaven’) is rarely contextualised in relation to other key geographical terms of the respective sources, such as ‘middle kingdoms’ (zhong guo 中国) or ‘east of the mountains’ (shan dong 山东), but is simply translated as ‘all-under-heaven’, or ‘the world’. Other concepts are distorted beyond recognition, for instance when realist scholar Wang Yiwei 王义桅 interprets ‘the people's heart’ (minxin 民心) as modern-day ‘public opinion’,Footnote 35 without question of whether pre-modern China had such a thing as a ‘public sphere’Footnote 36 and, if so, whether this ‘public’ then functioned the same way during the Zhou era as it does in diverse (post)modern contexts.

This latter example also illustrates how the ahistorical use of pre-modern concepts is at times married to nationalist outlooks. Wang's search for pre-modern validation is fuelled by the idea that ‘America is powerful enough to produce theory’ while other nation-states like China are not.Footnote 37 In such case, theorising becomes a project to promote the national interests of the PRC. Scholars such as Zhao Tingyang, Wang Yiwei, or Yan Xuetong thus repeatedly stress their claims for Chinese uniqueness. In much of their writings, Chinese theorising is not considered valuable because it addresses issues that mainstream ‘Western’ political thought underemphasises, but because it is supposedly distinctly Chinese. In this line of thinking, establishing a national IRT project is imperative because, so the logic goes, ‘China’ needs its own perspective of the world as it takes its rightful place as a Great Power. It should come as no surprise that advocates of such an argument then assure readers in ‘the West’ (or in East Asian countries bordering on PRC territory) that perceptions of a renewed nationalism in China are based on myths (shenhua 神话), misunderstandings (wujie 误解), and unnecessary worry (danxin 担心), all of which are rooted in the so-called ‘China Threat theory’ (Zhongguo weixie lun 中国威胁论). Analyses of nationalism in China then become a domination strategy by ‘the West’ to keep China down, instead of acknowledging that ‘China is still the mother of East Asian civilization’.Footnote 38

Before this backdrop, nationalist writers perceive the establishment of a ‘China School’ of IRT as the solution to the problem, though its supporters struggle with the contradictions of what this political project should exactly achieve. This becomes apparent when Wang simultaneously assures readers that establishing a ‘China School’ of IRT ‘does not mean overthrowing or replacing western IRT, but then immediately asserts that once ‘China represents the development trend of the advanced productive forces of the world, the orientation of advanced culture and the fundamental interests of the overwhelming majority of the world, the Chinese School will replace western IRT as the dominant school of IRT.’Footnote 39

Chinese thinkers are right to criticise mainstream IR theory for being ‘Western’-centric. Nevertheless, the critique at times moves in the wrong direction, ironically duplicating many of the biased assumptions that it set out to counter. This is apparent in the many comments that ‘Westerners’ think and behave in this or that way, whereas ‘the Chinese’ are different – and possibly in ways that cannot be bridged. Such attempts to frame IR theorising in terms of Chinese uniqueness or entitlement betray not only a highly problematic understanding of what nationalism is and how it works, but also the wish to co-opt the works of diverse thinkers for the purpose of creating a unified ‘imagined community’.Footnote 40 As will become clear from the case study below, popular nationalism in China is not at all a myth,Footnote 41 and nationalist attempts to theorise politics risk facilitating such sentiments and the problems they pose. Needless to say that I reject any such attempts to turn academic work into national projects, and that I agree with Shih Chih-yu 石之瑜 that ‘a plausible Chinese IR that has universal implications cannot emerge from the confrontational assumption of China being unique’.Footnote 42

Conceptual concerns in contemporary Chinese IR theorising

Quotes like these demonstrate that not all scholarship that draws from China's history of ideas is nationalist. Similarly, scholars who take a wordlist position may take an ahistorical perspective, but for some this is not an uncritical matter of course but a strategic move. The intention of many such projects is explicitly to not view pre-modern concepts ‘as set and fixed, evolved from millennia of “orthodoxy” despite internal debates, contestations, and reformulations’, but to instead ‘draw on their defining elements and integrate them with contemporary insights derived from Marxist, postcolonial, and feminist studies and practice to contest hegemonic assertions about modernity, ontology, subjectivity, and world history’.Footnote 43 It would be unfair to criticise such a deployment of pre-modern ideas for its lack of historical reflection. With this poststructuralist argument in mind, allow me to turn to attempts that conceptualise international politics from Chinese perspectives.

As outlined above, the theoretical approaches I am interested in here are the ones that aim to contribute to the understanding of IR. While such approaches differ in their specific focus, as well as in the degree to which they are willing to derive normative claims from their explanations, they each speak to three overarching themes. These are a general scepticism towards state-centric theories, a focus on performative behaviour and identity construction, and an attention to relations and processes. I will review these themes in turn.

A central charge of worldists’ critique is that mainstream IRT, along with the practices it arguably informs and legitimises, is grounded in a reductionist and misleading focus on the politics of nation-states. Agathangelou and Ling explain that the aim of worldism is to prioritise ‘a different locus of enunciation and existence that does not impose European Enlightenment's understanding of “modernity” with its contingent systems of organization: that is, the Westphalian inter-state system and its teleological understanding of development and change’.Footnote 44 Such concerns are thus similar to those of globalisation scholars such as Beck, who challenge the ‘methodological nationalism’ endemic to social science research.Footnote 45

Other Taiwanese and Chinese scholarship at times follows this logic. Shih, for instance, stresses the importance that domestic processes play in international politics when he outlines how citizens, intellectuals, and officials construct ‘Chinese identity’ by negotiating the meaning of nationalism outside of state institutional boundaries.Footnote 46 Qin and Wei, who are generally interested in state behaviour, similarly acknowledge that domestic factors such as economic and social developments influence how collective Chinese identity evolves.Footnote 47 That these processes have an important transnational dimension that falls outside of traditional International Relations becomes clear from Shih's argument that Chinese foreign policy is the outcome of complex role-making and role-taking processes that are influenced both by domestic actors as well as actors abroad, for instance International Relations scholars and so-called China watchers trying to make sense of their relationship with ‘China’.Footnote 48

The move away from state-centric theories is intricately linked to the attempts of these scholars to reconceptualise national identity. Qin and Wei, for instance, criticise mainstream social constructivism á la Wendt for its structuralist approach to culture and identity: to the authors, such an approach assumes that culture is an exogenous systemic structure that forms the identity of actors, ‘overlooking the constitutive effect of the agent on the structure and of each on the other’.Footnote 49 For Qin, Wendt's concept of identity creates the paradox that an actor ‘A’ can never be ‘non-A’, or in other words that identities are discrete and generally unchanging, even though the political world is in constant flux.Footnote 50

Identity, according to Qin, should instead be understood as a continuous process of assemblage that ‘must be examined and understood in social networks, which are the combination of all sorts of relations’.Footnote 51 Actors are born into distinct socio-temporal environments, which then define their identities. If we follow Qin's argument, then we should not conceptualise social actors as complete and distinct units, but as flexible entities that are in the process of continuously becoming: ‘identity is, by nature, multifold, interactive, and changeable along with practice’.Footnote 52 To understand how identity works, the focus should be on how actors are embedded in relational networks, and how these networks are nested in other networks. In Qin's words:

the identity of an individual is defined in terms of her nodes or positioning in the complex relational web and the significance of her action produced only through her dynamic relations with others. Social actors exist only in social relations. Rather than being independent and discrete natural units, individuals are born social beings in a relational web, where identities and roles of individuals and appropriateness of individual behavior are defined by nodes on the web. Individuals per se have no identities.Footnote 53

Like other Chinese thinkers, Qin is here invoking the yin-yang imagery: the circle with black and white halves, entwined in an organic fashion, and each containing part of the other. This metaphor is a powerful heuristic device that forces theorists to rethink whether the dualisms and contradictions they set up as part of their theories are actually as rigid as they conceive them to be. Chinese IR theory may thus argue that contradiction lies in the eye of the beholder. For instance, ‘A’ may be true to someone and non-true to someone else. Such ontological relativism is a useful point of intersection with poststructuralist theories of how meanings and identities are shaped through social practice.

This is also a theme in Shih's work, which critically draws from the ‘all-under-heaven’ system and its tributary logic to emphasise the performative elements in foreign policy. Shih argues that we should analyse International Relations as a form of role-playing:

In the all-under-heaven worldview, one cares primarily about the image of one's nation state in the eyes of other nation states, not the identity of one's nation state that enables one to construct the difference of other nation states in one's own eyes. In other words, how to be looked at from outside receives more attention than how to look out from within. China represents a relationship-oriented civilization in opposition to an interest/power-oriented civilization.Footnote 54

Shih thus evokes the imagery of ‘face’ (mianzi 面子) to argue that IRT should distinguish between identity (self-perception) and image (how the self is perceived by others), and should explore how actors construct identity through complex processes of role-taking and role-making.Footnote 55 Such a rationale opens up the opportunity to connect with elements of early (pre-mainstream) constructivism and its intersecting disciplines: performative sociology, speech-act theory, and discourse theory. It also shifts the focus from static actors to relationships (guanxi 关系) and processes (guocheng 过程), another central theme in this line of theorising.

In Qin's ‘procedural constructivism’ (guocheng jiangou zhuyi 过程建构主义) relationality and process are the core concerns. Qin asserts that ‘one of the basic features of Chinese society is its relational orientation, which means “relations” are the most significant content of social life and the hub of all social activities’.Footnote 56 His goal is to rethink how relations work, hoping that ‘if we could conceptualize the logic of “relationality”, it should be different from the Western logic of causation in its way of thinking and theoretical construction’.Footnote 57 To this end, Qin focuses on the idea of process, arguing that ‘process is of itself’, that social dynamics are self-perpetuating.Footnote 58 His definition in full:

Process refers to on-going interactive relations, embedded in social practice and producing social meaning. It is relations in motion, or a complex of interconnected and dynamic relations formed through social practice.Footnote 59

It is within these processes, Qin argues, that actors develop their identity. By focusing on change (bian 变), Qin emphasises how identities shift, depending on the situation. Referencing the sociologist Mustafa Emirbayer, Qin proposes that ‘in relational sociology, rather than being independent, discrete, and rational, an actor should be social, which means her social relations are given even before her existence’.Footnote 60

The main achievement of Qin's procedural constructivism is that it conceptualises the changeable identity of group actors, such as states. For Qin, a Chinese dialectic perspective allows an entity ‘A’ to become ‘non-A’ through process. The essence of ‘A’ is relational, situational, and consequently flexible. For instance, if I am sitting by the beach in Norway at 11pm, in late June, it may be both day and night for me at the same time. If I perceive this as a paradox, then only because I am confused by diverging definitions of what ‘night’ means: (1) the period between 10pm and 6am, for instance; or (2) the time of day when the sun has set. In essence, the non-paradox assumption is powerful in cases like these, because it demonstrates that something we perceived as a paradox is either a paradox of our own making, or not actually a paradox at all.

In summary, the theoretical endeavours reviewed in this section all share a common dissatisfaction with mainstream IRT that echoes many of the concerns that poststructuralist scholars have similarly raised. Chinese and Taiwanese attempts to overcome these perceived limitations of existing theories draw from the rich Chinese tradition of political philosophy to stress three related aspects of international politics that established IRT underemphasises: (1) the importance that domestic and transnational processes play in the formation of international politics; (2) the relevance of relational processes and interactions, and (3) the changing, situational nature of (collective) identities and self-images. The question remains to what degree a focus on these additional dimensions can contribute to the understanding of International Relations.

Relationality, process, and performance in the East China Sea

To explore this question, I now turn to a contemporary issue in the international politics of East Asia that has arguably posed a puzzle for mainstream IR theories such as neorealism, neoliberalism, and social constructivism: the East China Sea territorial dispute between the governments of the PRC, Japan, and the Republic of China on Taiwan (ROC). The conflict is over a group of uninhabitable islands, called Diaoyu 钓鱼 in Chinese and Senkaku 尖閣諸 in Japanese (in the following: Diaoyu/Senkaku Islands), which are situated between the islands of Taiwan and Okinawa. Sovereign control over the island formation is hotly contested by the three parties, and has repeatedly led to conflicts ever since the US government effectively transferred administrative control to the Japanese authorities in 1971.Footnote 61 Most recently, the issue flared up after the Japanese government bought several of the islands from a private Japanese owner in 2012, leading to popular protests in all three countries and diplomatic tensions that have continued throughout 2013.Footnote 62

Realist accounts of the conflict focus on the geopolitical concerns in the region, stressing the relevance of the Diaoyu/Senkaku Islands as fishing grounds and as potential sources of oil and gas, as well as their strategic relevance for the various states to project naval power in the Asia Pacific.Footnote 63 As Hagström outlines in his critique of such approaches, realist theorists conceptualise these issues in terms of relative gains: the regional tensions are then explained as a consequence of China's perceived ‘rise’, the resulting assertiveness of the Chinese leadership in matters of international politics, and the inability of other actors such as Japan or the US to balance the PRC's power.Footnote 64 According to Koo, such explanations ignore the restraint that the various parties regularly display and thus ‘cannot fully capture the continuing pattern of rise and fall of conflict’ over the islands.Footnote 65

Liberal authors like Koo or Chung thus focus on the economic ties between the actors, arguing that trade relations ‘have repeatedly fostered the de-escalation of Sino-Japanese conflict over territorial and maritime rights’, and that in the post-Cold-War era ‘both countries suddenly discovered that trade was too mutually advantageous to be held hostage to pieces of disputed rocks’.Footnote 66 However, the faith that these authors place in economic ties as a force for peace contradicts much of their own data: Koo, for instance, shows how economic relations have intensified over time, but then has to concede that for instance ‘the 1996 flare-up turned out to be far more serious in terms of its political salience and its level of hostility than were its predecessors’.Footnote 67 Similarly, when confronted with the increase of such flare-ups throughout the 2000s, Koo is forced to sustain his theories by only applying them to cases of de-escalation while drawing selectively from the very approaches he criticises when it comes to explaining escalation.Footnote 68 The assumed causal link between economic cooperation and conflict resolution thus remains tenuous, leading critics like Blanchard to question ‘whether economic ties alone will be sufficient to constrain the two states from escalating their conflict in the future’.Footnote 69

Conventional social constructivist explanations of East China Sea disputes face a similar challenge as when confronted with other regional issues in East Asia: if states are socialised by an already existing international culture that constructs their identities and interests, then what happens in a region where ‘there is no obvious structure of ideas’?Footnote 70 Similarly, the mainstream constructivist assumption that nation-states enter an interaction with pre-formed behavioural tendencies and habits remains problematic: in the case of the East China Sea, such a model would suggest that the history of war between China and Japan, and in particular their respective inability to critically revisit this past, will cause history to repeat itself.Footnote 71 These arguments at the very least raise doubts whether mainstream constructivism, with its static view of relations and its practice of treating states like persons, has the tools to explain the Diaoyu/Senkaku Island dispute.Footnote 72

If mainstream IRT is ill-equipped to explain the repeated cycles of escalation and de-escalation in the East China Sea, how would the theoretical considerations of Chinese and Taiwanese scholars fare in the same context? The recent developments are characterised not only by complex dynamic interactions, but also by highly symbolic behaviour across different political tires. This suggests that non-state-centric, procedural interpretation that focuses on situational identities and self-images might indeed be well suited to the task. I will again consider these three aspects in turn.

Firstly, the events in 2012 demonstrate that a successful explanation of the dispute needs to incorporate both state and non-state actors. State-actors demonstrably play an important role in the conflict: a major factor in the recent dispute has been the Japanese government's purchase of several of the disputed islands, as well as the diplomatic row that followed both the original announcement of those plans in August and the final transaction in September.Footnote 73 However, the state-level alone does not tell the whole story. Citizens of the PRC, the ROC, Japan, and also Hong Kong have repeatedly played an instrumental role in shaping the dynamics of the conflict. In many of the past disputes, groups of civilians have exacerbated inter-state tensions by travelling to the disputed waters and attempting (with varying degrees of success) to reach the islands. This was also the case on 15 August 2012, the day that marks the end of the Second World War in East Asia, when five Hong Kong activists swam to the islands after their boat had been stopped by the Japan Coast Guard.Footnote 74 Three days later, Japanese right-wing activists similarly swam to shore, raising Japanese flags and commemorating perceived Japanese war heroes.Footnote 75 The news of these activities quickly spread, generating heated online discussions across the region. In China, for instance, web forums and social media networks were awash with indignation at the deportation of the Hong Kong activists and the tenacity of the Japanese right-wingers.Footnote 76

It should be clear from these developments that the call to open up the ‘black box’ of state-centric International Relations has merit. It guides the analysis towards data that other approaches would ignore. However, attention to the actions of domestic non-state actors has been a theme in both liberal and poststructuralist scholarship on the Diaoyu/Senkaku Island dispute.Footnote 77 What is more, it is not yet an explanation in its own right. The question remains what a procedural, situational interpretation of this expanded selection of data can contribute.

If we follow Qin's approach, then the process that unfolds between the Japanese and Chinese governments should develop its own rationale and should shape the identities of the different actors. In an analysis of China-ASEAN relations, Qin and Wei argue that the informal process of the ‘ASEAN way’ has succeeded at transforming the role structure between the actors from a hostile to a non-hostile one, has produced norms that all sides internalise, and has prompted the actors to sustain the process even when this has not served their national interest.Footnote 78 If we accept Qin and Wei's reasoning that process generally leads to such outcomes, can similar patterns then also be observed in the conflict-laden relation between China and Japan in the East China Sea?

At first sight, the argument that the interaction process between the governments produces norms and sustains non-hostile relations seems to be confirmed by the official statements on both the Japanese and the PRC side. Despite the long history of animosities between these parties and the repeated eruption of the Diaoyu/Senkaku conflict, both sides keep reiterating their commitment to the interaction itself, even after the recent spike in tensions. On the Japanese side, this has included foreign ministry press releases and op-eds emphasising that ‘Japan is committed to continue dealing with the current situation in a calm manner from a broad perspective’ and that the government ‘stands ready to stabilize relations with China’.Footnote 79 Chinese Communist Party general secretary Xi Jinping has similarly emphasised most recently that his administration ‘wants to promote the strategic relationship of mutual benefit with Japan from broad perspectives’.Footnote 80 In addition, the interaction has provided each government with the opportunity to construct a collective identity – in the Japanese case ‘a responsible and democratic country in the Asia-Pacific region’, and in the case of the PRC ‘a peace-loving Chinese nation’.Footnote 81

However, can we conclude from such statements that the interaction constitutes a self-sustaining process that leads to order and harmony in the region? Several points make this an unlikely explanation. Firstly, the argument that process automatically leads from hostility to cooperation to friendship confronts Qin's procedural constructivism with the same problem that liberal teleologies face: if the relationship between China and Japan is on track towards harmony, then why does the Diaoyu/Senkaku Island conflict keep flaring up? Also, if processes have such a teleological rationale, then how precisely does this rationale work? The burden of persuasively answering these questions lies with the procedural constructivists. Secondly, the argument does not fit all of the evidence. While I have cited quotes that indeed substantiate Qin's argument, the documents also contain strong claims to national sovereignty and territorial integrity, and none of these claims seems to weaken over time. In this regard, at least, the process has either no transformative effect, or it possibly entrenches the norms of sovereignty and non-intervention. Thirdly, it is not clear that the process indeed leads the actors to behave in contradiction with their ‘national interests’. Not only am I sceptical of Qin's previous attempts to identify such interests for the Chinese case, I am also curious why he seems to imply that such interests remain largely stable throughout a sustained interaction.Footnote 82 If we take the axioms of procedural constructivism serious, then I would assume that the process radically reshapes ‘national interests’ along with identities, norms, and values – but that is not what the evidence in this case suggests. Finally, I am not convinced by Qin's argument that processes of identification develop and sustain their own intrinsic logic. Considering Qin's critique of the mainstream constructivist assumption that ideational structures exist a priori and detached from actors, his attempt to similarly divorce processes from the actors and treat them as phenomena that are ‘un-owned’ and ‘of themselves’ seems inconsistent.Footnote 83 The effect is that such a move deletes any agency from processes and no longer ask what roles governments, businesses, interest groups, and so on (whether Chinese or otherwise) play in bringing processes about.

The reference to ‘un-owned’ teleological process thus seems unhelpful in explaining territorial disputes such as those in the East China Sea, where the interaction oscillates between hostile and conciliatory actions. A more promising line of inquiry is Shih's argument that interactions consist of open-ended performances in which actors attribute and adopt different roles. In fact, if we allow for the idea that such performative behaviour transgresses borders as well as the categories of ‘state’ and ‘non-state’, then we are left with an interpretive framework that might explain why the actors in the Diaoyu/Senkaku Island dispute seem to be both ‘A’ and ‘non-A’, that is, both hostile and cooperative. The key questions in such an approach are how actors adopt and perform certain roles in certain interactions, and what happens when these interactions challenge an actor's self-image, causing a loss of ‘face’. A full analysis along these lines would arguably require additional empirical work that I am not in a position to provide here, for instance qualitative interviews with actors, participant observation, and detailed process tracing based on archival work.Footnote 84 Nevertheless, the available information from official and media sources on the 2012 dispute allows at least a tentative step in this direction.

In a framework that examines performative behaviour, the agents enact their roles in dynamic relations with a diverse range of other agents. For instance, citizens in the PRC, the ROC, or Hong Kong perform their nationalist attitudes vis-á-vis a foreign other (‘the Japanese’) on online stages in front of an audience of their peers, thereby pledging their commitment to this imagined ‘in-group’. Any offensive action by a member of the perceived ‘out-group’ then necessitates renewed commitment in the form of additional nationalist gestures, such as additional online comments, public protest, or activism. Meanwhile, intellectuals, entrepreneurs, and other public figures use the opportunity to promote their often diverging agendas in relation to the on-going protests. Such interactions have domestic ramifications, since they prompt government officials to adjust their own behaviour in line with or opposition to the rapidly shifting public discourse. They also have transnational ramifications, eliciting a parallel dynamic of performances in Japan. This shifting terrain of social practices and discursive statements provides a dynamic network of meanings, in which official agents have to locate their own role. This includes the staff of the Japan Coast Guard and Chinese PLA, who have to develop ‘appropriate’ behaviour in the face of the respective other as well as their peers. It also includes the actions of civilian officials, such as foreign ministry staff and ultimately state leaders, who navigate these dynamic interactions in search of performative solutions that make them appear credible to the various players while remaining true to their own conception of self.

In such a complex assemblage, it is not surprising if the performance of one actor clashes with the expectations of other actors, all of whom are waiting for certain cues to sustain their role-play. Confounded expectations can thus lead to very real tears in the ‘structures of feeling’ that the various actors have collectively knit.Footnote 85 This is how the indignation of nationalists can shift from the foreign other to compatriots who do not play according to the script, for instance by driving Japanese cars, calling for tolerance, or emphasising dialogue. The statements that official actors produce during such interactions, for instance policy documents, press releases, white books, etc., consequently consist of different templates, each drawing from a different script, and each stencilling its individual pattern into the resulting discourse. The outcomes are documents with seemingly contradictory statements, for instance advocating both stern opposition against violations of territorial sovereignty and collaboration to diffuse the situation.Footnote 86 However, these inconsistencies are not contradictions to those who know how to decode the various patterns and apply the appropriate script to the relationship.

An interactionist model that emphasises the situatedness of agents and their actions thus seems like a fruitful approach to understand complex, conflict-laden processes. A prerequisite for such endeavour is, however, that theorists abandon their commitment to teleological grand-narratives. The brief discussion of the Diaoyu/Senkaku Island conflict has shown that the processes that characterise this complex interaction have no intrinsic quality that exists outside of the actors and their performances. In other words, the processes are neither good nor bad in their own right, but receive these qualities through the judgements of those involved in them.

Conclusion: expanding IRT

The complexity of global politics is not only increasingly challenging the logic of the Westphalian system of nation-state politics and the Washington Consensus of economic governance with its teleology of economic development (and its supposed destination: liberal democracy). It is also challenging many of the core assumptions in mainstream IRT that provide justifications for the political systems they were designed to explain. The question of how to regulate societies in complex, dynamic environments and cooperate across regions has become a pressing issue across the globe, and scholars from diverse backgrounds have taken up the challenge of addressing these questions from arguably new perspectives, criticising mainstream IRT for its parochialism, and envisioning the world in terms other than conventional inter-nationality.

Poststructuralist theorists have taken up the challenge of reconceptualising international politics outside of mainstream paradigms, and they have received growing support from scholars in the field of so-called ‘non-Western’ IRT. This has included analytically-minded theorists from China and Taiwan, who have challenged the state-centric focus of conventional IR theorising, have shifted their focus to complex processes, and have asked how such processes shape the identities of and relations between actors. Where might such endeavours lead? I have argued that Chinese and Taiwanese IR theorising has value because it promises to provide fresh roadmaps to the territory of world politics. The various concepts that are currently on the table, and that I have outlined above, are still very much in a stage of ‘pre-theory’, but my tentative attempt to check their usefulness and limitations in the face of the on-going Diaoyu/Senkaku Island dispute has shown that their ability to capture complex processes has merit. Nevertheless, such theorising still has to confront several issues.

One such issue is the question of how to conceptualise the relation between state and non-state actors. Many of the authors reviewed in this article argue against a ‘methodological nationalism’ that treats states as black boxes. However, a convincing alternative will then have to carefully avoid falling back into the tried division between domestic and international politics, and the habit of treating states as persons, as procedural constructivism does when its proponents argue that states have ‘experience, expectations, and cognition’.Footnote 87 Worldist accounts, on the other hand, will have to justify their call for transitive consistency between the various ‘levels’ of the world (for example, the global, the national, and the family). Arguments by philosophers like Zhao Tingyang that all of these levels follow the same logic stand in harsh contrast to the findings from research into complex systems, which show that such transitivity is a myth.Footnote 88

Another question that remains is what role power plays in a relational, procedural account of politics. Qin has criticised mainstream IRT for its understanding of power as either ‘material capabilities (hard power) or cultural attraction (soft power)’, which ‘an independent actor possesses and [which] can be directly exercised on the receiver’.Footnote 89 Instead, he argues that ‘there is no power without relations’, and that relations are themselves sources of power.Footnote 90 Beyond this critique, however, Qin has to my knowledge not developed a concise account of how such relational power works. There is an opportunity here to make Chinese theorising constructively speak to poststructuralist theories of power (such as the works of Foucault, Derrida, or Bourdieu) as well as network theories, such as those developed by Ulrich Beck and Manuel Castells, respectively. Beck, for instance, argues that power in the age of our ‘second modernity’ is not about winning the game of politics, but about defining the rules of this game. The quest for power becomes an open-ended ‘rule-changing meta-power game’.Footnote 91 In this meta-game, ‘nothing remains fixed, neither the old basic institutions and systems of rules nor the specific organizational forms and roles of the actors; instead, they are disrupted, reformulated and renegotiated during the course of the game itself’.Footnote 92 Castells is similarly concerned with processes, arguing ‘power is not an attribute but a relationship’.Footnote 93 He interprets politics in the information age as network politics, and argues that we should examine power from the perspective of cognitive and communication processes. In Castells’ model, actors exert power by connecting their network to other networks, as well as by ‘switching’ other actors in their network on or off. They also exert power by ‘programming’ the network with specific values. Much like Beck, Castells is interested in meta-power in complex open-ended relationships that change through processes (or ‘flows’).Footnote 94

