Hostname: page-component-6bf8c574d5-rwnhh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-21T23:26:34.422Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

William D. Casebeer, Natural Ethical Facts: Evolution, Connectionism, and Moral Cognition. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press (2003), x + 214pp., $35.00 (cloth).

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Michael Bradie*
Affiliation:
Bowling Green State University
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Book Reviews
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

The ambitious aim of this book is to show how a pragmatic, neo-Aristotelian virtue theory that emerges from an appreciation of results in (1) evolutionary biology, (2) cognitive science, and (3) ethics can lead to both a revolutionary understanding of moral theory and to a radical reformation of social institutions. The idea is to forge a naturalistic, normative moral theory that is “empirically tractable.”

There is a good deal of literature on the possible interconnections between evolutionary psychology and ethics. The problem is that there is no general agreement about what the implications, if any, would be. For starters, evolutionary psychology seems to promise, at best, an empirical account of the evolution of our moral sentiments. Most moral philosophers, on the other hand, think that the articulation and justification of norms and behaviors are the central concerns of ethics. It is not at all clear what the relevance of the empirical story for the moral story might be.

The apparent dichotomy between facts and values poses a formidable problem for all those who seek to defend a naturalistic interpretation of norms. On the surface, it appears that facts are facts and norms are norms and never the twain shall meet (or so the tradition goes). On the other hand, the naturalist is committed to somehow bridging the gap between them or trying to argue that, despite appearances, norms just are facts (albeit perhaps of a peculiar kind). The argument of this book is that moral theory is (at once) a piece with our scientific knowledge about the workings of the world and that norms are facts about the world and not so peculiar after all.

Casebeer proposes a modern neo-Aristotelian (virtue theory of) ethics that taps into Ruth Millikan's (Reference Millikan1984) notion of “proper function” and Peter Godfrey-Smith's (Reference Godfrey-Smith1996) “modern-history” modification of the notion of proper functions. The view basically is this: Natural selection has shaped the evolution of functional capacities that enable organisms to successfully interact with their environments and enhance their fitness. As the ambient circumstances change, these capacities take on new functions in succeeding generations.

Following Dewey, Casebeer takes moral norms and theories to be functional instruments or tools that we use to investigate eco-social environments. Tools, he notes, are by nature, contextually constrained. Thus, we can explain how it is that, although all humans share a general evolutionary history and cognitive architecture, they still manage to produce a wide variety of social practices and particular moral norms.

Moral knowledge, Casebeer claims, is basically a set of ‘knowing-hows’ that enable us to make our way around in our social environment (104ff). This know-how can be best represented in terms of neural networks. The activation patterns of these networks can be represented in terms of multidimensional state spaces. The idea is that we might empirically explore such a space to discover whether, for example, as Casebeer suggests (105), “a Principal Components Analysis (PCA) might reveal that a particular axis correspond[s] to a particular normative moral theory.” But, what if it did? Suppose we succeeded in constructing such a multi-dimensional map and discovered that a PCA revealed that one major axis that explained most of the variance in what people take to be morally correct actions corresponded to, say, rule utilitarianism. How would that discovery amount to a “proof” that rule utilitarianism is the proper moral view? Would it, at best, only show that rule utilitarianism explains why people make the moral judgments that they do?

Remarks to the effect that a PCA might resolve the debate between moral particularists and moral universalists is symptomatic of the worries that moral questions are being illicitly transformed into empirical questions that are significantly different from the originals. For example, Casebeer writes “Perhaps the principal components and unifying concepts of morality really are captured by the “big three [Aristotelian virtue theory, Kantianism and Utilitarianism]” moral theories discussed in this book … or perhaps not. Moral progress [sic!] will consist in the continued exploration of this question, using the feedback of moral functional experience as our pragmatic guide (115).” Well, perhaps … if we construe moral theories as attempts to explain why people have the moral views they do and not as attempts to provide justifications for those views.

It is a well known axiom of moral theory that “ought” implies “can.” Casebeer points out that a cognitive psychology and evolutionary biology are waiting on the sidelines to supply information that may well serve to constrain and delimit the range of moral principles. Even so, this is not an argument for the superiority of this particular combination of empirical theories as potential constraints on moral theorizing. And even if it were, it is not clear what the constraints might be and hence it is not clear what the relevance of the empirical input really would be. By conceding that modern times may modulate the proper functions that constitute human virtues, we run the risk of diluting the significance of the evolutionary and cognitive stories for determining what they are. To take an example from the physical virtues, consider the ability of humans to fly. Unlike birds, insect and some ingenious mammals, human beings were not endowed by their creator with this natural ability. This has not prevented human beings from flying through the air with the greatest of ease by employing airplanes, balloons, helicopters, rockets and other sundry and assorted environmental contrivances. I daresay that a similar lack of constraint would be found with respect to the moral virtues as well.

These reservations vitiate to an extent Casebeer's criticism of Kantian moral theory as “transcendental.” It is flawed, he claims, since the theory provides no guidelines for the use of the categorical imperative or for the Kantian test of universalizability (pp. 129ff.). It is certainly true that the transcendental strain in Kant is at odds with the kind of naturalism that Casebeer advocates, but I don't see how a naturalistic theory is likely to do much better with respect to complaints about level of application and lack of guidelines. Of course, we could empirically investigate how people do, in fact, make moral judgments and what guidelines, if any, they employ. A moral theorist, however, is likely to respond with a “so what?” What does information about how people in fact navigate through their social environments have to tell us about how they ought to so navigate?

In the last chapter, Casebeer addresses some potential criticisms that might be raised against his analysis. He concludes that, despite all the conceptual maneuvering, the naturalistic fallacy is still to be reckoned with. Reservations about the concept of “human nature” are brushed aside.

A final brief section outlines some areas for further research. First, he argues, there is a need to produce a neurobiologically sensitive model of moral cognition. Second, we need to pursue “moral anthropology,” that is, to gather up the social facts that will need to be integrated with and serve of testing grounds for the models. Third, we need to pursue the neurobiology of moral cognition. Finally, we need to develop other naturalistic accounts and see how they interact with the functional account given here. These are all very interesting projects and definitely worth pursuing but whether they will result in a deeper understanding of the nature of moral normativity remains to be seen.

When all is said and done, I was not convinced that this proposed program shows how questions about morality can be resolved by appeals to evolutionary biology and cognitive science. I also have grave reservations about the argument. Nevertheless, Casebeer's analysis does raise a number of interesting questions about the mechanics of moral behavior that might fruitfully be addressed by undertaking the empirical and theoretical investigations that the author urges. It remains to be seen whether we come to see these results as having a central impact on our understanding of moral phenomena and the norms that underlie it.

References

Godfrey-Smith, Peter (1996), Complexity and the Function of Mind in Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, Ruth Garrett (1984), Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar