The argument from hiddenness
Say theism is the view that God – an omnipotent, omniscient, perfectly loving, and perfectly good being – exists. Many people don’t believe in God. And arguably many non-believers are non-resistant to belief in God – they would believe in God if only they had sufficient reason to do so (e.g. religious experience or a persuasive argument for theism). But if God exists, his omnipotence makes it such that he has the power to make all those not resistant to belief in him believe, his omniscience makes it such that he knows what it would take to make those non-resistant believe in him, his perfect love makes it such that he wants what’s best for all his creation, and his perfect goodness makes it such that he always does what’s right and never does what’s wrong. But then – so the argument goes – there probably wouldn’t be non-resistant non-believers, or as I shall call them non-resistant atheists.Footnote 1 This is because having a relationship with God is (arguably) in the best interest of all persons, and this means – if God is perfectly loving – he would be open to such a relationship. And, moreover, believing God exists is necessary to have a relationship with him – you can’t have a relationship with a person if you don’t believe she exists.Footnote 2 So, at the very least, God would ensure those who aren’t resistant to having a relationship with him would believe he exists. This is a minimum requirement of theism. However, there (at least) probably are (or have been) some non-resistant atheists: we all know people who want to believe in God and yet can’t bring themselves to do so. Moreover, we know that, historically, certain persons have lacked the concept of God, and hence couldn’t believe in God. So, since (at least probably) there are or have been some non-resistant atheists, it follows that, probably, God doesn’t exist.Footnote 3 Call this The Hiddenness Argument.
There have been numerous challenges presented to The Hiddenness Argument. Some argue there are goods that require the existence (or the permission of the existence) of non-resistant atheism, and that God would likely bring about these goods (e.g. Dustin Crummett Reference Crummett2015, Travis Dumsday Reference Dumsday2015, Reference Dumsday2016a, Reference Dumsday2016b, Reference Dumsday2016c, Reference Dumsday2018; Daniel Howard-Snyder Reference Howard-Snyder, Green and Stump2015, Kirk Lougheed Reference Lougheed2018) and others have expressed skepticism about this requirement (e.g. Hud Hudson Reference Hudson2017 and Perry Hendricks Reference Hendricks2023). It’s not my purpose to adjudicate this debate here, so I won’t consider the plausibility of these responses. Instead, below, I will explicate one particular response to The Hiddenness Argument that appears to be relatively popular, and tease out its implications.
Crummett (Reference Crummett2015), Dumsday (Reference Dumsday2010), and Richard Swinburne (Reference Swinburne1998) all defend The Responsibility Objection to The Hiddenness Argument. Roughly, the thought behind The Responsibility Objection is that it’s good for us to come to know God, his purposes, and so on through participation in communities in which we are mutually responsible for each other’s coming to know these things (Crummett Reference Crummett2015). Moreover, it’s good for us to be responsible for helping others come to know God, his purposes, and so on. This good – the good of having this kind of responsibility – makes it such that it’s worth the non-belief it requires.Footnote 4 So, at least some non-resistant atheism – the kind required for this sort of responsibility – isn’t a problem for theism. Of course, there may be other reasons why God allows non-resistant atheism – The Responsibility Objection doesn’t claim it’s the only reason God allows non-belief – but this is at least one reason why God allows (at least some) non-resistant atheism.