Overall, such network approaches offer new roads for IR theorising – roads that should appeal to theorists like Qin or Shih, precisely because they are concerned with shifting relations and varying socio-temporal contexts, and because they leave room to think of power in non-negative ways, that is, as the potential to connect with others.Footnote 95 They are also attractive approaches because they see actors as networks, nested in larger networks, and connecting with other actors (who, again, are themselves networks). Such a perspective is powerful because it does not shy away from complexity and dynamics, but in fact uses these elements to explain how politics work. Not only does such a theoretical framework include actors that mainstream IR often excludes (non-governmental organisations, enterprises, cities, neighbourhoods, families, football clubs, etc.), it also takes processes seriously that defy traditional intergovernmental relations, for instance transnational private-to-private or government-to-private interactions.

Whether they are willing to incorporate poststructuralist ideas or develop distinct frameworks, Chinese and Taiwanese IRT projects will need to be careful not to reproduce political programmes or serve vested political interests. As I have argued, some of the criticism from China, as well as some of the calls for a ‘China School’ of International Relations, are problematic due to the proclaimed uniqueness of the respective approaches. Such claims feed orientalist assumptions rather than making real contributions to the understanding of international politics. Hopefully, scholars from China, Hong Kong, Taiwan, or Chinese communities elsewhere will not simply receive attention because of their ostensible (and at times self-proclaimed) exoticism. Theoretical concerns from Chinese scholars are not important because they are somehow different, but precisely because they are not unique. They are arguably fresh perspectives, but at the same time they are based on legitimate observations of general problems – problems that need to be taken seriously if International Relations theories are to explain the complexity of twenty-first-century world politics. Chinese pre-theorising constitutes an important step in this direction, and may help bring some of the defects in conventional theory to the attention of established IRT. IR theorists need to rethink grand narratives and need to work with pragmatic solutions, drawn from diverse philosophical traditions, rather than buying into any one paradigm.Footnote 96 As Suganami has put it:

there are many ways in which the world – geographical or social – can be mapped. To suggest that any one map represents the social world ‘as it is’ is an effect of the power that the world so represented has upon the person who so suggests; and such a person is contributing to the legitimation and reproduction of that particular representation of the social world.Footnote 97

Suganami's comment is not merely a critique of theorising in mainstream IR, but also a warning to those who wish to rethink world politics from new angles. Such endeavours can only be fruitful if they allow for diversity. Otherwise they will merely replace the grand narratives IRT tells today with new grand narratives, leaving the discipline with revised though similarly one-sided political theories.

References

1 For examples drawing from French poststructuralist thinkers, see the Bourdieusian critique in Berling, Trine Villumsen, ‘Bourdieu, International Relations, and European Security’, Theory and Society, 41:5 (2012), pp. 451–78CrossRefGoogle Scholar, as well as the Deridarian arguments in Zehfuss, Maja, Constructivism in International Relations – The Politics of Reality (Cambridgeet al.: Cambridge University Press, 2002)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For feminist critiques, particularly of realist approaches to international security, see the various contributions in the Special Issue of Security Studies, 18:2 (2009). In addition, critical theorists like Robert Cox, David Campbell, or Michael Shapiro have similarly challenged mainstream IRT – for discussions see Moolakkattu, John S., ‘Robert W. Cox and Critical Theory of International Relations’, International Studies, 46:4 (2009), pp. 439–56CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Paipais, Vassilios, ‘Self and Other in Critical International Theory: Assimilation, Incommensurability and the Paradox of Critique’, Review of International Studies, 37:1 (2011), pp. 121–40CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 Seth, Sanjay, ‘Postcolonial Theory and the Critique of International Relations’, Millennium – Journal of International Studies, 40:1 (2011), p. 169CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3 See also the various contributions in Tickner, Arlene B. and Wæver, Ole (eds), International Relations Scholarship around the World (Oxon and New York: Routledge)Google Scholar as well as Acharya, Amitav and Buzan, Barry (eds), Non-Western International Relations Theory – Perspectives on and beyond Asia (Oxon and New York: Routledge, 2010)Google Scholar. For a discussion of approaches from Asia, see Shih Chih-yu, ‘The Plausible Asian Schools of International Relations: Hypothesizing Non-Interventionism’, European Research Center on Contemporary Taiwan Online Paper Series (EOPS No.2, Tübingen: Eberhard Karls Universität, 2009). For all Chinese names, this article follows the convention of placing the surname before the given name. Any translations are the author's, unless stated otherwise.

4 Yongjin, Zhang, ‘System, Empire and State in Chinese International Relations’, Review of International Studies, 27 (2001), p. 63Google Scholar.

5 See also, respectively, Damasio, Antonio, Self Comes to Mind – Constructing the Conscious Brain (London: William Heinemann, 2010)Google Scholar and Sperber, Dan, Explaining Culture – A Naturalistic Approach (Oxford and Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing, 1996)Google Scholar.

6 For a similar argument, see in particular ch. 1 in Trachtenberg, Marc, The Craft of International History – A Guide to Method (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2006)Google Scholar.

7 See also Acharya and Buzan (eds), Non-Western International Relations Theory, p. 3.

8 Acharya and Buzan (eds), Non-Western International Relations Theory, p. 6.

9 The diagram is not meant as a rigid taxonomy of approaches, setting up new dichotomies and placing scholars into set categories, but as a means to think about what different authors might aim to achieve through recourse to Chinese traditions, and how their contributions might enrich IRT. The distinctions should therefore not be understood in absolute terms, and many Chinese attempts to theorise politics indeed tend to fall between the extremes, often containing both universal and discrete claims as well as normative and analytical elements.

10 This is not to suggest that theories that aim to be ‘analytical’ are free of normative considerations. Suganami, Hidemi has criticised such distinctions in ‘The English School and International Theory’, in Bellamy, Alex J. (ed.), International Society and its Critics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005), pp. 2944Google Scholar, and in ‘Causal Explanation and Moral Judgement: Undividing a Division’, Millennium – Journal of International Studies, March (2011), pp. 1–18. Pragmatic political thinkers such as Geuss have made a similar point: see Geuss, Raymond, Philosophy and Real Politics (Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2008), p. 16Google Scholar. However, neither would be likely to argue that political thought should be guided by an ‘ideal theory’ that draws conclusions ‘about how people ought to act or live’ (ibid., p. 7).

11 Mittag, Achim, ‘Historiography’, Brill‘s Encyclopaedia of China (Leiden: Brill, 2009)Google Scholar.

12 On Chinese history, see Fairbank, John King and Goldman, Merle, China – A New History (2nd edn, Cambridge, MA and London: Belknap Press Harvard, 2006)Google Scholar.

13 The idea that there is one unified Confucian tradition is highly contested, particularly since many of the canonical ‘classics’ were heavily edited or even forged during later periods, such as the Han Dynasty, and interpreted in different ways throughout Chinese history. See Gernet, Jacques, A History of Chinese Civilization (2nd edn, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1972/2002), pp. 86–7Google Scholar.

14 Ling L.H.M., Hwang Ching-chang, and Chen Boyu, ‘China's Confucian Turn: Implications for Humanitarian Intervention and Global Governance’, conference paper presented at ‘Sovereignty and Humanitarian Intervention in the International Society of East Asia – Historical Legacies and New Dynamics’, 11 June 2010 (Leiden and The Hague: Modern East Asia Research Centre). See also Agathangelou, Anna M. and L.H.M., Ling, Transforming World Politics: From Empire to Multiple Worlds (Oxon and New York: Routledge, 2009), p. 92Google Scholar.

15 Analects XII, 22.1. See also Mengzi (Li Lao II, 28.2): ‘The benevolent man loves others’ (ren zhe ai ren 仁者爱人). The English translations of the Mengzi and Analects used here are taken from Legge, James, The Chinese Classics (Philadelphia: J. B. Lippincott and Co., 1876)Google Scholar.

16 Xuetong, Yan and Jin, Xu (eds), Wangba tianxia sixiang ji qidi (Thoughts of World Leadership and Implications) (Beijing: Shijie zhishi chubanshe, 2009)Google Scholar.

17 Hui, Victoria Tin-bor, ‘History and Thought in China's Traditions’, Journal of Chinese Political Science, 17 (2012), pp. 125–41CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

18 Yan and Xu (eds), Wangba tianxia, p. 241.

19 Yan Xuetong, ‘How China Can Defeat America’, The New York Times (20 November 2011), available at: {http://www.nytimes.com/2011/11/21/opinion/how-china-can-defeat-america.html?pagewanted=all} accessed 20 April 2012.

20 Qing, Jiang, Zhengzhi ruxue – dangdai ruxue de zhuanxiang, tezhi yu fazhan (Political Confucianism – Changes, Characteristics, and Developments in Contemporary Confucianism) (Beijing: San lian shudian, 2003)Google Scholar. For a review see Bell, Daniel A., China's New Confucianism: Politics and Everyday Life in a Changing Society (Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2008)Google Scholar. Note that the so-called ‘Confucian revival’ in Chinese politics should not be overemphasised. Confucian concepts form only part of the overall political discourse, and often in highly distorted ways, for instance when the CCP picks key terms like ‘harmony’ (he 和) and interprets them in line with New Left political thought. What is more, even such highly selective use of Confucian thought has encountered staunch opposition from Marxist scholars and cadres. For an example of such critique, see Keli, Fang, Xiandai xin ruxue yu Zhongguo xiandaihua (Modern Neo-Confucianism and China's Modernization) (Changchun: Changchun chubanshe, 2008)Google Scholar.

21 Yaqing, Qin, ‘Relationality and Processual Construction: Bringing Chinese Ideas into International Relations Theory’, Social Science in China, 30:4 (2009), p. 36Google Scholar.

22 Tingyang, Zhao, Tianxia tixi – shijie zhidu zhexue daolun (The ‘All-under-Heaven’ System – An Introduction to World System Philosophy) (Nanjing: Jiangsu jiaoyu chubanshe, 2005)Google Scholar.

23 Callahan, William A., ‘Chinese Visions of World Order: Post-hegemonic or a New Hegemony?’, International Studies Review, 10 (2008), pp. 749–61CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For a more favourable review of Zhao's work from a Chinese scholar, see Yiwei, Wang, ‘China: Between Copying and Constructing’, in Tickner, Arlene B. and Wæver, Ole (eds), International Relations Scholarship around the World (Oxon and New York: Routledge, 2009), pp.111–14Google Scholar.

24 Zhao, Tianxia tixi, p. 114. See also Tingyang, Zhao, ‘Rethinking Empire from a Chinese Concept “All-under-Heaven” (Tian-xia, 天下)’, Diogenes, 221:56 (2006), pp. 518Google Scholar.

25 Tingyang, Zhao, Huai shijie yanjiu – zuowei di yi zhexue de zhengzhixue (The Study of the Bad World – Political Philosophy as the Primary Philosophy) (Beijing: Zhongguo renmin daxue chubanshe, 2009), pp. 5175, 295Google Scholar, respectively.

26 Callahan, ‘Chinese Visions of World Order’, p. 758.

27 See Zhang, ‘System, Empire and State’, p. 54.

28 Qin, ‘International Society’, p. 36.

29 Ibid.

30 Callahan, ‘Chinese Visions of World Order’, p. 755, and Zhang, ‘System, Empire and State’, p. 51, respectively. For additional discussions of the tributary system, see Hsiao-Ting, Lin, ‘The Tributary System in China's Historical Imagination: China and Hunza, ca.1760–1960’, Journal of the Royal Asiatic Society of Great Britain and Ireland, 19 (2009), pp. 489507Google Scholar and Min, Shu, ‘Hegemon and Instability: Pre-Colonial Southeast Asia under the Tribute System’, WIAS Research Bulletin, 4 (2012), pp. 4562Google Scholar.

31 Wang, ‘China: Between Copying and Constructing’, p. 109. The call for a ‘harmonious society’ has become a cornerstone of CCP propaganda; see also Barmé, Geremie, ‘China's Flat Earth: History and 8 August 2008’, The China Quarterly, 197 (2009), pp. 6486CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

32 Callahan, ‘Chinese Visions of World Order’, p. 753.

33 Note the rhetorical question in Analects XIV, 8.0: ‘Can there be love which does not lead to strictness with its object?’ (ai zhi, neng wu lao hu 爱之、能勿劳乎).

34 Qin, ‘International Society’, pp. 148, 151.

35 Wang, ‘China: Between Copying and Constructing’, p. 117, fn. 12.

36 The idea of a public sphere is arguably an invention of the eighteenth- and nineteenth-century enlightenment movements in Europe; see also Habermas, Jürgen, Strukturwandel der Öffentlichkeit: Untersuchungen zu einer Kategorie der bürgerlichen Gesellschaft (The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere: An Inquiry into a Category of Bourgeois Society) (Berlin: Suhrkamp, 1990 [orig. pub. 1962])Google Scholar.

37 Wang, ‘China: Between Copying and Constructing’, p. 115.

38 Yiwei, Wang, ‘Tanxun Zhongguo de xin shenfen: guanyu minzuzhuyi de shenhua (Seeking China's New Identity: The Myth of Chinese Nationalism)’, Shijie zhengzhi, 2 (2006), pp. 1421, available at: {http://www.cas.fudan.edu.cn/picture/1433.pdf} accessed 20 April 2012Google Scholar.

39 Yiwei, Wang, ‘Between Science and Art: Questionable International Relations Theories’, Japanese Journal of Political Science, 8:2 (2007), p. 208Google Scholar. In another context, Wang expands his political project by arguing that a ‘China School’ of IRT ‘depends on the reunification of Taiwan and the Mainland’ (Wang, ‘China: Between Copying and Constructing’, p. 115). Apparently the diversity of worldviews he advocates elsewhere (ibid., p. 116) does not apply once the territorial integrity of the Chinese nation is in question.

40 Anderson, Benedict, Imagined Communities (3rd rev. edn, London and New York: Verso, 2006)Google Scholar.

41 For comprehensive analyses of Chinese nationalism, see Gries, Peter Hays, China's New Nationalism – Pride, Politics, and Diplomacy (Berkeleyet al.: University of California Press, 2004)Google Scholar and Suisheng, Zhao, A Nation-State by Construction – Dynamics of Modern Chinese Nationalism (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2004)Google Scholar.

42 Shih, ‘The Plausible Asian Schools’, p. 8.

43 Agathangelou and Ling, Transforming World Politics, p. 93.

44 Ibid.

45 Beck, Ulrich, Power in the Global Age (Cambridge and Malden, MA: Polity Press, 2007), p. 22Google Scholar.

46 Chih-yu, Shih, ‘Consuming Part-time Nationalism: China as an Immigrant in the Global Society’, New Political Science, 25:3 (2003), p. 367Google Scholar.

47 Yaqing, Qin and Ling, Wei, ‘Structure, Process, and the Socialization of Power – East Asian Community-Building and the Rise of China’, in Ross, Robert S. and Feng, Zhu (eds), China's Ascent: Power, Security, and the Future of International Politics (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2008), p. 135Google Scholar. It should be noted, however, that Qin and Wei do not follow through on this argument and in fact produce an analysis that focuses almost entirely on inter-state relations.

48 Chih-yu, Shih, ‘Assigning Role Characteristics to China: the Role State versus the Ego State’, Foreign Policy Analysis, 8 (2012), pp. 7191Google Scholar.

49 Qin and Wei, ‘Structure, Process, and the Socialization of Power’, p. 122.

50 Qin, ‘Relationality and Processual Construction’, p. 16.

51 Ibid., p. 14.

52 Ibid., pp.14–16.

53 Ibid., p. 15.

54 Shih, ‘The Plausible Asian Schools’, p. 8.

55 Shih, ‘Assigning Role Characteristics’, p. 74.

56 Qin, ‘Relationality and Processual Construction’, p. 14.

57 Ibid., p. 15.

58 Ibid.: pp. 9–10.

59 Ibid.

60 Ibid., p. 13.

61 For an overview of the conflict, see Koo, Min Gyo, ‘The Senkaku/Diaoyu Dispute and Sino-Japanese Political-Economic Relations: Cold Politics and Hot Economics?’, The Pacific Review, 22:2 (2009), p. 208CrossRefGoogle Scholar. The history of US involvement in the issue is examined in Blanchard, Jean-Marc F., ‘The U.S. Role in the Sino-Japanese Dispute over the Diaoyu (Senkaku) Islands, 1945-1971’, The China Quarterly, 161 (2000), pp. 95123CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Shaw, Han-yi provides a legal assessment in The Diaoyutai/Senkaku Islands Dispute: Its History and an Analysis of the Ownership Claims of the P.R.C., R.O.C., and Japan (Baltimore: School of Law, University of Maryland, 1999)Google Scholar and Lee, Lai To analyses the diplomatic aspects in China and the South Sea Dialogues (Westport and London: Praeger, 1999)Google Scholar.

62 For journalistic accounts of the most recent developments, see in particular the issue website of the BBC {http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/world-asia-pacific-11341139} accessed 24 January 2013. Scholarly analyses of previous disputes include Koo Min Gyo, ‘The Senkaku/Diaoyu Dispute’, pp. 205–32; Chung, Chien-Peng, ‘Resolving China's Island Disputes: A Two-Level Game Analysis’, Journal of Chinese Political Science, 12:1 (2007), pp. 4970CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Hagström, Linus, ‘“Power Shift” in East Asia? A Critical Reappraisal of Narratives on the Diaoyu/Senkaku Islands Incident in 2010’, The Chinese Journal of International Politics, 5 (2012), pp. 267–97CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

63 See also Blanchard, ‘The US Role’, pp. 95–6.

64 Hagström, ‘“Power Shift” in East Asia?’, p. 268.

65 Koo, ‘The Senkaku/Diaoyu Dispute’, p. 206.

66 Ibid., p. 227 and Chung, ‘Resolving China's Island Disputes’, p. 60, respectively.

67 Koo, ‘The Senkaku/Diaoyu Dispute’, p. 221.

68 Ibid. Chung's liberal, rationalist arguments on territorial disputes remain equally unconvincing, particularly his predictions for developments in the South China Sea, where he expects increased trade volumes to ‘expand the domestic constituencies for greater economic interdependence, which will lead to more willingness to cooperate on other non-economic issues’ (Chung, ‘Resolving China's Island Disputes’, p. 64). Considering recent developments in that region, such arguments seem fallacious.

69 Blanchard, ‘The US Role’, p. 123.

70 Qin and Wei, ‘Structure, Process, and the Socialization of Power’, p. 123.

71 Koo, ‘The Senkaku/Diaoyu Dispute’, p. 209.

72 Wendt has defended this perspective, arguing that states ‘are “intentional” or purposive actors’, and that ‘since intentionality is the primary quality of persons that scholars typically attribute to states’ this ultimately justifies ‘personifying state persons’; a practice ‘in which almost all of us engage’. He goes on to warn that ‘the question of the reality of state persons goes to the heart of IR's epistemic authority as a science of world politics’ – an argument with which I agree – and claims that ‘giving up the concept of state personhood would result in a substantial loss of extant scientific knowledge about world politics’ – an argument that I find questionable. See Wendt, Alexander, ‘The State as Person in International Theory’, Review of International Studies, 30 (2004), pp. 291–2, 316CrossRefGoogle Scholar, respectively.

73 See the various reports in The Guardian, particularly ‘Japan Stokes Tensions with China over Plan to Buy Disputed Islands’, available at: {http://www.guardian.co.uk/world/2012/sep/05/japan-china-disputed-islands?INTCMP=SRCH}, and ‘China Warns of Consequences as Japan Announces Purchase of Disputed Islands’, available at: {www.guardian.co.uk/world/2012/sep/11/china-warns-japan-disputed-islands} both accessed 24 January 2013.

74 Sheila Smith, ‘Why Japan, South Korea, and China Are So Riled Up Over a Few Tiny Islands’, The Atlantic, available at: {www.theatlantic.com/international/archive/2012/08/why-japan-south-korea-and-china-are-so-riled-up-over-a-few-tiny-islands/261224/} accessed 24 January 2013.

75 BBC News, ‘Japan Activists Land on Disputed Islands amid China Row’, available at: {www.bbc.co.uk/news/world-asia-china-19303931} accessed 24 January 2013.

76 The web-service China Smack has collected online discussions, both in the original Chinese and in English translation; see ‘The Diaoyu Island Dispute’, available at: {www.chinasmack.com/tag/diaoyu-islands-dispute} accessed 24 January 2013.

77 See also Chung, ‘Resolving China's Island Disputes’, and Hagström, ‘“Power Shift” in East Asia?’, respectively.

78 Qin and Wei, ‘Structure, Process, and the Socialization of Power’, pp. 130–7.

79 See, respectively, Ministry of Foreign Affairs of Japan, ‘Position Paper: Japan-China Relations Surrounding the Situation of the Senkaku Islands’ (9 November 2012), available at: {www.mofa.go.jp/region/asia-paci/senkaku/position_paper_en.html} and Gemba Koichiro, ‘Japan-China Relations at a Crossroads’, International Herald Tribune (21 November 2012), available at: {www.mofa.go.jp/mofaj/annai/honsho/gaisho/gemba/pdfs/iht_121121_en.pdf} both accessed 24 January 2013.

80 See Japan Times, ‘Xi Vows to Better Ties despite Isle Row’ (25 January 2013), available at: {www.japantimes.co.jp/news/2013/01/25/national/xi-vows-to-better-ties-despite-isle-row/#.UQLWuL-Yt0o} and Ministry of Foreign Affairs, the People's Republic of China, ‘Xi Jinping Meets with Natsuo Yamaguchi, Leader of Japan's New Komeito Party’, available at {www.fmprc.gov.cn/eng/zxxx/t1008008.shtml} both accessed 25 January 2013.

81 See, respectively, MOFA, ‘Position Paper’, and State Council Information Office, ‘Diaoyu Dao, an Inherent Territory of China’ (25 September 2012), available at: {news.xinhuanet.com/english/china/2012-09/25/c_131872152.htm} accessed 24 January 2013.

82 See Qin and Wei, ‘Structure, Process, and the Socialization of Power’, p. 134.

83 Note Qin's example of globalisation processes, for which he argues ‘if we accept that un-owned process exists in social life, we should also accept that process is its own prime mover and maintainer …. In the globalizing process, states and other actors of the international system continuously adapt, adjust, define, and redefine their self-interest. But no individual can be found that started the process or that can stop or reverse it.’ See Qin, ‘Relationality and Processual Construction’, pp. 10–11, emphasis added. While Qin's observation that the movers behind globalisation processes are hard to identify is surely accurate, it does not follow that there are no such actors, or that their influence on such processes is trivial. It is also no justification to stop looking for the persons and interest groups that actually ‘move’ the processes in world politics. What Qin is essentially arguing, is that a process like globalisation ‘happens’. Such an argument brings him in close proximity with the dominant discourse of PRC government officials, who argue that globalisation is ‘an inevitable trend of economic development’ – an unstoppable external force that simply is, and which nation-states like the PRC then react to, much like ships sailing a stormy ocean. See Wen Jiabao, ‘World Summit for Social Development and Beyond: Achieving Social Development for All in a Globalizing World’, speech held at the Special Session of the UN General Assembly (15 October 2003), available at: {www.china-un.org/eng/chinaandun/socialhr/shfz/t29344.htm} accessed 20 April 2012.

84 Hagström, though arguably approaching the subject from a different poststructuralist angle, has demonstrated how such methods can be deployed in the analysis of the Diaoyu/Senkaku Island conflict. See Hagström, ‘“Power Shift” in East Asia?’.

85 The term ‘structures of feeling’ is borrowed from Callahan, William A., China – The Pessoptimist Nation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010)Google Scholar.

86 See, for example, State Council Information Office, ‘Diaoyu Dao’.

87 Qin and Wei, ‘Structures, Processes, and the Socialization of Power’, p. 126.

88 Mitchell, Melanie, Complexity – A Guided Tour (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 2009)Google Scholar.

89 Qin, ‘Relationality and Processual Construction’, p. 17.

90 Ibid.

91 Beck, Power in the Global Age, p. 116.

92 Ibid., p. 4.

93 Castells, Manuel, Communication Power (Oxfordet al.: Oxford University Press, 2009), p. 11Google Scholar.

94 Ibid., p. 20.

95 In other words, such an approach makes it possible to reconceptualise Weberian power not as the ability to overcome opposition, or even the ability to achieve something (goal-oriented), but as the potential to act. This can also include the ability to engage others in non-confrontational ways, making it possible to reframe interactions in terms that are not zero-sum.

96 Note that this is not an endorsement of what Katzenstein has called ‘analytical eclecticism’. Katzenstein argues that IR scholarship should draw from mainstream theories as needed in order to cover the various dimensions of politics: relative gains, absolute gains, and symbolic interactions. While this move indeed helps overcome some of the limitations of mainstream IR, Katzenstein's approach nevertheless remains firmly anchored in the major research traditions it draws from, thereby arguably reinforcing rather than thoroughly challenging their premises. Also, this particular eclecticism is rooted in a specific analytical tradition that emphasises causal relations between variables and seeks to predict political outcomes. It remains unclear whether such eclecticism is versatile enough to accommodate both an Aristotelian approach to knowledge and its poststructuralist critique. This is a fundamental problem, particularly since scholars of complexity and emergent systems have shown how causal explanations and predictions of complex processes are not only impossible for practical reasons (lack of data), but also impossible in principle, due to the very nature of complex, dynamic processes (see Mitchell, Complexity). For Katzenstein's arguments and analyses, see Katzenstein, Peter J. and Nobuo, Okawara, ‘Japan, Asia-Pacific Security, and the Case of Analytical Eclecticism’, International Security, 26:3 (2001), pp. 153–85CrossRefGoogle Scholar, as well as Sil, Rudra and Katzenstein, Peter J., ‘Analytic Eclecticism in the Study of World Politics: Reconfiguring Problems and Mechanisms across Research Traditions’, Perspectives on Politics, 8:2 (2010), pp. 411–31CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

97 Suganami, ‘The English School’, p. 43, fn. 9.

Figure 0

Figure 1. Contemporary Chinese political theorising.