1 Introduction
The relatively recent prominence of socioeconomic rights discourse in constitutional law has given rise to two distinct types of scholarship. The first discusses their moral, legal and political justifications (e.g. Fabre, Reference Fabre2000), whereas the second attends to the practical implications entailed in enshrining such rights in a constitution (e.g. Barak-Erez and Gross, Reference Barak-erez and Gross2007). In his new book Weak Courts, Strong Rights: Judicial Review and Social Welfare Rights in Comparative Constitutional Law, Professor Mark Tushnet takes on this latter aspect. Given that socioeconomic rights have come to be recognised in some form in various constitutions, he asks: How should courts exercising judicial review attempt to enforce them?
Readers familiar with Tushnet’s work in constitutional theory, articulated most poignantly in Taking the Constitution Away from The Courts (Tushnet, Reference Tushnet1999), will likely be surprised at his present embrace of judicial review. Indeed, Weak Courts, Strong Rights resumes the theme of Taking the Constitution Away in that authority over constitutional interpretation should be ‘taken away’ from courts, and, for the most part, given to the legislature and the people.Footnote 2 And yet, here Tushnet argues that judicial review can help make socioeconomic rights more robust, a seeming departure from his earlier work (e.g. Tushnet, Reference Tushnet2006a).
This review will proceed in three parts. The first part will offer a fairly close reading of the main arguments developed in the book. In particular, I will focus on Tushnet’s argument that weak form judicial review, meaning a system wherein the judiciary does not have the last word over constitutional interpretation, has a tendency to degenerate into a strong form system. This discussion will be connected to Tushnet’s argument that socioeconomic rights occupy the same theoretical space as civil and political rights, and are, in a sense, two sides of the same coin. Despite their theoretical similarity, however, socioeconomic rights present unique challenges for their enforcement, and Tushnet suggests a framework of weak form judicial review to address these challenges while still striving to maintain democratic legitimacy.
The second part of the review will address and attempt to resolve the problems entailed in Tushnet’s solution. Specifically, I will argue that judicial enforcement of socioeconomic rights requires a hospitable environment for them to flourish. This means meeting two preconditions: first, a strong civil society; and second, a pre-existing institutional willingness to apply socioeconomic rights. I elaborate on each in turn and argue that failing to meet these preconditions makes the prospect of successful judicial enforcement of socioeconomic rights unlikely, or at least speculative.
The third and last part of the review attempts to answer the question posed earlier: How should readers consider Tushnet’s constitutional theory as a whole, as it has been articulated over the past decade? Here I try to square Weak Courts, Strong Rights with Tushnet’s previous writings, in particular his Taking the Constitution Away From the Courts, a book which takes a strong stance against judicial review.
I argue that despite the seeming tension, the two can be reconciled if we think of Taking the Constitution Away as a political manifesto and Weak Courts, Strong Rights as a pragmatic prescription. In other words, Taking the Constitution Away is a study in ideal theory, whereas Weak Courts, Strong Rights occupies the realm of non-ideal theory. If we were to design a constitution from scratch, argues Tushnet, we should not provide for judicial review. However, given that we already live in a system with judicial review, the question is how to design the adjudicative process so that it will meet objections from democratic self governmentFootnote 3 and be an effective tool in promoting rights, specifically socioeconomic rights.Footnote 4
2 Summary of the book
2.1 On doing comparative constitutional law
Tushnet begins Weak Courts, Strong Rights by making an argument for the usefulness of comparative constitutional law. This serves as a helpful reminder that the current controversy in the US over the use of comparative law in constitutional interpretation has taken on exaggerated and politicised overtones.Footnote 5 Tushnet points out, and rightfully so, that looking at foreign constitutional law, aside from the pure intellectual interest, may be helpful when we encounter a new problem where there is no settled precedent. To be sure, the comparativist must exercise caution when situating the foreign element within the specific institutional framework where it originated, and the foreign approach still needs to be compatible with domestic requirements.
With this presupposition in mind, what should we make of judicial review? On the one hand, judicial review as it is practised today seems to be a settled and permanent feature of US constitutional law. And yet, this was not always the case. Throughout American history there have been, and still are, disagreements as to the validity and kind of judicial review the US should have.Footnote 6 Thus, it is not implausible to suggest, as Tushnet does, that in terms of institutional design the question of which form judicial review should take is still an open question (Weak Courts, Strong Rights, p. 17). And here comparative constitutional law may be useful.
2.2 Strong form and weak form judicial review in constitutional law
The basic premise underlying Tushnet’s argument is that courts and legislatures can have reasonable disagreements about the meaning of a constitutional provision (Weak Courts, Strong Rights, p. 21; Waldron, Reference Waldron2006, pp. 1366–1369). In these situations both interpretations will fall into a zone of reasonableness. From this it follows that there is no a priori or intrinsic reason to favour a judicial decision over a legislative one (Weak Courts, Strong Rights, p. 79).Footnote 7 However, the current form of judicial review in the US – termed strong form review – explicitly favours the finality of a judicial decision over a legislative one. Yes, constitutional decisions may be overruled by a constitutional amendment, but Article V makes that almost impossible. Thus the reality is that the Court is the final expositor of constitutional meaning.Footnote 8
The problem of strong form review, Tushnet argues, lies precisely with the difficulty of overruling it (Weak Courts, Strong Rights, p. 22). In a strong form system, after a judicial decision has been made the people have no recourse, even if the Court happens to interpret the Constitution reasonably but in a way contrary to the also reasonable interpretation offered by the political branches. The broader question, then, is how can judicial review be reconciled with democratic self-government?Footnote 9 The answer proposed by Tushnet is weak form judicial review, which attempts to answer the problem of judicial finality by allowing the legislature to respond in real time to judicial pronouncements. The hope is that this will promote a dialogue between the branches, thus mitigating democratic objections.Footnote 10 The judiciary will still have its say, but the final word will rest with the legislature.
Weak form judicial review can take on various forms. It can be a mandate that the court interpret any enactment so that it complies with enumerated individual rights – an interpretation the legislature can reject by a subsequent enactment.Footnote 11 It can consist of incompatibility declarations – a process by which the court declares an enactment to be incompatible with constitutional commitments. There, like in the UK, the legislature can choose not to amend the enactment, but it can also work toward complying with its constitutional commitments articulated by the court (Weak Courts, Strong Rights, pp. 27–31). It can be a regime where a court’s decision is binding, unless the legislature actively overrules it.Footnote 12 Finally, weak form review can take the form of weak remedies. These are remedies that relegate the court to a monitoring role, while leaving the particulars to other branches.
2.3 The difficulty of sustaining weak form review
Much has been written in the past few years about weak form review.Footnote 13 The initial hope that weak form mechanisms will deliver real-time inter-branch dialogue has turned into scepticism that such dialogue can exist, let alone be ascertained.Footnote 14 Less sceptical commentators argue that, at best, such dialogue happens only infrequently (e.g. Manfredi and Kelly, Reference Manfredi and Kelly1999; Klug and Starmer, Reference Klug and Starmer2005; Huscroft, Reference Huscroft2007). The main concern here is that weak form review is unstable, turning into strong form review, thus bringing back the same democratic tensions familiar from the US context. On this view, weak form review does not seem promising.
Tushnet’s response suggests a different interpretation. He argues that what happened, most notably in Canada, is that the move toward strong form review reflected the considered judgment of the polity which came to favour judicial supremacy (Weak Courts Strong Rights, p. 44). Thus, if the shift to strong form occurs ‘organically’, it gives rise to fewer democratic objections.Footnote 15 Equating weak form review with democratic experimentalism (Weak Courts, Strong Rights, p. 66, fn55),Footnote 16 the repeated interactions between courts and legislatures are viewed as experiments in constitutional law. When experiments end, i.e. when the branches have reached a stable solution they find acceptable, so does weak form review. Thus, we can have strong form areas in a general system of weak form review and weak form areas, i.e. areas where the law isn’t sufficiently established, in a general system of strong form review. Therefore, one should view the transformation from weak form to strong form as the reflection of a people on their constitutional commitments.
But an important question, I think, remains. Even if democratic objections are mitigated when the people decide to transfer their rights to the judiciary, what if the people change their minds? It seems then that even if an ‘experiment has ended’, we would need a mechanism which will allow for its re-examination. In other words, strong form review should never be too strong so as to preclude us from revising an existing legal arrangement.
2.4 The sameness of socioeconomic rights
Systems of weak form review purport to designate a larger role for legislatures in constitutional interpretation because the institutional mechanisms permit input after a judicial decision.Footnote 17 However, it is clear that the original motivation behind weak form review was not to enhance the status of socioeconomic rights. In order to make that connection, Tushnet needs to pre-empt another argument, that courts should not enforce such rights in the first place. Enter the state action doctrine (Weak Courts, Strong Rights, pp. 161–195). The state action doctrine, which requires that in order for there to be a justiciable action the claim must be brought against a government action, is one of the core doctrines of US constitutional law, and one of the more complex ones.
The purpose of the state action doctrine is to track the public/private act/omission distinctions, making only public acts actionable while removing private acts from the scope of constitutional law. If the government acts, there is state action. Failure to act will usually not be considered an ‘action’ warranting judicial review.Footnote 18 While this classification is commonplace in liberal, and especially libertarian, circles, Tushnet argues the doctrine ‘does no independent work’ (Weak Courts, Strong Rights, p. 167).Footnote 19 A private act is private because a political authority decides what is private and what is public; a decision not to regulate is just like a decision to regulate, in the sense that they are both decisions. Nothing, then, is naturally private or public, because these categories are derived from a particular and pre-existing political philosophy.Footnote 20
This last point has political and legal implications. Tushnet argues that the doctrine leaves in place the background rules of contracts, torts and property, choosing to make actionable only the decisions emanating from these background rules. In that sense, the state action doctrine is artificial, because both the background rules and the specific rules are the result of governmental choice. Think, for example, of our property law. There is nothing necessary about designing our property regime so as to allow a person complete control over his property to the detriment of others. But once that rule is in place we cease to question it. We accept it as natural, choosing only to adjudicate specific disputes that arise out of our antecedent commitment to that rule. The state action doctrine attempts to demarcate first order actions from second order choices regarding institutional design; but, again, these are all choices the state makes.
State action, then, is everywhere. It is in the details of specific state activities and it is in the second order choices about how legal regimes will look. The upshot, and problem, is that once we do away with the doctrine, everything is potentially the subject of litigation; particularly the background rules responsible for wealth distribution (Weak Courts, Strong Rights, p. 168).Footnote 21
Tushnet’s argument is that the background rules – the ones the courts are reluctant to interfere with – are, in fact, socioeconomic rights. When courts employ the state action doctrine they are saying that they will not enforce (or rather refuse to acknowledge) socioeconomic rights (the rights dealing with allocation of resources). The doctrine thus serves to maintain a hard distinction between first and second generation rights. Now, while this may make sense in a jurisdiction that embraces the public/private distinction, there is nothing necessary about adopting this particular conception of constitutional law. Moreover, if this line of thought lies with state action, and if state action is unworkable, then so is the distinction between socioeconomic rights and civil and political rights which presupposes government action.Footnote 22
2.5 Connecting weak form review with socioeconomic rights
The state action doctrine has proven to be less problematic in other jurisdictions, most notably Canada, Germany and South Africa. Equipped with a social democratic concern for welfare rights, these post World War II constitutions and judiciaries have managed to escape the problem of applying judicial review to socioeconomic rights. They did it either by specifically providing for socioeconomic rights in their constitution (South Africa), by interpreting non-constitutional norms with an eye to constitutional values (Germany), by changing the common law to cohere with constitutional values (Canada) and/or by holding the state accountable when it fails to regulate an area which has constitutional implications (Canada). For example, if Canada decides to regulate housing, it must provide for all aspects of that right, and a failure to provide a certain aspect which is deemed to be within the scope of that right can be tantamount to a constitutional violation (Weak Court, Strong Rights, p. 205). Potentially this means that the constitution will have horizontal implications. It will apply not only in conflicts between state and citizen, but also in private conflicts between two citizens or non-state actors.Footnote 23
The immediate problem is one of scope. Questions of resource allocation, economic policy and social welfare are complex. Even if judicial review is theoretically permissible, there are still issues of judicial competence and democratic legitimacy to address. Unlike free speech cases, for example, there is the concern that courts will not be able to enforce their decisions having to do with socioeconomic rights (e.g. Christiansen, Reference Christiansen2007). After all, ordering the state to permit a demonstration is not like ordering an overhaul in the health-care system. Weak form review is supposed to address that problem, not by decreeing the ultimate decision, but by partnering with the other branches and facilitating gradual changes without assuming a coercive role.
It should be clear by now that the emphasis of weak form review is on the remedies it provides. Indeed, weak form review calls into question the assumption that judicial review requires coercive orders (Weak Courts, Strong Rights, p. 228). In closing his book, Tushnet illustrates the kind of weak remedies he is referring to. First, courts can issue declaratory judgments regarding violations of socioeconomic rights. The hope there is that the political branches will then seek to remedy the declared violation, but without the courts having to specify exactly (or at all) what the solution should look like. In these cases, the rights are, in a sense, non-justiciable,Footnote 24 but there is an implicit expectation that non-binding decisions will be bolstered by an active civil society that will apply pressure on the political branches to fix the problem the court indicated.
Second, courts can impose real duties while still leaving the government broad discretion. The South African Grootboom case,Footnote 25 which Tushnet discusses (Weak Courts, Strong Rights, pp. 242–244), is a good example of weak remedies. There, petitioners, essentially homeless people who were evicted from private land, relied on South Africa’s constitutional guarantee to a right to housing and sued, arguing that the government’s plans for affordable housing did not address their plight. The Constitutional Court ordered the government to devise a new housing plan in which it must take into account people in the situation of the petitioners. Although the Court issued a decree, the government still had wide latitude in devising the particular plan.
Similar examples are familiar from the US. Think of the Supreme Court’s use of the ‘all deliberate speed’ formula in Brown II,Footnote 26 or the school adequacy litigation in state courts.Footnote 27 In the latter, some courts have been successful in defining broad standards of an adequate education, allowing the state to design its own educational system and retreating to a supervisory role meant to enforce the ongoing reform process (Schrag, Reference Schrag2003).
Tushnet’s ultimate point is this: weak remedies produce increased political and civic participation in the formation of the rights themselves. Moreover, weak form review is a legitimate and effective method for courts to work together with other branches without overstepping their boundaries. Moving in such a way may work out to provide a stronger version of the socioeconomic right, even though it did not come about through strong form judicial review.
3 Critique
Tushnet’s argument is rich and complex, fusing together insights gleaned from disparate constitutional practices. In this review, I would like to focus mostly on his conclusion, that weak form review will enable a more robust version of socioeconomic rights. Parts 3.1 and 3.2 underscore two important preconditions – a strong civil society and a pre-existing institutional willingness to apply socioeconomic rights – which, I believe, are imperative for Tushnet’s project to succeed. Part 3.3 squares Weak Courts, Strong Rights with some of Tushnet’s previous writings on judicial review. Part 4 concludes.
3.1 The need for a strong civil society
At the outset, I believe it is important not to overstate Tushnet’s overarching argument. Tushnet himself seems to recognise that a lot depends on his argument working out.Footnote 28 Most importantly, it seems to me that it is regime dependent and context specific to a point which may make generalisations difficult. Here is what may seem a trivial point, but should not, I think, be underestimated: For socioeconomic rights to be ‘strong’ in the Tushnetian sense, we need a polity that already possesses an interest in making these rights real, for two reasons. First, there needs to be an active civil society that can complement the work of the courts and which will make sure weak remedies turn into real results. Second, for courts to issue even weak remedies, there must be some institutional willingness on their behalf to do so, as opposed to simply rejecting claims relying on these rights.
Regarding the need for a strong civil society, consider, for example, a situation where a court finds that a privately financed health-care system violates a constitutional right to health because coverage is denied to those who cannot afford to pay.Footnote 29 Rather than devise a complete scheme of health-care coverage for the poor, the court tells the legislature that the problem of poor people without coverage needs to be addressed and gives it a year to come up with a plan that will meet the constitutional standard. So far this is in line with weak form review. Now, without an effective civil society – individuals, politicians, organisations, media – that will continue to push for such a plan, the chances that such a plan will in fact materialise are not clear.Footnote 30 This is so because there is no real sanction (other than perhaps public embarrassment) that attaches to the judicial remedy. This enables the legislature to ‘get away with it’. To be sure, the problem of ‘no sanction’ is not confined to weak form review, but its potential does seem to increase there.
It would seem, then, that Tushnet’s argument is circular. If weak form judicial review stands to be most effective in countries with a strong civil society, why do we need any kind of judicial review in the first place? Presumably, part of the role of weak form review is to remove political blockage or to instigate some kind of governmental action. But if that is the case, then wouldn’t a strong civil society have already accomplished that? And if not, how can we expect weak form review to live up to its expectations when there is not a strong civil society to reinforce the courts’ judgments?
A possible response could take the following approach: yes, we need a strong civil society which can mobilise politically, but that is often easier said than done. The hope, then, is that weak form review will be able to contribute to the formation of an engaged citizenry by letting it know that the courts cannot accomplish everything on their own. Here we may think of some sort of trade-off. Courts will stay out of particular areas, especially when it comes to ‘policy’, leaving more room for the political branches and the people to act. The trade-off is that in the short run things might not get done as quickly as they might have had courts been stronger. Moreover, to the extent that socioeconomic rights are indeed rights, we are legitimising a time period (short as it may be) in which these rights are not granted a proper defence once a court has found the government to be in violation of the constitution. In the long run, however, weak form review has an educative value, in that it results in better self-government and a more democratic polity.Footnote 31
This reading also answers the critique that political actors may at times be comfortable with judicial review because it allows for blame shifting.Footnote 32 If the difficult and controversial decisions are made by life-tenured judges, the legislator will be relatively immune from public criticism and will be better able to retain her seat. Weak form review undermines the blame shifting argument, because it forces legislators to make the decisions for which they are democratically accountable. Paradoxically, then, weak form review may contribute more to maintaining the separation of powers scheme than strong form review, even though the latter provides a clearer demarcation between the branches.
At this point it is important to keep in mind that much in the preceding paragraphs is speculative. Weak form review is a relatively young experiment, and whether it can bring about the changes Tushnet hopes for has yet to be determined decisively. It does seem clear, though, that weak form review needs a hospitable environment in which it can flourish. This does not just mean an engaged citizenry, but also institutional willingness from courts, agencies and legislatures, to co-operate on these issues in a thoughtful and beneficial manner. I turn now to this issue.
3.2 The need for institutional willingness
As I argued above, for socioeconomic rights to be strong we need some form of institutional willingness to implement these rights. When Tushnet is writing for an American audience – which is why, I believe, he discusses the state action doctrine in such detail – he is arguing that the traditional American aversion to social welfare rights is unfounded because it relies on an untenable conceptual distinction (public/private, act/omission). However, if that was all there was to it then we would expect that doctrine to dissipate. And yet it hasn’t, suggesting that the real impasse is cultural–philosophical rather than legal.Footnote 33 This impasse is a view of government as curtailing rights rather than expanding them. In a way, American political culture (and this is a generalisation, of course) is committed to the notion of negative rights much more than positive rights because it is believed that human flourishing is best achieved with minimal governmental interference. Embracing socioeconomic rights also means a commitment to an enlarged role for the government in the public sphere, something which Americans traditionally are wary of.Footnote 34 This, then, calls into question the plausibility for weak form review to be implemented wholesale in the US.
It is perhaps no accident, then, that the relatively few successes of weak form review in the US, such as educational adequacy suits, happen at the state level where constitutions are more malleable, less entrenched and constitute less of a non-negotiable identity. Moreover, almost all state constitutions contain explicit mentions of some socioeconomic rights, thus resolving the state action problem.Footnote 35 To this we can add that many state judges are elected and may have an incentive to designate a larger role for the political branches so as not to alienate politicians whose support will be needed come election time.
The factor of institutional willingness, which is not strictly a part of judicial review, can be as important as how judicial review will be operationalised. To put it differently, judicial review can shift the order of priorities, making particular issues more salient than others. But getting a particular issue resolved will require the operation of politics. Here, courts cannot but rely on the political branches (and by extension on civil society) for realising the judicial decision.
In his example for weak form review in the US, Tushnet discusses educational adequacy suits, where states were found to be violating the state constitutional requirement to provide an adequate education. There have been several lawsuits stemming from such provisions, some successful and some not.Footnote 36 A comprehensive study conducted by William Koski suggests that legal norms in and of themselves are insufficient to bring about educational reform. Koski points to ‘judicial attitudes’ that made reform in some states possible, and to the inter-institutional conflict – with governors and legislatures – which sometimes made co-operation difficult (Koski, Reference Koski2003; Reference Koski2004, pp. 1228–1230). In particular, certain courts – based on their pre-existing political leanings – viewed judicial intervention more favourably than others. In other words, they possessed the institutional willingness needed to carry out such reforms. Similarly, they needed the co-operation of legislatures and governors to make progress.
To be sure, every court needs the co-operation of other institutions to carry out its decisions (Cover, Reference Cover1986). When it comes to socioeconomic rights, however, courts will need even more co-operation from other co-equal branches because the nature of these matters is that they require further deliberations and resource allocations. This is, of course, the nature of weak form review, that it leaves much to be decided after a court has ruled. Therefore, as the potential for institutional conflict and constraint grows, the potential failure of such an enterprise grows as well.
The conclusion is that weak form review can accomplish the task that Tushnet designates for it only if there is a good faith effort from all concerned; weak form review necessitates political conditions hospitable for its implementation. A case in point is the Grootboom litigation. Grootboom – heralded by legal scholars as perhaps the best example of enforcement of socioeconomic rights – has caused quite a stir in comparative constitutional law circles.Footnote 37 But the situation in its aftermath has been rather grim. Although South African Constitutional Court Justice Albie Sachs begins his 2007 article with the words ‘Mrs Grootboom has had enough’ (Sachs, Reference Sachs2007), Mrs Grootboom still hasn’t received the government housing which was the subject of the litigation that ended in 2001 (Hweshe, Reference Hweshe2008). My point is not that the decision has been a complete failure – recently 277 housing units were allocated to the group of over 1,000 petitionersFootnote 38 – but that implementing socioeconomic rights requires sustained co-operation over a relatively long period of time from other branches; and that, in itself, necessitates institutional willingness and an active civil society that can push for the implementation of court decisions.
For those who express scepticism that such conditions could ever be met, a recent case from the South African Constitutional Court suggests that this is not impossible. In Occupiers of 51 Olivia Road Berea Township,Footnote 39 the City wanted to evict 400 people from their homes, citing unsafe and unhealthy building conditions. Petitioners sought relief, citing their constitutional right to housing.Footnote 40 Instead of definitively resolving the case, the Constitutional Court took a different path, opting for weak form review. It ordered the parties to engage in meaningful deliberations, something it believed had not been done prior to the eviction requests, ‘in order to alleviate the plight of the applicants . . . by making the buildings as safe and as conducive to health as is reasonably practicable’.Footnote 41 The Court held that if the City is aware that its decision to evict is going to make people homeless, and in so doing impact their constitutional right to housing, then it is, at the least, under a duty to engage meaningfully with the occupiers. The judicially sanctioned ‘meaningful engagement’ led to an agreement that the City would not evict the tenants, that it would renovate the buildings and that it would provide temporary accommodation. The parties also agreed to meet and discuss permanent housing solutions.
The lesson of Occupiers of 51 Olivia Road Berea Township is important. It demonstrates that weak form review has the potential to induce co-operation between government and the people and the capacity to remove political blockage – here in the area of housing rights – while letting the people fashion their own solutions, leaving the court in a monitoring role. Of course, identifying in advance the types of cases where weak form review will be successful is difficult, and perhaps impossible,Footnote 42 but the two preconditions I elaborated on – institutional willingness and a strong civil society – seem to be key.
3.3 Enhancing popular democracy – a constitutional project in Ideal and Non-ideal Theory
Readers of Tushnet’s previous work, especially Taking the Constitution Away from the Courts (Reference Tushnet1999), might be perplexed when reading Weak Courts, Strong Rights. As Frank Michelman noted in his review of the former, ‘the background preference is for democracy, the immediately implied default position is against judicial review (Michelman, Reference Michelman2000, p. 462). In his earlier book, Tushnet calls for a new constitutional amendment that will do away with judicial review and that will give the people, i.e. its representatives, the final word on constitutional interpretation.Footnote 43 And yet here, Tushnet is advocating judicial review, albeit weak, in order to arrive at more robust socioeconomic rights. Can the two be squared?
I think they can, and in two ways that are not mutually exclusive. The first is to think about Taking the Constitution Away as a political manifesto calling for reconceptualising the role of judicial review in American society. To borrow from John Rawls, Taking the Constitution Away is a study in Ideal Theory, whereas Weak Courts, Strong Rights is a project in Non-ideal Theory. The second is to think of ways by which judicial review develops democratically.
The distinction between Ideal and Non-ideal Theory was first offered by John Rawls in his A Theory of Justice (Reference Rawls1971/1999, esp. pp. 7–8, 215–216, 308–309). Roughly, Ideal Theory describes the set of principles that would be appropriate to a morally and politically ideal order. Non-ideal Theory recognises that our political order is, well, not ideal. Thus, Non-ideal Theory accounts for the set of principles that are appropriate in these less than perfect conditions (Phillips, Reference Phillips1985).Footnote 44
Now, if we were to design a legal system from scratch, with an eye toward enhancing popular democracy, majoritarianism and civic participation, Taking the Constitution Away would counsel us against incorporating judicial review in our constitutional structure.Footnote 45 In that sense, Taking the Constitution Away is an aspirational text. It is a prescription for institutional designers considering, perhaps for the first time, the role constitutional courts play in society. Weak Courts, Strong Rights, however, is a study in Non-ideal Theory because, despite the recent popular constitutionalist trend invoked by some scholars, US constitutional history and culture have made it practically impossible to do away with judicial review.Footnote 46 For better or worse, strong judicial review has come to be a defining feature of US constitutional law.Footnote 47
Consequently, we need to figure out what to do with the institution of judicial review, or how best to conceptualise it so that it will fit our current goals (one of them being an original preference against judicial review).Footnote 48 This is precisely what Weak Courts, Strong Rights sets out to do with regards to socioeconomic rights.Footnote 49 Indeed, this book has a pragmatic ring to it: if we already inhabit a world with judicial review, here’s how we can harness it to our benefit.Footnote 50 The way to do this is through weak form review, because on the one hand it preserves judicial review, and on the other it ‘tweaks’ it so as to increase the range of democratic possibilities, encourage deliberation and preserve the ultimate authority over constitutional interpretation with the people – a necessary element of self-government.
The second way one can square Tushnet’s previous work with this book is by telling a story about how judicial review can develop democratically. Roughly, if the people opt for judicial review then the degree to which it is a counter-majoritarian practice is lessened. But unlike other countries that specifically provide for judicial review, the US Constitution does not. Still, weak form review allows for experimentation with constitutional rights. It enables a back and forth between legislatures, agencies and the courts until the specific issue has been sufficiently crystallised.Footnote 51 This is the dialogic conception of judicial review. Now, if weak form judicial review generates real-time constitutional dialogue, then one could argue that it does not raise the same democratic objections because it is the result of deliberations between all branches rather than one branch assuming the role of a final arbiter.Footnote 52
4 Conclusion
Weak Courts, Strong Rights takes an instrumentalist approach to judicial review by arguing that the best way to enforce socioeconomic rights may be through weak remedies. It is therefore important to note what the book is not saying. Tushnet is not making the argument that people have a right to judicial review,Footnote 53 or that judicial review is an intrinsic aspect of a democratic regime,Footnote 54 or even that people should have constitutional socioeconomic rights (Fabre, Reference Fabre2000). Rather, the overarching argument is that if we already have a judicial system with judicial review, and it so happens we are considering enforcing socioeconomic rights, then weak form review may be a possible way to do it more or less successfully while preserving other important democratic values.
For those among us who look to the courts for large-scale societal reform, the message in this book may be disappointing. Tushnet acknowledges that legislatures are imperfect, but then so are courts. More often than not, the two branches will have reasonable disagreements. In bringing about societal reform, however, courts can only play a minor, though important, role. The message in this book is that while courts can have a meaningful and legitimate role in a democratic society, they cannot go at it alone. For the project to succeed we need to immerse ourselves in politics and not just law. Professor Tushnet’s thesis will therefore become a reality only when the political branches and the public at large will join the experiment he has outlined.