Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-kw2vx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T15:16:03.826Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The reification objection to bottom-up cognitive ontology revision

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 June 2016

Joseph B. McCaffrey
Affiliation:
Department of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh, PA 15217. jbm48@pitt.edumachery@pitt.eduhttp://www.josephbmccaffrey.comhttp://www.hps.pitt.edu/profile/machery.php
Edouard Machery
Affiliation:
Department of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh, PA 15217. jbm48@pitt.edumachery@pitt.eduhttp://www.josephbmccaffrey.comhttp://www.hps.pitt.edu/profile/machery.php

Abstract

Anderson (2014) proposes a bottom-up approach to cognitive ontology revision: Neuroscientists should revise their taxonomies of cognitive constructs on the basis of brain activation patterns across many tasks. We argue that such bottom-up proposal is bound to commit a mistake of reification: It treats the abstract mathematical entities uncovered by dimension reduction techniques as if they were real psychological entities.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2016 

Reverse inference consists in inferring that a task recruits a psychological process (P) on the grounds that a brain structure (S) is activated during this task (as observed by, e.g., fMRI). It is often assumed that reverse inference is valid only if activation is selective, that is, if the ratio P(activation of S/P is recruited)/P(activation of S/P is not recruited) is high (Poldrack Reference Poldrack2006). Because brain areas are typically multifunctional, cognitive neuroscientists have grown skeptical of area-based reverse inference. Anderson endorses this pessimistic conclusion – “It should go without saying that we must also curtail the common practice of reverse inference” (Anderson Reference Anderson2014, p. 113) – and the first two chapters of After Phrenology (Anderson Reference Anderson2014) extensively review the multifunctionality, hence low selectivity, of brain regions.

One can address the problem raised by multifunctionality in three different ways. First, reverse inference can be reformulated to depend on diagnosticity instead of selectivity (Machery Reference Machery2014). In this approach, reverse inference is valid only if the activation discriminates between the recruitment of a first psychological process, P, and of a second psychological process, P′, that is, only if the ratio P(activation of S/P is recruited)/P(activation of S/P' is recruited) is high. Second, one can increase the selectivity of brain activation by revising cognitive neuroscientists' brain ontology: Instead of focusing on regional activation, one can reverse infer on the basis of activation in other brain structures (e.g., networks) that may be selectively associated with psychological processes (e.g., Glymour & Hanson, Reference Glymour and Hansonforthcoming). In chapter 4 of After Phrenology, Anderson rejects this second approach on the grounds that brain networks too can be multifunctional. Anderson's concern here is speculative, and more evidence is needed before discrediting brain ontology revision. Large-scale brain networks (e.g., effective connectivity networks), or activation patterns within those networks (e.g., as measured by MVPA), may be far more selective or diagnostic than individual regions. Third, one can increase the selectivity of brain activation by revising cognitive neuroscientists' cognitive ontology: On this approach, activation of brain structures is not selective because cognitive neuroscientists lack the right set of cognitive constructs for describing the functions or computations that these structures perform (e.g., Poldrack Reference Poldrack2010).

This third approach has led to a lively debate about cognitive ontology revision (Klein Reference Klein2012; Lenartowicz et al. Reference Lenartowicz, Kalar, Congdon and Poldrack2010; McCaffrey Reference McCaffrey2015; Poldrack et al. Reference Poldrack, Halchenko and Hanson2009; Price & Friston Reference Price and Friston2005). As Anderson perspicuously notes, most “revisionists” have a conservative goal: Taking current cognitive ontology as their starting point, they attempt to validate cognitive constructs by investigating whether they can be selectively associated with brain activation patterns (e.g., Lenartowicz et al. Reference Lenartowicz, Kalar, Congdon and Poldrack2010). By contrast, chapter 4 of After Phrenology advocates a revolutionary goal. Anderson's project is not to determine which members of current cognitive ontologies are valid and which are invalid, but rather to propose entirely new cognitive constructs by mining fMRI datasets. Before describing and assessing Anderson's proposal, we note that it is unclear whether his goal is to revolutionize the constructs psychologists are working with (e.g., recommending they stop using the construct of working memory) or, less ambitiously, whether he is proposing a new cognitive ontology for cognitive neuroscientists: In this case, the idea would be to develop novel ways of characterizing what neural structures do.

Anderson's central idea is that cognitive neuroscientists should not characterize the intrinsic function of each brain region – that is, the operation the region performs independently of its neural context (e.g., its computational function); instead, they should quantitatively characterize each region's disposition to be involved in a given set of tasks. Anderson calls such dispositions “neural personalities.” Neural personalities allegedly vary with respect to some fundamental psychological dimensions (or “neuroscientifically relevant psychological (NRP) factors”), exactly as personality varies with respect to a few dimensions (e.g., extraversion). The dimensions of neural personality need not correspond to existing cognitive constructs, and they must be discovered by examining brain activation across many tasks (more on this below).

Several points about Anderson's proposal are noteworthy. First, the focus on neural personalities instead of intrinsic functions is a radical change of heart for Anderson, who previously advocated characterizing regions' workings – roughly, their context-insensitive computational functions (Anderson Reference Anderson2010). Second, it is not clear whether Anderson denies that brain regions have intrinsic functions or merely thinks the best strategy for cognitive neuroscientists is to characterize their neural personalities, while conceding that future efforts could identify their intrinsic functions. The anti-computationalist rhetoric in After Phrenology suggests the former, but more guarded remarks support the latter. Third, Anderson mainly resists the call to revise brain ontology, focusing mostly on the brain structures – that is, individual regions – that cognitive neuroscientists have traditionally studied. In this respect, After Phrenology is surprisingly conservative. Fourth, Anderson's focus on neural personalities implies that, in contrast to Poldrack's approach, the search for selective activation plays no role in cognitive ontology revision: A “central point of this book is not just that we don't get selectivity in the brain but that we don't need it. We can stop looking for it” (Reference Anderson2014, p. 141, emphasis in the original). Fifth, Anderson proposes to identify the dimensions of neural personalities (the NRP factors) in a strictly bottom-up manner: The proposal is to infer these new cognitive constructs from the brain's “behavior” – its activation patterns – across many tasks. In this respect, After Phrenology is surprisingly radical. Cognitive neuroscientists typically impose existing cognitive constructs onto the brain to interpret task-related activation. Instead, Anderson proposes using brain activation patterns across tasks to determine their psychological nature – what the tasks have in common and how they differ from a psychological point of view: “[O]ne can (…) use these data [i.e., the data from imaging experiments] to let the brain tell us something about these experiments – to reveal the underlying attributes of the task situation to which the brain differentially responds” (Reference Anderson2014, p. 138).

How should researchers interpret NRP factors (the dimensions along which neural personalities vary) and neural personalities themselves? There are two ways of interpreting them: an instrumentalist or a realist interpretation. According to the instrumentalist interpretation, these dimensions (NRP factors) are just a way of summarizing how similar the brain activation patterns elicited by the tasks under consideration are, and ascribing a neural personality to a brain area is just nothing more than a way of summarizing the data showing how this area is differentially active in a set of tasks. According to the realist interpretation, the dimensions of neural personality are real psychological constructs: That is, they can feature in causal explanations. After Phrenology is unclear about which of these two interpretations is correct, but Anderson appears to view NRP factors as explanatory and causal: “NRP factors should be understood as a region's disposition to help shape an organism's behavior in a situation, to help determine the character of the organism's interaction with its environment, or to manage some aspect of the organism-environment relationship” (Reference Anderson2014, p. 151). These two interpretations of neural personalities should be familiar to readers acquainted with the history of psychology: Psychologists have long debated whether traits such as IQ or personality dimensions should be interpreted instrumentally or realistically.

Our main contention is that, just like other attempts at revising cognitive ontologies in a strictly bottom-up manner, Anderson's revolutionary endeavor to develop new cognitive constructs – the NRP factors and the neural personalities – can be interpreted only instrumentally, and that this is in tension with his goal of developing a new set of causally explanatory cognitive constructs. To characterize brain areas' dispositions, Anderson first appeals to the notion of a functional fingerprint developed by Passingham et al. (Reference Passingham, Stephan and Kötter2002) (Anderson Reference Anderson2014, sect. 4.2; Anderson et al. Reference Anderson, Kinnison and Pessoa2013; Uddin et al. Reference Uddin, Kinnison, Pessoa and Anderson2014). Identifying a region's functional fingerprint begins with categorizing the tasks in the fMRI literature on this area as recruiting one of several psychological processes. Anderson and colleagues (Reference Anderson, Kinnison and Pessoa2013) typically use a coarse-grained categorization scheme, distinguishing about 20 processes such as vision, attention, phonology, semantics, learning, or working memory. This scheme allows them to represent quantitatively how often, according to a given literature, a given area is activated when one of these 20 processes is recruited by an experimental task, for example how often articles studying working memory report activation in the dorsal anterior insula. The pattern of recruitment of a given area, given a particular set of fMRI articles and a categorization scheme, is its functional fingerprint. Although, unsurprisingly, areas tend to be activated by many processes, their functional fingerprints vary. Importantly, a functional fingerprint is a mere summary of a data set: It does not explain why the area is activated the way it is.

Following Poldrack et al. (Reference Poldrack, Halchenko and Hanson2009), Anderson (Reference Anderson2014, sects. 4.3 and 4.4) proposes to use dimension reduction techniques (factor analysis, MDS, PCA, etc.) to identify a few dimensions explaining why an area has its functional fingerprint. Instead of merely summarizing the involvement of a given area in a set of tasks, as functional fingerprints do, neural personalities explain this involvement: They allow cognitive neuroscientists to claim that because an area has a given neural personality (its score is i on NRP factor 1, j on NRP factor 2, etc.), it is involved more in some tasks than in others.

However, dimension reduction techniques are ill suited for discovering new cognitive constructs (Glymour Reference Glymour2001; Gould Reference Gould1996). These statistical techniques project high-dimensional spaces onto spaces with fewer dimensions. On their own, the resulting dimensions cannot be interpreted realistically; they merely provide convenient ways of summarizing high-dimensional data. Three main arguments support this deflationary understanding of dimension reduction techniques. First, the outcome of these techniques is underdetermined. A given set of vectors in a high-dimensional space can be projected onto different spaces with different dimensions. To highlight merely three issues, there are many nonequivalent dimension reduction techniques, the number of dimensions is typically arbitrarily chosen, and these dimensions can be oriented in different manners. None of the possible spaces should be interpreted realistically because it would be arbitrary to treat one of them as real to the detriment of the others. Second, just like causally-based correlations, accidental correlations can be projected onto a lower-dimensional space, resulting in meaningless dimensions (e.g., Gould Reference Gould1996, p. 280). Hence, that a high-dimensional space can be projected onto a lower-dimensional space does not justify interpreting the resulting dimensions realistically. Finally, the capacity of dimension reduction techniques such as factor analysis to identify causes has not been validated (Glymour Reference Glymour2001, Ch. 14). These three arguments bear on Anderson's project, exactly as they bear on IQ and personality research: On their own, dimension reduction techniques do not justify interpreting the dimensions of neural personalities realistically. Forgetting their limitations is committing the error of reification – namely, presuming that the abstract mathematical entities uncovered by dimension reduction analyses correspond to real psychological entities.

Naturally, the products of dimension reduction techniques can sometimes be interpreted realistically instead of as mere instruments for summarizing high-dimensional data. To do so scientists need to bring their broader empirical knowledge to bear on the interpretation of the dimensions of the lower-dimensional space. In the present context, this means that a purely bottom-up approach to cognitive ontology revision is unlikely to succeed: Some other information beyond the activation of brain areas across a range of tasks and their dimension reduction is needed to interpret the resulting dimensions realistically. Perhaps it is also worth noting that establishing the predictive validity of neural personalities does not justify understanding them realistically.

Anderson's approach to cognitive ontology revision is not the only one to fall prey to this reification objection; in fact, we speculate that in general purely bottom-up cognitive ontology revisions commit the error of reification (e.g., Poldrack et al. Reference Poldrack, Halchenko and Hanson2009). Such approaches must reduce the very high-dimensional space defined by the number of voxels considered in order to identify cognitive constructs defined solely by brain activation patterns. Doing so probably requires using techniques whose product cannot be interpreted realistically. In our opinion, the reification objection reveals a fundamental shortcoming of bottom-up cognitive ontology revision.

References

Anderson, M. L. (2010) Neural reuse: A fundamental organizational principle of the brain. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33(4):245–66. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X10000853.Google Scholar
Anderson, M. L. (2014) After phrenology: Neural reuse and the interactive brain. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, M. L., Kinnison, J. & Pessoa, L. (2013) Describing functional diversity of brain regions and brain networks. NeuroImage 73:5058.Google Scholar
Glymour, C. (2001) The mind's arrows: Bayes nets and graphical causal models in psychology. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glymour, C. & Hanson, C. (forthcoming) Reverse inference in neuropsychology. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.Google Scholar
Gould, S. J. (1996) The mismeasure of man. WW Norton.Google Scholar
Klein, C. (2012) Cognitive ontology and region-versus network-oriented analyses. Philosophy of Science 79:952–60.Google Scholar
Lenartowicz, A., Kalar, D. J., Congdon, E. & Poldrack, R. A. (2010) Towards an ontology of cognitive control. Topics in Cognitive Science 2:678–92.Google Scholar
Machery, E. (2014) In defense of reverse inference. British Journal for Philosophy of Science 65:251–67.Google Scholar
McCaffrey, J. (2015) The brain's heterogeneous functional landscape. Philosophy of Science 82:1010–22.Google Scholar
Passingham, R. E., Stephan, K. E. & Kötter, R. (2002) The anatomical basis of functional localization in the cortex. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 3:606–16.Google Scholar
Poldrack, R. A. (2006) Can cognitive processes be inferred from neuroimaging data? Trends in Cognitive Sciences 10:5963.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Poldrack, R. A. (2010) Mapping mental function to brain structure: How can cognitive neuroimaging succeed? Perspectives on Psychological Science 5(6):753–61.Google Scholar
Poldrack, R. A., Halchenko, Y. O. & Hanson, S. J. (2009) Decoding the large-scale structure of brain function by classifying mental states across individuals. Psychological Science 20:1364–72.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Price, C. J. & Friston, K. J. (2005) Functional ontologies for cognition: The systematic definition of structure and function. Cognitive Neuropsychology 22(3–4):262–75.Google Scholar
Uddin, L. Q., Kinnison, J., Pessoa, L. & Anderson, M. L. (2014) Beyond the tripartite cognition–emotion–interoception model of the human insular cortex. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 26:1627.Google Scholar