Hostname: page-component-6bf8c574d5-8gtf8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-23T17:57:37.841Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Return of Results in Participant-Driven Research: Learning from Transformative Research Models

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2021

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Participant-driven research (PDR) is a burgeoning domain of research innovation, often facilitated by mobile technologies (mHealth). Return of results and data are common hallmarks, grounded in transparency and data democracy. PDR has much to teach traditional research about these practices and successful engagement. Recommendations calling for new state laws governing research with mHealth modalities common in PDR and federal creation of review mechanisms, threaten to stifle valuable participant-driven innovation, including in return of results.

Type
Symposium Articles
Copyright
Copyright © American Society of Law, Medicine and Ethics 2020

Introduction

Biomedical research involving human participants is undergoing a revolution. In domains as disparate as genomics and environmental health, patients, families, and other members of the public are increasingly taking the lead. They may partner with traditional academic researchers or may fly solo. Organizations such as Genetic Alliance have become pioneers, forging new participant-driven (and family-driven) models of research, biobank assembly, and research governance.Reference Eriksson, Kaye, Terry, Terry, Vayena, Tasioulas, McGowan, Buyx, Lamas, Engelbrecht, Grant, Wiggins and Wilbanks1

The importance of these new research models is widely recognized. In the multi-year effort to revise the federal Common Rule regulating research with human participants, the emergence of these new models was cited as one of the catalysts for revision.2 The federal “All of Us” precision medicine research program expressly aims to facilitate participant-driven research, and incorporates a commitment to return individual-specific results and data in part for this purpose.3 A burgeoning literature documents the growing importance of these new forms of research, which I will group under the rubric “participant-driven research” (PDR). The literature uses a range of terms, including “citizen science.”4 In an era marked by sharp conflict over who is a “citizen” and how non-citizens are treated, this paper avoids the assumption that participants are (or should be) “citizens.”

When these new forms of PDR are conducted in partnership with traditional researchers at an academic institution, they are likely to fall under the Common Rule.5 Such institutions often render to the federal government a Federalwide Assurance (FWA), committing to oversee all research conducted by the institution under federal rules for research with human participants, regardless of whether a particular research project is funded by the federal government.6 PDR may also be conducted with partners aiming to develop a drug or device requiring federal approval for marketing and thus be covered by regulations on human subjects research promulgated by the federal Food & Drug Administration (FDA).7 PDR may further be conducted with funding from (or under the aegis of) a federal science agency, and thus be subject to federal rules on research with human participants.8 However, organizations and individuals may conduct PDR without such conventional collaborations. In that case, PDR may fall outside the Common Rule and FDA human subjects regulations. The organizers of such research may voluntarily elect to follow federal regulations and may seek review by an independent Institutional Review Board (IRB), but these steps are not ordinarily required. A small number of states impose their own compliance requirements that may reach PDR in their jurisdiction, but most do not.Reference Rothstein9

PDR often relies on the Internet to connect geographically separated individuals and mobile technology such as smartphones or activity trackers to collect and share information. Thus, a number of scholars have asked what rules or norms should govern PDR, especially when it falls outside the Common Rule and FDA regulations and may be facilitated by the Internet and mobile technology. Proposals have varied.Reference Vayena and Fiske10 Vayena and Tasioulas limit the requirement for formal ethics review to those projects posing more than minimal risk. Their caution in imposing this requirement is based on respect for the innovative character of PDR. They strive to “prevent ethics review becoming a strait-jacket on [PDR]-inspired innovation, stifling individual liberty, and serving as a disincentive to non-experts who might otherwise make valuable contributions to medical knowledge.” The danger is that ethics analyses will take traditional research as the gold standard and treat PDR as a rogue offshoot that requires taming. Thus, recommendations to impose federal oversight on the mHealth technologies commonly used in PDR including federal governance features modeled (strictly or loosely) on IRBs11 seem at odds with the fundamental thrust of PDR — to free research from traditional constraints and hierarchies. Even when those recommendations are aimed at mHealth technologies and Internet-enabled research, they threaten to significantly alter or close down much PDR.

It may be tempting to divorce the modality of mHealth-enabled research from the context in which it is used — here, PDR. That is highly problematic, as it treats the data-gathering and communicative machinery of research as the focus of legal and ethical analysis, stripped of context.

Such recommendations fail to recognize that PDR is actually leading research innovation in a number of ways, and that traditional research needs to learn from PDR rather than insisting on the reverse. One domain in which PDR is ahead is return of a participant’s results (RoR) — used here to include return of incidental or secondary findings — and providing participants with access to their own raw data. Many PDR projects are pioneering RoR and data access, with much to teach conventional research. Indeed, RoR and data access are central to many PDR projects.Reference Terry12 They inform participants of their individual findings, empower participants to make knowledgeable decisions about sharing their results and data, allow them to find others with related findings in order to collaborate in research, permit them to track emerging knowledge related to their findings, and catalyze them to seek clinical consultation as needed. RoR and data access in PDR move research designs away from the traditional paternalism in which only the researchers could view findings and data to a more horizontal model in which participants can themselves see those findings and make decisions about whether and how to share the information.

This pioneering contribution by PDR is under-recognized. When an analysis of PDR fails to pay attention to the path-breaking character of PDR in creating important models for RoR and data access and fails to recognize how central this feature is in much PDR,13 that analysis significantly under-credits PDR. It thus perpetuates a vision of PDR as less valuable than traditional research, with little to teach. And when commentary finds even less warrant for RoR in PDR than in traditional research,Reference Rothstein14 it misunderstands the architecture of much PDR, which often depends on robust involvement of participants, transparency about findings, and giving participant control over their own findings and data.

It may be tempting to divorce the modality of mHealth-enabled research from the context in which it is used — here, PDR. That is highly problematic, as it treats the data-gathering and communicative machinery of research as the focus of legal and ethical analysis, stripped of context. Context, however, makes all the difference. Consider an analogy: if research regulation and oversight were proposed for genetic testing regardless of how such testing was used in research, this would treat alike genetic testing in research to determine how best to provide care to patients with colorectal cancer, and genetic testing in research to decide what claims of familial relationship immigration authorities should allow at the U.S. southern border. Many other examples could illustrate the pitfalls of grounding research regulation on the technology used. The technology may certainly be relevant to evaluation of the research, but only in context. In assessing research, context matters.Reference Beskow and Burke15

Grounds for RoR and Data Access in PDR

A robust literature already details the ethical and legal grounds for RoR and access to data in traditional research. My focus here is on the grounds that obtain in PDR. While PDR is heterogeneous, four grounds for RoR and access to data generally obtain. The analysis below considers RoR and data access separately. Though they are often conflated, as both accomplish forms of information transfer and transparency, they actually have different histories and underpinning, as well as different processes.Reference Evans and Wolf16

1. Ethical Bases for RoR

First, the ethical grounds that have been articulated for RoR in traditional research generally apply to RoR in PDR as well. Commentators have articulated a range of ethical justifications for RoR, including participant vulnerability and partial entrustment of information to those performing the research leading to reciprocal duties,Reference Richardson17 the importance of researcher respect for participant autonomy and interests,Reference Illes18 the problem that withholding data makes participants “passive purveyors of biomaterials and data” not partners,Reference Kohane19 and in some cases the existence of a researcher duty to warn, especially when warning might prevent imminent harm.Reference Shah20 Most of these rationales do not require a particular type of researcher. A participant-(or family-) driven research organization would be subject to these same arguments. While a physician or other clinician conducting research might be subject to additional arguments for RoR (such as those based on the researcher being a type of professional with special access to participant informationReference Miller21), the organization conducting PDR is already subject to adequate grounds for RoR.

It is important to recognize what is being argued here. Some commentators have misunderstood the literature on RoR (including return of incidental or secondary findings) as relying on a claim that RoR is mandatory.Reference Rothstein and Morreim22 For the most part, the RoR literature does not make this claim. Instead, RoR is customarily subdivided into cases in which researchers should consider return, may consider return in their discretion, and should not consider return.Reference Wolf, Fabsitz, Wolf, Jarvik and Wolf23 “Should” is not “must.” Moreover, the RoR literature is virtually uniform in arguing that RoR should generally be an offer to convey findings, not an insistence.24 If the participant chooses to refuse the offer, they have the right to do so.

2. Legal Grounds for RoR

To date, the ethical grounds for RoR have received far more attention than the legal grounds. Yet many (though not all) of the legal grounds for RoR could apply in PDR, not just in traditional research. For example, an assertion that the researchers owed a duty of reasonable care that in a specific case warrants RoR, could ground a claim for research negligence if RoR was not undertaken. This would likely be a negligence claim, not a malpractice claim; malpractice claims generally apply only to clinicians rendering clinical care, rather than non-clinicians conducting research.Reference Marchant and McGuire25 In the research context, claims of negligence figure larger, the claim being that the researcher (whether a professional or not) failed to exercise ordinary care or failed to act as a prudent researcher. As yet, there are few cases litigating failure to return research results (though there are reported cases suing for failure to appropriately communicate results in clinical care, rather than researchReference Clayton, Pike, Wolf, Wolf and Wolf26).

There are some legal grounds for RoR that would not apply in PDR that lies beyond the Common Rule and FDA regulations on research with human participants, namely the provisions of these regulations themselves that support RoR. Legal commentators have argued that the provisions of these regulations requiring informed consent and detailing the need to specify potential risks and benefits support the necessity of addressing whether RoR will be offered and the implications of offering it or failing to do so as part of the protocol.Reference Wolf27 Indeed, the revised Common Rule includes provisions requiring researchers to clarify whether RoR will be offered.28 In addition, the Common Rule and FDA regulations call for communicating findings that may affect a participant’s willingness to continue in the research.29 That provision, too, may support a duty to offer a finding that may have such an effect.

3. Ethical Grounds for Access to Data

In the context of PDR, commentators have offered strong justification for participant access to their own data. In the context of Internet-enabled research and citizen science, Vayena and colleagues have emphasized the importance of participant access to their own data and using participatory data governance models that can create a “data democracy.”Reference Vayena, Blassime, Vayena and Tasioulas30 Evans has illuminated the virtues of self-governing data communities, lauding them as an advance over traditional models of research that robbed participants of data access and control. “The existing regulations… do not excite people about becoming partners in the grand scientific challenges of the twenty-first century… showering individuals with unwanted, paternalistic protections—such as barriers to the return of research results—while denying them a voice in what will be done with their data.”Reference Evans31 Lunshof and colleagues argue that, “providing access to their raw data is essential to taking individuals seriously as partners in research not merely as sources of samples and data.”Reference Lunshof, Evans and Thorogood32

PDR projects and advocates have themselves done the best job of articulating the importance of facilitating participant access and control. Thorogood and colleagues explain:

There are many good reasons for researchers to provide access to individual-level uninterpreted data. Empirical studies show that many people believe that their genomic data belongs to them…. Providing access may also build trust and incentivize participation. Moreover, patients are often experts in their condition and may be more motivated to determine the relevance of their health data than researchers focused on discovery. Access will enable curious citizen scientists to explore the myriad meanings of their DNA. Research may even thrive when individuals themselves share data with patient-led registries, research projects, or public repositories like openSNP or Open Humans.33

Participants’ access to their own raw data is a hallmark of PDR. This type of data transparency and open access is central to PDR’s respect for participants as the drivers of this type of research.

4. Legal Grounds for Access to Data

The law conferring a right of data access may be relevant as well to PDR.Reference Evans34 The best-known law conferring a right of data access in the United States is the Health Insurance Portability and Accountability Act (HIPAA) Privacy Rule.35 HIPAA’s application depends on the involvement of a HIPAA-covered entity. PDR research, even when conducted outside of a health care institution or academic center that is a covered entity, may utilize a laboratory that is HIPAA-covered.

HIPAA, however, is only one example of a law conferring a right of data access. Many additional federal and state statutes do so as well. Indeed, there is nearly a 50-year history in American law of recognizing data access rights in multiple contexts.Reference Evans, Wolf, Evans, Wolf and Evans36 This stands to reason. Individuals have a strong interest in seeing what data are being held on them. Those data may pose privacy risks, reputational risks, and risks of being subject to discrimination and stigma. Unless people can see information collected on them, they have no way of assessing those risks and deciding whether to authorize further use and sharing of those data. Indeed, data may sometimes be incorrect and require revision.37

Whether specific federal or state law would apply to a particular PDR protocol, biobank, or data repository would depend on the facts. The general point, however, is that rights of data access suffuse federal and state law. Analysis of their application to a particular PDR project will often be warranted.

Strengths and Potential Concerns over RoR and Data Access in PDR

Commentators have cautioned that RoR in the mHealth research that is a frequent hallmark of PDR “raises a variety of issues including the quality and validity of the findings provided, the scientific rigor, validity of data and quality, app users’ expectations and understanding of the limitation of these findings and their privacy interests.”38 Yet these same core issues — research data quality and whether participants understand the limits of the research findings and difference between research and clinical results — are debated as well in the context of traditional research. In fact, RoR and data access in PDR echo a broader trend toward designing research to allow participant access to their own information and the capacity to self-manage it, including in return of results.Reference Yu and Kohane39

A recent report from a committee of the National Academies on RoR in research involving biospeci-mens focused mainly on traditional research and recommended limiting both RoR and data access based on data quality.40 That committee held up clinical data as the gold standard, and evidenced great reluctance to endorse access to research findings and data that did not meet clinical standards, creating multiple roadblocks and requirements. Evans and I have argued that the committee erred in its understanding of the ethics and the law, on both RoR and data access.41 Much research generates information and data that are exploratory and do not meet clinical standards. The committee itself cited studies — such as those involving environmental exposures — that could not yet generate clinical-grade data, but were firmly based in a community of participants and committed to sharing results while scientific understanding progressed.42 The committee further recognized that research projects have already developed impressive methods for communicating research findings together with the caveat that the information’s clinical and health implications are still being investigated and no clinical action should be taken based on the research findings without clinical confirmation. As indicated above, the case for participant access to raw data regardless of data quality is also clear.43

At the same time, responsible handling and communication of research data and findings are ethically required in all research with human participants. This requirement flows not just from law (including the Common Rule and FDA regulations on research with human participants), but from multiple other sources as well, including participant expectations, organizational commitments and reputational concerns, and journal publication requirements. The requirement applies to both traditional research and PDR. Indeed, examples the National Academies committee cites of community-based and participant-driven research with deep roots in the participant community and strong communicative practices suggest that traditional research may have much to learn from PDR.44 Particular PDR protocols (like particular protocols in traditional research) can certainly raise issues. But to approach PDR research projects as intrinsically more problematic than traditional research — including protocols from well-established PDR entities responsibly conducting sophisticated research and carefully offering RoR and data access — is a mistake.

PDR studies are fully capable of eliciting careful and informed consent. They can clearly state the quality of the data they generate — whether clinical-quality data (e.g., from a CLIA-certified laboratory), or research-quality data whose meaning is still being investigated. They can caution participants to refrain from making clinical decisions based on data that are not clinical grade. When PDR projects make interpreted results available to their participants, they can again communicate warnings about the nature of those interpretations. If the analytic and clinical validity of the interpretations is not established, they can communicate this warning. Indeed, PDR studies with strong participant governance have the advantage that they are likely to be motivated to assess participant understanding and perspectives in order to refine their communicative strategies, and likely to know how to perform this assessment effectively. They can also establish recommended referral pathways to clinical assessment and care for those participants whose data and/or interpreted results suggest a need for clinical follow-up and evaluation. PDR studies can take advantage of their participant engagement to rigorously assess their communicative practices, participant understanding and actions, and the practical usability of routes to clinical care.

Particular PDR protocols (like particular protocols in traditional research) can certainly raise issues. But to approach PDR research projects as intrinsically more problematic than traditional research — including protocols from well-established PDR entities responsibly conducting sophisticated research and carefully offering RoR and data access — is a mistake.

What PDR Can Teach Traditional Research

Participant-driven research has much to teach traditional research on multiple fronts. Certainly, the level of participant engagement in much PDR would be the envy of many traditional research projects struggling to recruit and retain participants. The self-governing quality of PDR communities and organizations, their accountability to participants, and their transparency about research results, individuals’ data, and aggregate findings create a fundamentally different landscape than typically found in traditional research. Studying how PDR communities and organizations form, how they conduct research, and how they ensure accountability and transparency would offer an enlarged set of possibilities to traditional research.

To some extent, community-based participatory research (CBPR) occupies the middle ground between traditional and participant-driven research. CBPR can take multiple forms, with some commentators describing a spectrum involving greater or lesser community control.Reference Blumenthal45 PDR goes a step further by assuming that participants are driving the research, sometimes with no involvement with traditional researchers, and often enabled by Internet communications and mobile technologies such as smartphones.

When Vayena et al. laud the virtues of PDR “data democracies” and Evans shows the powerful possibilities open to self-governing data communities, they invite traditional researchers to learn from practitioners of PDR. Instead of treating PDR as the unruly off-spring of “real” research, they respect the potential of PDR to create new and powerful models for research. They treat PDR protocols as sites for learning.

Conclusion: Learning from PDR

Return of results and data access are commonly core elements of participant-driven research. They are central features, not bugs. The methods that PDR projects use and protections they incorporate deserve special study by traditional research entities.

Whether traditional research mechanisms will learn from PDR remains an open question. The rhetoric of respect for new, more participant-driven research models is now commonplace. From the preface to the revised Common Rule to the “All of Us” program’s commitment to returning participants’ data, the rhetoric is everywhere. As always, however, there is a big difference between talking the talk and actually embracing PDR and what it offers. The actual content of the revised Common Rule offers little to PDR and learns little from it. And whether “All of Us” will actually facilitate PDR remains an open question.

PDR is still evolving, though a number of models have emerged. As Rothstein et al. acknowledge, most collection of data using mobile devices and the Internet — a central method in PDR — involves very limited risk. Yet they urge all states to promulgate law governing this and all research. They recommend that federal bodies (namely, the National Institutes of Health (NIH) with the Office for Human Research Protections (OHRP) at the U.S. Department of Health & Human Services (DHHS)) educate those involved in mHealth research and urge those federal bodies to create research review organizations.46

None of this constitutes learning from the methods core to PDR. This instead treats those methods and PDR as a problem to be tamed by those in charge of traditional research and regulation. There is signifi-cant danger that state governments in regulating all research would stifle PDR, and that NIH and OHRP in creating research review organizations for PDR would re-impose the rules that organizations and communities conducting PDR have found detrimental to sustained engagement and progress in scientific understanding.

Threats to clamp down on the methods used in PDR will come as no surprise to those involved. Perhaps the last recommendation offered by Rothstein et al. offers some hope. Those authors recommend that, “Organizations of researchers conducting studies in unregulated environments, such as community organizations, member associations, and patient research networks, should adopt guidance and/or standards for their members….”47 There may be safety in numbers and articulation of collective norms. Ultimately, the future of PDR rests on the willingness of PDR organizations and communities to persist — to share their protocols and practices, to show how they handle RoR and data access, to publish their findings, and offer transparency on risks and benefits. On the other side of the divide, the future of traditional research may rest on the willingness to learn from PDR experiences, embrace change, and recognize progress.

Acknowledgments

Preparation of this article was funded in part by National Human Genome Research Institute (NHGRI), National Cancer Institute (NCI), and Office of the Director grant #R01CA207538 (Rothstein, Wilbanks, PIs) on “Addressing Ethical, Legal, and Social Issues (ELSI) in Unregulated Health Research Using Mobile Devices” and by NHGRI and NCI grant #1R01HG008605 (Wolf, Clayton, Lawrenz, PIs), on “LawSeq: Building a Sound Legal Foundation for Translating Genomics into Clinical Application.” The views expressed in this article are those of the author and not necessarily those of the funders.

Footnotes

The author reports grants from NIH during the conduct of the study.

References

On participant-driven research generally, see, e.g., Eriksson, N. et al., “Web-Based, Participant-Driven Studies Yield Novel Genetic Associations for Common Traits,” PLoS Genetics 6, no. 6 (2010): e1000993; Kaye, J. et al., “From Patients to Partners: Participant-centric Initiatives in Biomedical Research,” Nature Reviews Genetics 13, no. 5 (2012): 371-376; Terry, S. F. and Terry, P. F., “Power to the People: Participant Ownership of Clinical Trial Data,” Science Translational Medicine 3, no. 69 (2011): 69cm3; Vayena, E. and Tasioulas, J., “Adapting Standards: Ethical Oversight of Participant-Led Health Research,” PLoS Medicine 10, no. 3 (2013): e1001402; McGowan, M. L. et al., “‘Let’s Pull These Technologies Out of the Ivory Tower’: The Politics, Ethos, and Ironies of Participant-Driven Genomic Research,” BioSocieties 12, no. 4 (2017): 494-519; Buyx, A. et al., “Every Participant is a PI. Citizen Science and Participatory Governance in Population Studies,” International Journal of Epidemiology 46, no. 2 (2017): 377-384; Lamas, E. et al., “The Meaning of Patient Empowerment in the Digital Age: The Role of Online Patient-Communities,” in Engelbrecht, R. et al., eds., The Practice of Patient-Centered Care: Empowering and Engaging Patients in the Digital Era (IOS Press, 2017): 43-47, available at <https://books.google.com/books?hl=en&lr=&id=qvA-DwAAQBAJ&oi=fnd&pg=PA43&ots=JtLNTfvNlm&sig=KlDzQVP2qjTMsbsRFS47Y7fjI28#v=onepage&q&f=false> (last visited February 17, 2020); Grant, A. D. et al., “Approaches to Governance of Participant-Led Research: A Qualitative Case Study,” BMJ Open 9, no. 4 (2018): available at <https://bmjopen.bmj.com/content/9/4/e025633> (last visited February 17, 2020); Wiggins, A. and Wilbanks, J., “The Rise of Citizen Science in Health and Biomedical Research,” American Journal of Bioethics 19, no. 8 (2019): 3-14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Department of Homeland Security et al., “Federal Policy for the Protection of Human Subjects: Final Rule,” Federal Register 82 (2017): 7149-7258.Google Scholar
See Precision Medicine Initiative (PMI) Working Group Report to the Advisory Committee to the Director, NIH, “The Precision Medicine Initiative Cohort Program — Building a Research Foundation for 21st Century Medicine” (2015), available at <https://www.nih.gov/sites/default/files/research-training/initiatives/pmi/pmi-working-group-report-20150917-2.pdf> (last visited February 17, 2020); National Institutes of Health (NIH), All of Us Research Program, Participation, available at <https://allofus.nih.gov/about/participation> (last visited February 17, 2020).+(last+visited+February+17,+2020);+National+Institutes+of+Health+(NIH),+All+of+Us+Research+Program,+Participation,+available+at++(last+visited+February+17,+2020).>Google Scholar
See generally Vayena and Tasioulas, supra note 1, at first page (“These projects are described as ‘citizen driven’, ‘participant driven’, ‘crowd sourced’, or ‘participant centric’ research. What they have in common is that participants are the leading force in the initiation or conduct of research projects.” (references omitted)).Google Scholar
45 C.F.R. pt. 46, subpt. A. See also U.S. Department of Health & Human Services, Office for Human Research Protections, Federal Policy for the Protection of Human Subjects (‘Common Rule’), available at <https://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/regulations-and-policy/regulations/common-rule/index.html> (last visited February 17, 2020).+(last+visited+February+17,+2020).>Google Scholar
See U.S. Department of Health & Human Services, Office for Human Research Protections, Federalwide Assurance (FWA) for the Protection of Human Subjects, available at <https://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/register-irbs-and-obtain-fwas/fwas/fwa-protection-of-human-subjecct/index.html> (last visited February 17, 2020).+(last+visited+February+17,+2020).>Google Scholar
21 C.F.R. pts. 50, 56. See also U.S. Department of Health & Human Services, Office for Human Research Protections, Food & Drug Administration, available at <https://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/regulations-and-policy/regulations/fda/index.html> (last visited February 17, 2020).+(last+visited+February+17,+2020).>Google Scholar
See, e.g., Crowdsourcing and Citizen Science Act of 2017, 15 U.S.C. § 3724.Google Scholar
See Rothstein, M.A. et al., “Unregulated Health Research Using Mobile Devices: Ethical Considerations and Policy Recommendations,” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 48, no. 1, Suppl. (2020): 196-226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See, e.g., Vayena and Tasioulas, supra note 1; Vayena, E. et al., “Research Led by Participants: A New Social Contract for a New Kind of Research,” Journal of Medical Ethics 42, no. 4 (2015): 216-219; Wiggins & Wilbanks, supra note 1; Fiske, A. et al., “Meeting the Needs of Underserved Populations: Setting the Agenda for More Inclusive Citizen Science of Medicine,” Journal of Medical Ethics 45, no. 9 (2018): 617-622.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Rothstein et al., supra note 9.Google Scholar
See, e.g., Fiske et al., supra note 10, at 620 (“Claims of democratisation generally envision a world in which patients have full access to their own data….”); Terry, S.F., “The Tension Between Policy and Practice in Returning Research Results and Incidental Findings in Genomic Biobank Research,” Minnesota Journal of Law, Science & Technology 13, no. 2 (2012): 691-736.Google Scholar
See Rothstein et al., supra note 9, (“Unregulated research may generate novel individual findings that unregulated researchers may want to return to participants either through the app or by re-identifying app users. This situation raises a variety of issues…. Return of results is a complicated matter discussed separately in this symposium.” (footnote omitted with citation to this article)).Google Scholar
See Rothstein, M.A. et al., “Citizen Science on Your Smart-phone: An ELSI Research Agenda,” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 43, no. 4 (2015): 897-903, at 901 (“It is difficult to imagine that unregulated, citizen science health research containing few of the characteristics of the researcher-participant relationship would give rise to comparable ethical obligations to disclose incidental findings.”).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See, e.g., Beskow, L.M. and Burke, W., “Offering Individual Genetic Research Results: Context Matters,” Science Translational Medicine 2, no. 38 (2010): 1-5, available at <https://stm.sciencemag.org/content/scitransmed/2/38/38cm20.full.pdf> (last visited February 17, 2010).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Evans, B.J. and Wolf, S.M., “A Faustian Bargain that Undermines Research Participants’ Privacy Rights and Return of Results,” Florida Law Review 71, no. 4 (2019): 1281-1345.Google Scholar
Richardson, H.S., “Incidental Findings and Ancillary Care Obligations,” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 36, no. 2 (2008): 256-270.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Illes, J. et al., “Incidental Findings in Brain Imaging Research,” Science 311, no. 5762 (2006): 783-784.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kohane, I.S. et al., “Reestablishing the Researcher-Patient Compact,” Science 316, no. 5826 (2007): 836-837.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See, e.g., Shah, S.K. et al., “What Does the Duty to Warn Require?” American Journal of Bioethics 13, no. 10 (2013): 62-63; Beskow and Burke, supra note 15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, F.G. et al., “Incidental Findings in Human Subjects Research: What Do Investigators Owe Research Participants?,” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 36, no. 2 (2008): 271-279.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Rothstein, et al., “Citizen Science on Your Smartphone,” supra note 14; Morreim, H., “The Return of Individual-Specific Research Results from Laboratories: Perspectives and Ethical Underpinnings,” Appendix D, in National Academies of Science, Engineering, and Medicine (NASEM), Returning Individual Research Results to Participants: Guidance for a New Research Paradigm (National Academies Press, 2018): 339-358.Google Scholar
See, e.g., Wolf, S.M. et al., “Managing Incidental Findings in Human Subjects Research: Analysis and Recommendations,” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 36, no. 2 (2008): 219-24, at 242; Fabsitz, R.R. et al., “Ethical and Practical Guidelines for Reporting Genetic Research Results to Study Participants: Updated Guidelines from a National Heart, Lung, and Blood Institute Working Group,” Circulation: Cardiovascular Genetics 3, no. 6 (2010): 574-580; Wolf, S.M. et al., “Managing Incidental Findings and Research Results in Genomic Research Involving Biobanks and Archived Data Sets,” Genetics in Medicine 14, no. 4 (2012): 361-384; Jarvik, G.P. et al., “Return of Genomic Results to Research Participants: The Floor, the Ceiling, and the Choices in Between,” American Journal of Human Genetics 94, no. 6 (2014): 818-826; Wolf, S.M. et al., “Returning a Research Participant’s Genomic Results to Relatives: Analysis and Recommendations,” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 43, no. 3 (2015): 440-463.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See, e.g., sources cited in the prior endnote.Google Scholar
See Marchant, G. et al., “From Genetics to Genomics: Facing the Liability Implications in Clinical Care,” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 48, no. 1, Suppl. (2020): 11-43. See also McGuire, A.L. et al., “Can I Be Sued for That? Liability Risk and the Disclosure of Clinically Significant Genetic Research Findings,” Genome Research 24, no. 5 (2014): 719-723.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Clayton, E.W. et al., “Managing Incidental Genomic Findings: Legal Obligations of Clinicians,” Genetics in Medicine 15, no. 8 (2013): 624-629. For more on law, see Pike, E. R. et al., “Finding Fault? Exploring Legal Duties to Return Incidental Findings in Genomic Research,” Georgetown Law Journal 102 (2014): 795-843; Wolf, et al., “Managing Incidental Findings in Human Subjects Research,” supra note 23; Wolf, et al., “Managing Incidental Findings and Research Results in Genomic Research Involving Biobanks,” supra note 23; Wolf, S.M., “The Role of Law in the Debate over Return of Research Results and Incidental Findings: The Challenge of Developing Law for Translational Science,” Minnesota Journal of Law, Science & Technology 13, no. 2 (2012): 435-448.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Wolf, S.M. et al., “The Law of Incidental Findings in Human Subjects Research: Establishing Researchers’ Duties,” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 36, no. 2 (2008): 361-383, at 366.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See 45 C.F.R. § 46.116 (c) (8) (“one or more of the following elements of information, when appropriate, shall also be provided to each subject…: A statement regarding whether clinically relevant research results, including individual research results, will be disclosed to subjects, and if so, under what conditions….”).Google Scholar
See Wolf et al., supra note 27.Google Scholar
See Vayena, E. and Blassime, A., “Biomedical Big Data: New Models of Control Over Access, Use and Governance,” Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 14 (2017): 501-513. See also Vayena, E. and Tasioulas, J., “Adapting Standards: Ethical Oversight of Participant-Led Health Research,” PLoS Medicine 10, no. 3 (2013): e1001402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Evans, B.J., “Barbarians at the Gate: Consumer-Driven Health Data Commons and the Transformation of Citizen Science,” American Journal of Law & Medicine 42, no. 4 (2016): 651-685.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lunshof, J.E. et al., “Raw Personal Data: Providing Access,” Science 343, no. 6169 (2014): 373-374, at 374. See also Evans, B.J. et al., “Regulatory Changes Raise Troubling Questions for Genomic Testing,” Genetics in Medicine 16, no. 11 (2014): 799-803, at 799–803 (discussing the individual right of access to one’s own data and implications for return of results); Thorogood, A. et al., “APPLaUD: Access for Patients and Participants to Individual Level Uninterpreted Genomic Data,” Human Genomics 12, no. 1 (2018): 7, (supporting “a default right of participants to access their own individual-level genomic data upon request”).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thorogood et al., supra note 32, at 4 (references omitted).Google Scholar
For further consideration of this topic and the relevance of FDA Investigational Device Exemption (IDE) requirements, see Evans, B.J., “The Perils of Parity: Should Citizen Science and Traditional Research Follow the Same Ethical and Privacy Principles?” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 48, no. 1, Suppl. (2020): 74-81. Evans specifically considers the applicability of FDA requirements (such as the requirement of an IDE) when a research app developer intends to provide medical information for diagnosis. A responsible research app developer, however, should generally not aim to substitute for a clinician performing a clinical evaluation. Instead, the developer should offer a warning that RoR and data in research are no substitute for clinical evaluation and that individuals concerned by their results and data should consult a clinician and seek such an evaluation. For further discussion of the applicability of IDE requirements, see Rothstein et al., supra note 9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Pub. L. No. 104-191, 110 Stat. 1936 (1996) (codified as amended in scattered sections of 18, 26, 29, and 42 U.S.C. (2012)); 45 C.F.R. pts. 160, 164 (2018).Google Scholar
See Evans and Wolf, supra note 16; Evans, B.J., “HIPAA’s Individual Right of Access to Genomic Data: Reconciling Safety and Civil Rights,” American Journal of Human Genetics 102, no. 1 (2018): 5-10; Wolf, S.M. and Evans, B.J., “Return of Results and Data to Study Participants,” Science 362, no. 6411 (2018): 159-160; Wolf, S.M. and Evans, B.J., “Defending the Return of Results and Data,” Science 362, no. 6420 (2018): 1255-1256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Evans and Wolf, supra note 16.Google Scholar
Rothstein et al., supra note 9.Google Scholar
See, e.g., Yu, J-H et al., “Self-Guided Management of Exome and Whole-Genome Sequencing Results: Changing the Results Return Model,” Genetics in Medicine 15, no. 9 (2013): 684-690. See also Kohane, I.S. et al., “Reestablishing the Researcher-Patient Compact,” Science 316, no. 5826 (2007): 836-837 (presenting a research model in which a participant can elect to receive research results by “‘tun[ing] in’ to a broadcast”).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
NASEM, supra note 22.Google Scholar
See Evans and Wolf, supra note 16; Wolf and Evans, “Return of Results and Data to Study Participants,” supra note 36; Wolf and Evans, “Defending the Return of Results and Data,” supra note 36.Google Scholar
See NASEM, supra note 22, at 196-98.Google Scholar
See, e.g., Thorogood et al., supra note 32; Vayena and Blassime, supra note 30.Google Scholar
See, e.g., NASEM, supra note 22, at 196-98 (environmental health studies).Google Scholar
See, e.g., Blumenthal, D.S., “Is Community-Based Participatory Research Possible?” American Journal of Preventive Medicine 40, no. 3 (2011): 386-389.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Rothstein et al., supra note 9.Google Scholar