There’s some appeal to this view: being responsible for another person coming to know important truths is a good thing. For example, Daryl Davis is personally responsible for over 200 members of the Klu Klux Klan leaving the Klan.Footnote 5 That is no doubt a good and admirable thing for him to have done. And this responsibility of ours to help others come to know important moral truths is indeed valuable. Moreover, being responsible for helping someone have a relationship with another person is good. For example, if I’m responsible for helping an adopted child come to know her long-lost mother, I’ve done something good. And this suggests that if having a relationship with God is in one’s best interest (as defenders of The Hiddenness Argument maintain), then it’s good for us to have the responsibility of bringing others into this relationship. So, there’s at least some plausibility to The Responsibility Objection – there’s some plausibility to the claim that God would allow non-resistant atheism in order to allow us to have the valuable and important responsibility involved with helping others come to know him.Footnote 6
Obviously, there are objections that can and have been made to this view.Footnote 7 However, it isn’t my purpose to adjudicate this dispute here. Instead, my purpose is to tease out a novel implication of The Responsibility Objection. So, I’m just going to assume that the responsibility objection succeeds to see what follows.Footnote 8
The problem of gratuitous evil
Evil is often taken to be a problem for theism. Some think evil is incompatible with God’s existence (e.g. J.L. Mackie Reference Mackie1955), and others think that some fact about evil poses an evidential problem for theism (e.g. Paul Draper Reference Draper1989; Draper, Reference Draperforthcoming and William Rowe Reference Rowe1979, Reference Rowe and Howard-Snyder1996). There have been many proposed solutions to the problem of evil. For example, some argue that free will explains (at least partially) why God allows evil (e.g. Swinburne Reference Swinburne1998), others argue that building connections between persons plays an important role (e.g. Robin Collins Reference Collins, J and D2013), and still others claim the best possible worlds contain evil, because these – the best possible worlds – contain incarnation and atonement, which require evil (e.g. Alvin Plantinga Reference Plantinga and van Inwagen2004).
For my purposes, I want to focus on one particular variant of the problem of evil, namely, the problem of gratuitous evil. An evil is said to be gratuitous (or axiologically gratuitous)Footnote 9 just in case its permission isn’t required to prevent an evil (or set of evils) equally bad or worse or to produce a greater good (or set of goods).Footnote 10 Rowe (Reference Rowe and Howard-Snyder1996) claims there are evils for which we recognize no greater good of which their permission was required to produce. And so, he infers, these evils are probably gratuitous.Footnote 11 However, claims Rowe, God’s existence is incompatible with gratuitous evil. And so, probably, God doesn’t exist.
There have been numerous responses to Rowe’s argument: some try to cast doubt upon whether there is gratuitous evil (e.g. Swinburne Reference Swinburne1998), others argue that gratuitous evil is compatible with theism (e.g. Peter Van Inwagen Reference Van Inwagen2006 and Justin Mooney Reference Mooney2019), and still others cast doubt upon the inference from our lack of recognition of a good that would justify God in allowing evil to the conclusion that there probably is no such reason (e.g. Bergmann Reference Bergmann2001, Reference Bergmann, Flint and Rea2009, Reference Bergmann, Clark and Rea2012; Hendricks Reference Hendricks2023; Howard-Snyder Reference Howard-Snyder and Kvanvig2009; Hudson Reference Hudson and Kvanvig2014). However, one response in particular is of interest for my purposes, namely William Hasker’s (Hasker Reference Hasker1992, Reference Hasker2004, Reference Hasker2008). Hasker doesn’t dispute that there’s gratuitous evil. Rather, he argues, roughly, that if all evils are required for a greater good, it would undermine one of our best reasons for preventing evil – it would morally demotivate us. And so God must allow gratuitous evil to avoid this result. In other words, if we believe God exists and that all evils lead to a greater good, one of our best reasons for preventing evil is undermined, and we lose motivation for preventing the evil. For example, suppose I come across Sarah assaulting Sally. And suppose I’m a theist and I believe God wouldn’t allow evil unless its permission was required for a greater good. If that’s the case, I know that if I allow this assault to continue, it will result in a greater good. Thus, I lose one major reason for intervening: if I prevent the assault, I’m thereby preventing a greater good from obtaining – the world is going to be better if I allow the assault to continue.Footnote 12 So, I shouldn’t intervene – or, at least, my best reason for intervening has been undermined.Footnote 13 Because of this, Hasker argues, God must allow gratuitous evil – if he doesn’t, we will become morally demotivated.
While Hasker primarily frames the issue psychologically – we would lose motivation to intervene – one can also run his argument in terms of rationality and reasons. Footnote 14 Assume we are irrational if we act in a way that goes against what we have most reason to do. And assume that every instance of evil leads to a greater good. If that’s true, we lose one – and perhaps our strongest – reason for preventing evil. That is, one of our strongest reasons for preventing evil is that the world is made worse off on account of the evil. But if that’s not true – if all evils result in a greater good – that’s no longer a reason for us to prevent evil, and it may be irrational for us to do so – we would be making the world worse by doing so, after all! Insofar as rationality is valuable, God has reason to ensure that his creatures act rationally when preventing evil. And this means God would not ensure there’s no gratuitous evil. For my purposes, it doesn’t matter which way we frame Hasker’s argument – although, I’ll note I find it more plausible when framed in terms of rationality and reasons.
Of course, objections can and have been raised to Hasker’s argument (e.g. Klaas Kraay Reference Kraay2019). It’s not my purpose to evaluate Hasker’s position or objections to it here. Rather, I want to tease out an implication of this sort of reasoning when it’s paired with The Responsibility Objection discussed above. So, I’m going to just assume it’s correct for the sake of argument to see what follows.Footnote 15
Pointless atheism
As mentioned above, many have cited particular goods or reasons that God has for allowing non-resistant atheism. However, I’ll argue here that – assuming The Responsibility Objection and that something like Hasker’s view is correct – theism is compatible with – indeed, predicts – pointless atheism, that is, non-resistant atheists whose non-belief doesn’t result in a greater good.Footnote 16
Why think that theism and pointless atheism are compatible given these assumptions? Here’s why. First, assume that God may allow non-resistant atheism only if it’s required for a greater good. (This seems to be an assumption made by both opponents and proponents of The Hiddenness Argument – no one has argued, to my knowledge, to the contrary.) Second, assume The Responsibility Objection is correct, that is, God allows at least some Footnote 17 non-resistant atheism because it’s required for humans to be responsible in bringing others into relationship with God, and so on. Given these assumptions, if theism is true, at least some non-resistant atheism is permitted in order to bring about a greater good, namely, the good of our having the responsibility to help others come to know God.
At this point, it should be clear that Hasker-esque reasons come into play. Suppose it’s true that God would allow some bad state of affairs only if it resulted in a greater good. Non-resistant atheism, of course, is a kind of bad state of affairs. Given this, it follows that non-resistant atheism occurs only if there’s a greater good it’s required for. So, if it’s true that non-resistant atheism only occurs if its permission is required for a greater good and God allows (at least some) non-resistant atheism to give humans the responsibility to bring others into relationship with him, then our best reason for helping others come into relationship with God has been undermined.Footnote 18 This is because, given these assumptions, it follows that all instances of non-resistant atheism are cases in which either (i) they will come to know God or (ii) their continued lack of relationship with God will result in a greater good. So, any case in which one might try to help a non-resistant atheist come to know God will be unmotivated (or, less motivated): we know that if the non-resistant atheist remains an atheist, a greater good will come from it. And so we need not intervene to help this person come to know God – after all, if we don’t, the world will be better!Footnote 19 So, if God wants us to be responsible for helping others come to know him, he needs to allow instances of non-resistant atheism that don’t bring about a greater good, that is, God needs to allow pointless atheism. This is the only way for us to have responsibility for bringing others into relationship with him and for us to be motivated (or, have reason) to do so. This result is surprising, for it shows that not only is non-resistant atheism compatible with theism, pointless atheism is compatible with theism. Furthermore, it follows from this that theism entails pointless atheism, meaning we should expect there to be pointless atheism if theism is true – a result more surprising than finding a Dutchman with a small nose!
Objections
In this section, I’ll consider several objections one might raise to my above argument.
The problem of the amount of pointless atheism
One might claim the amount of pointless atheism poses a problem of theism. So, even though God might allow some pointless atheism, he wouldn’t allow as much pointless atheism as we find in our world. There’s much to say about this charge, but I won’t dispute it here.Footnote 20 Rather, my purpose is just to show the compatibility of pointless atheism with theism, given the assumptions made above.
A paradox?
One might claim that I’ve reached a paradoxical result: I’ve claimed, given theism, there’s pointless atheism, but, given the assumptions laid out above, there is a point: purportedly pointless atheism is, given my argument, required to ensure that humans are responsible for, and motivated to, help others come to know God. Hence, atheism isn’t pointless after all!
Is there a paradox here? In brief, no. Here’s why. My argument above shows there are instances of non-resistant atheism for which no greater good comes about, that is, there’s pointless atheism. However, this is compatible with there being a reason (or greater good) for the class of non-resistant atheism – that there is a reason for the whole doesn’t entail there’s a reason for each individual part.Footnote 21 Put differently, there is in fact pointless atheism – non-resistant non-belief that could be eliminated without making the world worse – despite there being a global reason for non-resistant atheism. So, there’s no paradox here. At most, there’s a ‘pair of docs’ – the pair of docs in this case being Dr Philip Swenson and Dr William Hasker mentioned above.
What if theists remain motivated?
Perhaps one would object that there are many theists who actually think that everything in this world is for the best, and yet they continue to proselytize. So, it looks like, for this group, motivation to help others come to know God hasn’t been undermined even though they think all non-resistant atheism results in a greater good. But this seems to conflict with my argument above.
Several lines of reply are in order here. First, this is a general objection to Hasker’s argument, which it’s not my intention to defend here. (Again, I’m making a conditional argument that assumes Hasker’s view is correct.) Second, while it’s likely that theists described above exist, it’s also likely there are theists whose motivation would be undermined if all instances of non-resistant atheism resulted in a greater good. So, God would have reason to allow pointless atheism so that group of theists wouldn’t have their motivation undermined. Indeed, nothing in my argument requires that all persons lose such motivation – that some would be demotivated is sufficient for my purposes. Third, and more importantly, perhaps it’s a sociological fact that some people continue to proselytize despite recognizing that a greater good would come about if they didn’t. But then we should think that those people are irrational. So, insofar as God would be interested in producing creatures who act rationally in response to reasons, this means that God would make it such that one would be rational in proselytizing, meaning that he would allow pointless atheism.Footnote 22
Objections to Hasker and the responsibility objection
At this point, one might raise objections to Hasker’s argument or to The Responsibility Objection. Indeed, many have raised objections to these views. However, it isn’t my purpose to defend these positions here. Rather, my purpose is to show that if these views are accepted, we get a surprising result: pointless atheism is compatible with theism. Indeed, it’s expected given theism. So, insofar as these views are plausible, it’s plausible to think that we should expect pointless atheism if theism is true.
Conclusion
I’ve argued that, given two assumptions,Footnote 23 it follows that theism is compatible with (and perhaps we should expect there to be) pointless atheism. This has the result that theists need not explain all instances of non-resistant atheism. Instead, given theism, we should expect there to be pointless atheism.
Acknowledgements
Thanks to Philip Swenson, Noah McKay, Jashiel Resto, and Eric Sampson for discussions about this issue. I asked each of them if this was a terrible idea, and none of them said it was – at least to my face! Any errors in my article, therefore, should be attributed solely to them. Thanks to Amos Wollen for helping me with my title – any complaints about the title should be sent his way. Thanks to G.L.G. – Colin Patrick Mitchell – for particularly insightful comments. Thanks also to a couple helpful referees, who provided comments that exceeded the length of this article! Finally, I owe thanks to Paul Draper: the idea for this article originated in a Directed Study I took with him in 2019 – I was too lazy to write it up until recently.