Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-lrblm Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-11T09:06:54.913Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The selfish goal: Self-deception occurs naturally from autonomous goal operation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 February 2011

Julie Y. Huang
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, Yale University, New Haven, CT 06520. julie.huang@yale.edu, john.bargh@yale.eduwww.yale.edu/acmelab
John A. Bargh
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, Yale University, New Haven, CT 06520. julie.huang@yale.edu, john.bargh@yale.eduwww.yale.edu/acmelab

Abstract

Self-deception may be a natural consequence of active goal operation instead of an adaptation for negotiating the social world. We argue that because autonomous goal programs likely drove human judgment and behavior prior to evolution of a central executive or “self,” these goal programs can operate independently to attain their desired end states and thereby produce outcomes that “deceive” the individual.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2011

We agree with von Hippel & Trivers (VH&T) that motivation plays a key role in self-deception. There are reasons to believe, however, that self-deception is part and parcel of normal goal operation, instead of constituting a specific adaptation for negotiating the social world. To support this argument, we discuss the selfish goal model of behavior (Bargh & Huang Reference Bargh, Huang, Moskowitz and Grant2009), which holds that human judgment and behavior were driven (unconsciously) by goal pursuit programs prior to the evolution of a central executive self. Next, we review research suggesting that all goals – even conscious ones – maintain this ability to operate autonomously and thus are capable of producing effects that appear, on the surface, to “deceive” the individual self.

Evolutionary theorists have argued that consciousness and strategic, intentional mental processes were relatively late arrivals in human evolutionary history (e.g., Corballis Reference Corballis, Zelazo, Moscovitch and Thompson2007; Donald Reference Donald1991). If so, then another, unconscious, system must have directed hominid behavior in adaptive ways prior to the evolution of consciousness.

Indeed, evolutionary biologists and psychologists view motivations as the crucial link between genetic influences and adaptive behavior (Dawkins Reference Dawkins1976; Tooby & Cosmides Reference Tooby, Cosmides, Barkow, Cosmides and Tooby1992). Because of constantly changing and shifting environmental conditions, coupled with the very slow rate of genetic change, direct genetic controls over behavior tend to be inflexible and unable to adapt quickly enough to changes in the environment. Genes program the individual with generally adaptive motivations, which are translated as “goal programs” within the nervous system (Mayr Reference Mayr1976).

These goals had to guide the individual toward evolutionarily adaptive outcomes in the local environment without the guidance of an executive self – in other words, they must have been capable of autonomous operation. When conscious goal-pursuit processes then came on-line, they likely took advantage (made use) of the already-existing autonomous goal structures (Bargh & Morsella Reference Bargh and Morsella2008). As a consequence, conscious goals retain some features of nonconscious goal pursuits, including the capability to operate independently from the “self” or central executive. Thus, we argue, any goal pursuit, conscious or unconscious, operates autonomously to an extent and can thus produce effects that can be considered “deceptive” from the perspective of the self.

How do goals operate independently from individual guidance while still prodding that individual to achieve the goal's end state? Research suggests that both conscious and nonconscious goals, once active, exert temporary downstream effects upon the individual's information processing and behaviors in ways that facilitate successful pursuit of that goal. An active goal's systematic influence can be considered “selfish” because it is geared toward attaining its desired end state, regardless of whether the consequences of goal pursuit (e.g., temporary valuation of stimuli) are consistent with the values of the stable self-concept. For instance, participants perceive goal-facilitating stimuli as bigger (Veltkamp et al. Reference Veltkamp, Aarts and Custers2008), closer (Balcetis & Dunning Reference Balcetis and Dunning2010), and more likable (Ferguson Reference Ferguson2008) when that goal is active than when it is not. These influences can be considered deceptive because as perceptions of reality, they are shifted in inconsistent, sometimes inaccurate ways.

Because they also operate autonomously (once intentionally activated), even consciously pursued goals can produce effects which deceive the individual. Bargh, Green, and Fitzsimons (Reference Bargh, Green and Fitzsimons2008) tested the hypothesis that all goal pursuits, conscious and unconscious alike, operate autonomously and so can produce consequences unwanted at the level of the self. In their experiments, participants watched a videotape of two people in an office with the explicit, conscious goal of evaluating one of the people for a job. Some participants were told the job in question was a restaurant waiter; others were told it was a newspaper crime reporter position. During the interview, the two conversation partners were interrupted by a person who behaved in either a rude and aggressive or a polite and deferential manner.

Note that the desired personality characteristics of a waiter and a crime reporter are mirror opposites: The ideal crime reporter is tough and aggressive, whereas the ideal waiter is polite and deferential. After viewing the video, participants were asked how much they liked not the job candidate (on whom they had been consciously focused), but this interrupter. Unsurprisingly, participants in the control and the waiter-job conditions liked the polite interrupter more than the rude interrupter. However, participants in the reporter-goal condition (for whom rudeness and aggressiveness are desired traits) liked the rude interrupter more than the polite interrupter. Because the interrupter's traits matched the desired qualities of the currently active goal, he was evaluated positively by people prepared to evaluate a crime reporter – though as the control condition indicates, he would not have been liked at all in the absence of this active goal. Thus, even consciously pursued goals can lead to self-deception by producing effects contrary to the individual's (i.e., self's) preferences.

Moreover, both conscious and unconscious goal pursuits can turn off, independently from self-direction or awareness, thus producing potentially self-deceptive effects. When a goal is completed it temporarily deactivates, inhibiting the mental representations involved in the pursuit of that goal (Förster et al. Reference Förster, Liberman and Higgins2005). The goal's downstream influence on the person's cognition and behavior evaporates, now allowing the production of behavior that is inconsistent with previous actions. For example, participants given the opportunity to disagree with blatantly sexist remarks were ironically more likely afterward to recommend a man for a stereotypically male job than if they had not had the counterarguing opportunity (Monin & Miller Reference Monin and Miller2001). Similarly, when supporters of then-candidate Barack Obama were given a chance to express that support, afterwards they were counterintuitively more likely to rate a job opening as more suitable for Whites than for Blacks (Effron et al. Reference Effron, Cameron and Monin2009). In these studies, successfully asserting egalitarian values temporarily completed participants' self-valued goals to appear egalitarian; this goal completion caused the production of behaviors counter to the participants' self-professed values – in other words, it produced self-deception at the behavioral level.

Instead of evolving to facilitate the deception of others, self-deception may be a natural consequence of the autonomous goal operation that characterized our pre-conscious past. Goal structures predated the evolution of a central self and so must have operated autonomously to guide the individual toward their specific desired end states. Research suggests they continue to do so today.

References

Balcetis, E. & Dunning, D. (2010) Wishful seeing: Desired objects are seen as closer. Psychological Science 21:147–52.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bargh, J. A., Green, M. & Fitzsimons, G. (2008) The selfish goal: Unintended consequences of intended goal pursuits. Social Cognition 26:520–40.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bargh, J. A. & Huang, J. Y. (2009) The selfish goal. In: The psychology of goals, ed. Moskowitz, G. B. & Grant, H., pp. 127–50. Guilford Press.Google Scholar
Bargh, J. A. & Morsella, E. (2008) The unconscious mind. Perspectives on Psychological Science 3:7379.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Corballis, M. C. (2007) The evolution of consciousness. In: The Cambridge handbook of consciousness, ed. Zelazo, P. D., Moscovitch, M. & Thompson, E., pp. 571–95. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dawkins, R. (1976) The selfish gene. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Donald, M. (1991) Origins of the modern mind. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Effron, D., Cameron, J. S. & Monin, B. (2009) Endorsing Obama licenses favoring Whites. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 45:590–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ferguson, M. J. (2008) On becoming ready to pursue a goal you don't know you have: Effects of nonconscious goals on evaluative readiness. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 95:1268–94.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Förster, J., Liberman, N. & Higgins, E. T. (2005) Accessibility from active and fulfilled goals. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 41(3):220–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayr, E. (1976) Evolution and the diversity of life. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Monin, B. & Miller, D. T. (2001) Moral credentials and the expression of prejudice. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 81:3343.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tooby, J. & Cosmides, L. (1992) The psychological foundations of culture. In: The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture, ed. Barkow, J. H., Cosmides, L. & Tooby, J., pp. 19136. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Veltkamp, M., Aarts, H. & Custers, R. (2008) Perception in the service of goal pursuit: Motivation to attain goals enhances the perceived size of goal-instrumental objects. Social Cognition 26:720–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar