1. Preamble
Pain scientists and clinicians often say that pain is a subjective experience. This is epitomized in the widespread acceptance and use of the definition of “pain” adopted by the International Association for the Study of Pain (IASP):Footnote 1
An unpleasant sensory and emotional experience associated with actual or potential tissue damage, or described in terms of such damage.
(IASP Taxonomy 1979/2011)The Note to the definition adds that “Pain is always subjective,” and goes on to state that:
…This definition avoids tying pain to the stimulus. Activity induced in the nociceptor and nociceptive pathways by a noxious stimulus is not pain, which is always a psychological state, even though we may well appreciate that pain most often has a proximate physical cause.
(1979/2011)Even those who take issue with the IASP definition typically do not question the claim that pains are subjective experiences.
Given that toes, buttocks, guts, and other bodily parts and organs aren’t regions of the body that can have experiences in them, the subjective experience conception of pain creates a tension with people’s routine and otherwise unremarkable practice of attributing pains to bodily parts like, “I have a pain in my toe,” “my back hurts,” “I have a toothache,” etc. One might wonder whether the scientists and clinicians may be advising against the practice of locating pains in body parts. But, of course, they themselves routinely engage in this practice. Are they aware of the tension? They seem not. The very same Note contains the following sentence: “[pain] is unquestionably a sensation in a part or parts of the body, but it is also always unpleasant and therefore also an emotional experience” (1979/2011).
The IASP definition and the remark in the accompanying Note seem to rule out identifying pain with any objective condition of the body part to which a pain is attributed, such as any actual or potential tissue damage, injury, or any kind of physical disturbance. The implication seems to be that although a pain is typically associated with such a condition, it’s not to be identified with such. Can the pain scientists or clinicians be serious in affirming the implication that when one sincerely claims to have a pain, say, in one’s toe, one is attributing a subjective experience (something like an emotion) to one’s toe? Can they be serious in thinking that people can have subjective experiences in body parts like toes, guts, buttocks, etc.? This seems very unlikely.Footnote 2 Subjective experiences like pains are said to be realized in the brain (or the central nervous system). Indeed, many pain scientists think of pain experiences as being in the brain. Clearly, toes, guts, buttocks and the like don’t have the complex functional organization sufficiently similar to the brain (any brain) to support subjective experiences.
So, we seem to have a puzzle. This puzzle isn’t confined only to the conception of pain that scientists and clinicians have; it seems widespread in the larger population reflecting the puzzle embedded in the folk conception of pain.Footnote 3 To explicitly state: the puzzle stems from the fact that we seem to conceive of pains as both subjective experiences and as locatable conditions of the very objective bodily parts and organs. The folk may be excused for being sloppy, inattentive, and sometimes even confused. This wouldn’t be very surprising. The folk aren’t doing any kind of research relying on this conception after all—they are most often just trying to get by in their hectic daily lives.
But the puzzle becomes more puzzling when it’s realized that pain scientists and clinicians worked long and hard to come up with the IASP definition and the accompanying Note.Footnote 4 Pain science is the science of pain so defined. Pain clinicians treat patients with pain so defined. How can the pain scientists and clinicians be confused? If there is a confusion, it seems to be of such an elementary and fundamental kind that one wonders how the scientists and clinicians can seem to be unaware of it. Indeed, if there is a confusion, it doesn’t seem to be even below the surface (to wit: “[pain] is unquestionably a sensation in a part or parts of the body, but it is also always unpleasant and therefore also an emotional experience” [ISAP 1979/2011]).Footnote 5 Also, if there is a confusion, wouldn’t one expect this to somehow show up somewhere—perhaps having a somewhat adverse impact on scientific research or clinical practice? But as far as anybody knows, there seems to be no trouble or difficulty in any aspects of scientific pain research or clinical practice that is traceable to this “confusion.”
So, we seem to have a puzzle of a very peculiar sort. Scientists, clinicians, and the folk alike seem to be utterly competent in attributing pains to body parts while talking of pains as subjective experiences without much hesitation in their discourse or in their practical dealings with each other or in their clinical and research settings. Everybody seems to implicitly know what the truth-conditions of pain attributing utterances are, so they routinely speak and evaluate the relevant language without any signs of confusion even though most seem to draw a blank when asked to articulate what these truth-conditions are.
This puzzling situation calls for an explanation. In particular, we need to understand how scientists and clinicians can be operating with two apparently conflicting conceptions of pain without any discomfort or sign of confusion, especially when the apparent conflict seems so manifest. My own view is that despite appearances, these two conceptions of pain, call them bodily versus experiential conceptions, are not actually in conflict and, consequently, there is no serious or deep confusion in the conception of pain had by scientists, clinicians, and the folk alike.
In what follows, I will go over various options about the truth-conditions of utterances of pain to body parts. With the exception of the second option below, we’ll see that all six of them—if they turn out to be adequate on other grounds—would bring the bodily and experiential conceptions into harmony with each other and remove the apparent conflict. However, I will argue that the first five options (including suboptions) are not adequate on various independent grounds. Some of them have straightforward naturalist credentials, some don’t. Some options are recommended on quite independent grounds (not on their own merits) as part of an otherwise interesting philosophical program (like representationalism), some are not. At the end, in section 3, I will offer my own adverbialist proposal—the sixth option—and provide a naturalistic framework in which it can be implemented. I will argue that this proposal is superior to all of its rivals. As we’ll see, it has also wider implications in the philosophy of perception.
2. Options
Consider John who has started to feel a pain in his toe after a long weekend run. John is a mature person with an intact healthy body. He sincerely makes the following utterance:
“I have a pain in my toe.”
In what follows, we will assume that John is speaking truthfully, and that such utterances locating pains in body parts and the judgments expressed by them (call these L-utterances and L-judgments respectively), when made sincerely, are often literally true. We would like to know both the logically necessary and sufficient conditions for such utterances and judgments to be true. We’ll attempt to answer this general question by working through the example of John’s utterance.
So, what are the truth-conditions of John’s utterance? We already ruled out this option above, and I won’t belabour the point further:
(1) John’s toe has a “painful” subjective experience in it.
Given the remarks in the Note added to the IASP definition, quoted earlier, we can rule out the following option too:
(2) John’s toe has some kind of physical injury (disorder, tissue damage) in it.
The appended Note warns us against tying the pain to physical noxious stimuli and explicitly disapproves of identifying pain with the activity of nociceptors or nociceptive activity in the afferent peripheral pathways. It would be particularly weird if it left open the option of identifying pain with the actual or impending tissue damage that is typically in between the noxious stimuli causing it and the nociceptor activity caused by it. Option (2) is neither necessary nor sufficient for John’s utterance to be true.
But perhaps what makes John’s utterance true is the fact that:Footnote 6
(3) John’s toe has some kind of tissue damage in it, and John feels it in a “painful” way.
This option does better: the truth of (3) seems sufficient for John’s utterance to be true. But (3) is clearly not necessary. Suppose that the pain in John’s toe is due to a slightly compressed and inflamed nerve in his lower back that started to act more aggressively after his long run. There is nothing physically wrong with his toe—no actual or potential tissue damage of any kind detectable by nociceptors. The pain John feels in his toe is now what pain scientists call a “referred pain.” Under such a scenario, John’s utterance remains true but (3) becomes false. Therefore, (3) cannot capture what makes John’s utterance true.
It is important to elaborate this point. Referred pains are no less genuine pains, and they are not mislocated pains either. John doesn’t feel the pain in his lower back; he feels the pain in his toe. It is his toe that has pain in it. When asked whether he has any pain in his lower back, John sincerely reports that he has none. John is not confused, nor is any physician who agrees with John. The physical disorder that is the cause of John’s pain is in his lower back. So, to this extent, it may be plausible to say that there is something misleading about John’s pain in the toe if we expect pains in body parts to signal physical disorders in those parts. But when we don’t speak loosely and are careful, we don’t stop believing that John has a pain in his toe upon learning where the cause of the trouble is if John continues to feel the pain in his toe. So (3) won’t do.Footnote 7
To say that John is having a referred pain in his toe is to say that John has a pain in his toe and the cause of his pain is somewhere other than in his toe. So, John still has a pain in his toe and we are trying to understand what makes this true. At this point, it seems clear that John’s pain in his toe has nothing to do with any physical or objective condition of his toe. Perhaps we can capture John’s utterance with the following:
(4) Whether or not John’s toe has any physical disturbance in it, John’s toe has a subjective “painful” quality in it, and John now senses or is aware of this quality.
With this option we seem to be in the realm of fantastical metaphysics. It is not quite clear what it means to say that John’s toe has a subjective quality in it. Nevertheless, from a phenomenological point of view, it’s also clear that it seems to John that there is a “painful” hurting quality instantiated in his toe, and that he is aware of it. What makes this quality subjective is the fact that it also seems to John that this quality is awareness-dependent. It would seem to disappear the moment he ceases to be aware of this quality (let’s say, despite his full attention). John might worry about the physical condition of his toe or back that has caused the pain in his toe in the absence of his feeling pain (let’s say, after taking strong analgesics), but it seems very unlikely that John would worry about the “current” pain in his toe if he is not feeling it at all. Option (4), then, is an attempt to respect the first-person phenomenology (how things seem to a person from the person’s experiential perspective) by turning it into a metaphysical account. On this view, there really are subjective qualities literally instantiated in body parts despite their having an awareness-dependent status. An analogy might help here. Consider using your flashlight in the dark to illuminate your environment. The circular bright spot falling on objects around you is dependent on whether you shine the light on them with your flashlight. The light spot really exists on objects when you illuminate them with your flashlight. The bright spot on objects is one thing, and your act of shining light on them with your flashlight is another. Similarly, John’s act of feeling the painful quality is one thing, and the quality instantiated in John’s toe is another—even though the quality’s instantiation in John’s toe metaphysically depends on his feeling it.Footnote 8
Unlike the spotlight, however, the subjective quality in Joe’s toe has further peculiarities. Not only is it subjective, but it also seems epistemically private in the following sense: there seems to be a radical asymmetry between the way John has epistemic access to it and the way others may have access to John’s pain in his toe. This radical difference in epistemic access sustains another radical difference in epistemic and practical/prudential authority John has over the pain in his toe over the kind of authority others might have about John’s pain.
Despite its near-perfect match with first-person phenomenology, what makes (4) difficult to accept is its apparently fantastical nature as a piece of metaphysics.Footnote 9 Subjectivity, privacy, being a source of privileged and perhaps incorrigible knowledge, all seem to be mysterious features associated with either sense-data or sensory experiences with qualia—not associated with body parts. Sense-data are thought to be metaphysically dubious entities, whereas qualia are thought to be metaphysically dubious qualities of sensory experiences for similar reasons. If there is a way of making (4) metaphysically acceptable for both naturalistically oriented philosophers and pain scientists, then (4) would seem to fit the bill well for what it is that makes John’s utterance true. Later on, I’ll have a proposal that might accommodate most of its attractiveness. But for the moment, we may want to look into another option that may be suggested by the fact that subjectivity, privacy, etc., all seem to be features associated with sensory and emotional experiences and their qualities.
Perhaps we can turn the experiential conception of pain into an account that will answer the bodily conception as well.
(5) Whether or not John’s toe has any physical disturbance in it, John has a subjective experience that attributes to his toe some sort of “painful” quality.
There are different ways of understanding this that we need to carefully sort out. The most natural interpretation is to take the experience to represent a “painful” quality as being in John’s toe. The attribution involved isn’t as if the experience is throwing a quality at the toe so that the toe can catch it—it is an intentional attribution. If so, the experience has accuracy conditions: it “says” of the toe that it has a certain quality in it. What it says is correct if and only if the toe has the quality attributed; it would be false or incorrect otherwise. We now have a similar worry about what this represented/attributed quality is.
Perceptualists and representationalists (PR theorists)Footnote 10 claim this quality to be an objective/physical condition of the toe, such as actual or potential tissue damage or injury (disorder, for short). On this view, what makes John’s utterance true is the fact that John undergoes a subjective experience that (nonconceptually or in an analog format) represents his toe as having a physical disorder of the appropriate kind in it. This experience is veridical if John’s toe has indeed such a disorder in it (and is relevantly caused by the disorder), nonveridical otherwise. So, if John’s pain in his toe is caused by a nerve compression in his lower back, then John’s subjective experience is inaccurate, nonveridical. But, according to PR theorists, this subjective experience is, because of its intentional/phenomenal content, still a genuine pain experience despite its inaccuracy. So, according to PR theorists, pains are primarily subjective experiences, just as the IASP definition says, but they claim that they can make sense of pain-locating judgments if the representational content of such experiences is taken into account. What makes John’s utterance true is the fact that:
(5i) Whether or not John’s toe has any physical disturbance in it, John has a subjective experience that represents his toe as having a physical disturbance in it.
Whether or not John knows it or can articulate it, when John sincerely reports a pain in his toe by uttering, “I have a pain in my toe,” he is in fact expressing this fact. Option (5i) articulates the truth-conditions of John’s utterance as well as his relevant belief thereby expressed. Another way to understand (5i) is to make a relational property out of the intentional content of the experience: John’s toe has a pain in it if and only if John’s toe is the intentional target of John’s experience attributing a disorder to it. Such properties are sometimes known in the philosophical community as inverse intentional properties and are subject to debate as to whether they are genuine properties because they are said to flout the Leibniz Law.Footnote 11 But we need not worry about this debate here. The point is that attributing an inverse intentional property to the toe seems to make sense of what it is that we are attributing to the toe while at the same time we can trace the subjectivity and privacy involved in this attribution to the subjectivity and privacy of the experience itself, thus apparently removing our initial puzzle.Footnote 12
This seems promising, but the view has quite unattractive consequences. One has already been mentioned and may be considered relatively minor: it makes a lot of genuine pain experiences literally mistaken; a lot of them turn out to be incorrect or seriously in error. We don’t normally talk about pain experiences as literally mistaken in the sense that they “say” something false. To be sure, we take them to be sometimes misleading given our natural expectation of finding something physically wrong in those body parts where we feel pain. But this is quite different than taking them to be literally mistaken. A PR theorist may find this to be a small price to pay compared to what the view seems to accomplish in bringing a unifying solution to the initial puzzle (the tension between the bodily and experiential conceptions of pain).
But (5i) in the hands of PR theorists generates another puzzle that cries out for explanation. Following the IASP definition, PR theorists consider pain to be primarily a subjective experience (realized in the central nervous system). Their proposal about how to make sense of pain attributions to body parts is to postulate that pain experiences are representational—they have an intentional content. This content is about what happens where in the body. Pain experiences are like other sensory experiences in telling us what is happening where so that we can form direct (noninferential) perceptual beliefs on their bases. The point of having sensory experiences is that we know how to epistemically and practically deal with our extramental (worldly, including bodily) environment. Our ordinary epistemic and practical focus in having sensory experiences as representational media is on what they represent to us accurately, not that they represent to us whatever the accuracy. So, if pains are primarily experiences that represent physical disorders in body parts, then one would expect the L-utterances and the beliefs expressed thereby to reflect this fact and therefore come to be true or false depending on whether or not the represented bodily parts have the represented disorder. But what we find instead is quite different, namely, (5i). Option (5i) is precisely what a PR theorist ought not to say as a response to our question about what makes John’s utterance (“I have a pain in my toe”) true.
A PR theorist might reply in the following way:
L-utterances are not perceptual, they are introspective. Their form is misleading. They are really different ways of making an introspective report to the effect that one is simply having a subjective pain experience with a certain intentional content about body parts and their disorders. They are misleading because pains are really in the brain, they are never in one’s body parts—strictly speaking, they can’t be (just as the IASP definition seems to imply). But they nevertheless represent disorders in body parts. So, our L-utterances don’t report disorders. Rather they report our subjective experiences. Thus, the best we can do about L-utterances is (5i), which gives the truth-conditions for what it is for John to have a pain in his toe.
However, the admission that L-utterances are not perceptual is perplexing given the general motivation of PR theorists. For we are now missing a proper (direct) perceptual judgment on this view. Judgments [this is damaged] and [this hurts]Footnote 13 immediately made consequent upon having a pain experience where “this” refers to a body part are very different judgments with radically different truth-conditions. The former is also inferential (although quite habitual), but the latter is not. The former judgment is rarely made solely on the basis of information supplied by nociception alone or even somaesthesis alone; it usually requires visual or other kinds of confirmation.
I don’t intend these brief remarks as anything like a refutation of PR, but I do want to highlight my dissatisfaction with this option. PR theorists make a mystery out of their own claim that pain experiences are perceptual/representational by conceding that we don’t seem to have (ever) genuine direct perceptual judgments properly based on them. So, I will leave (5i) aside for what follows.Footnote 14
Our troubles seem to stem from the fact that we wanted to interpret (5) as saying that the quality attributed to body parts is some sort of objective condition (disorder) of those parts. What if we drop this interpretation and opt for something else as the quality attributed to body parts? What would this be?
Given that we are taking the language of “attribution” as intentional in (5), whatever candidate we come up with as the quality attributed, it will generate accuracy conditions for pain experiences. This is, in fact, the source of our trouble with (5). Our options here are quite limited. This quality is either a naturalistic quality or it is not. If it’s a naturalistic quality, I don’t see any plausible candidate other than some kind of physical disorder (say, actual or potential tissue damage or injury).Footnote 15 But given the troubles with (5i), we can rule this possibility out. But, then, what could this quality be such that it can generate accuracy conditions when attributed to body parts? Consider (5ii) where the quality is taken to be a sui generis primitive quality not reducible to anything else:
(5ii) Whether or not John’s toe has any physical disturbance in it, John has a subjective experience that attributes to his toe some sort of primitive “painful” quality.
With this option, John has a pain in his toe if and only if he undergoes a subjective experience that represents his toe as having a primitive “painful” quality. Let’s call this quality P. Is this a veridical experience? Or in the material mode: does John’s toe have this primitive quality in it? It seems impossible to tell. P is not a physical quality, not identifiable or even (strongly) correlated with any physical condition of the body (beyond the CNS). So how do we make a judgment of veridicality?
The most plausible way to proceed here is to say that P is only a represented quality: the experience presents his toe to John as if it instantiated P but, in fact, P may not be instantiated in the actual world—not in the toe anyway. So, the experience is almost certainly not veridical. In fact, all pain experiences may be nonveridical according to this interpretation. P may live only in the intentional content of the pain experience projected on to John’s toe as if instantiated there. But P may in fact not be instantiated anywhere—including the experience. P is represented as instantiated, for sure, but in fact is not instantiated anywhere. Such a view is sometimes called figurative projectivism.Footnote 16
The important point, however, is that for John’s utterance to be true, it doesn’t matter whether John’s toe has P or not. According to option (5ii), the truth-conditions of L-utterances will be fixed independently of whether these experiences are accurate or veridical. In so far as John is undergoing a subjective experience that is presenting his toe as having this “painful” quality, P, John is having a pain in his toe. Thus, the primitive quality P and the property of being represented as having P are distinct properties. It’s the former property that is represented by the experience, not the latter. Bodily pain—John’s pain in his toe—is therefore not to be identified with P, but rather with the inverse intentional property of being represented as having P. The defender of this option wants John’s utterance to come out true. So, the concept John uses when he makes his report cannot be the mere concept expressing the property of P, as expected under this proposal. For his labeling use of this concept to locate an instance of P in his toe would make his utterance false, since P is nowhere instantiated. With this option, the concept John is utilizing (along with the rest of us) when he makes his true utterance must therefore be a concept expressing something like the inverse intentional property of being represented as having P. But this concept is not the concept of P.
At this point, however, the claim that John’s experience represents his toe as having this primitive quality becomes unmotivated for the purposes of understanding L-utterances. The notion of representation not only does no work here, it puts extra burden on the effort to remove the tension between bodily and experiential conceptions of pain by generating accuracy conditions for the subjective experience that the IASP definition identifies pain with. It makes the pain experiences always mistaken (in error), even though, surprisingly, the L-judgments based on these experiences reporting pains in body parts come out true as specified by (5ii). Note that this is a consequence of the fact that the concept utilized in the L-judgment attributes a different property than represented by the experience itself. Hence, the defender of this option owes us an explanation of the discrepancy between the contents of the experience and of the L-judgment directly based on it, for representationalism of this sort entails precisely the absence of such a discrepancy.
There is a more straightforward form of projectivism whose discussion will make the frivolousness of insisting on representationalism about pain even clearer:
(5iii) Whether or not John’s toe has any physical disturbance in it, John has a subjective experience with a “painful” quality P that attributes itself to John’s toe—equivalently: that represents itself as being instantiated in John’s toe.
This view is sometimes called literal projectivism (cf. Shoemaker Reference Shoemaker1994). The primitive quality P is not merely a represented property, but it’s also literally instantiated by John’s pain experience. However, P is a self-representational property too: it represents itself as being instantiated somewhere else, namely in John’s toe. So, the pain experiences are always in error as in figurative projectivism: P is not instantiated in John’s toe or in any bodily part (except in the CNS). Nevertheless, on this view, John’s utterance still comes out true despite the massive error the experience commits that directly grounds the L-judgment.Footnote 17
Sydney Shoemaker (Reference Shoemaker2000) has advanced an interesting variant of (5iii) for bodily pains. His view about what he calls occurrent appearance properties can be taken to imply that John’s utterance is true just in case: John has an experience with a subjective “painful” quality (quale) P that represents itself as being occurrently caused by his toe. This view fares better in normal acute pains in delivering veridical experiential contents, but makes most referred pain cases involve misrepresentation. Shoemaker seems to think that “a ‘referred pain in the arm’ is not really in the arm” (2000, 262) since the occurrent appearance property represented in the experience is not actually instantiated in the arm; it is, in fact, the heart that is occurrently causing P. To Shoemaker’s credit, this is an attempt to make the contents of the experience and of the L-judgment directly based on it semantically aligned. If we take a pain in body part b to be the relation that b instantiates by occurrently causing an experience with quality P in subject s, then John doesn’t have a pain in his toe, although he falsely thinks he does. So, on Shoemaker’s view, in a referred pain case, both the pain experience and the L-judgment based on it are mistaken—that is, have false intentional content. The implication of the view that John doesn’t have a pain in his toe is unacceptable.Footnote 18 The toe is where John feels the pain, so his L-utterance is true, even when there is nothing physically wrong with the toe and the toe is not causally responsible for John’s feeling pain in his toe.
A way of saving Shoemaker’s proposal is to make the same move as in the case of other representationalist options by saying that the experiential error involved, by fiat, should make no difference whatsoever in assigning truth-conditions to John’s utterance. In other words, it’s both necessary and sufficient for John’s utterance to be true that he has a subjective experience with a quality P that (mis)represents his toe as (occurrently) causing itself (P). So, again, the veridicality (thus, the representational character) of pain experiences is irrelevant whatsoever to the truth of those L-judgments directly based on them.
To better see the frivolousness of representationalism in the latter two formulations of (5), we can further note that another way to describe these options is to say that his toe somatosensorially appears to John to have a subjective primitive quality; this quality is appearance-dependent even to John. It is in fact an appearance property: it exists only in so far as it appears. On reflection, John won’t claim his toe to have the pain if there is no appearance whatsoever of the relevant kind (say, despite John’s full attention). It doesn’t make much sense to ask whether John’s toe might, in fact, lack the quality despite the appearances. But if so, this makes sense only if we don’t take the appearances to be making a semantic claim on reality—on whether or not John’s toe has in fact the “represented” quality. In other words, we have the option of not taking the appearances in pain experiences intentionally.
The situation is quite different here than in a case where I report how a ripe tomato appears by saying “it appears red to me.” Here the redness of the tomato is not (merely) an appearance property, so we can meaningfully ask whether the tomato is in fact red despite how it appears to me. The appearance here makes a claim on the reality,Footnote 19 inviting us to take the appearance intentionally, so that if the tomato turns out not to be red, one can blame my visual experience for providing me with “false appearances.”
Option (5), then, is not satisfactory no matter how we take the attributed quality to be. The moment we insist on John’s experience intentionally attributing a quality to his toe, we generate accuracy conditions for the experience that turn out to be irrelevant for the truth of the L-utterance or L-judgment based on it. John’s subjective experience doesn’t seem to represent his toe as having a certain quality in it or as being in a certain appearance-independent condition. This is not to say that John’s experience is completely representation free. There is clearly a representational element in so far as John’s experience is about his toe—it makes reference to his toe as part of his body. Rather, it is to say that it doesn’t do any predication by attributing any property or quality to it. In having the experience John has, his toe appears to John in a certain way, it appears to him “painfully.” This way of appearing is not intentional in the case of “pain in the toe”: it doesn’t represent any quality or property as instantiated in the toe even if the experience, in this case, manages to successfully refer to the toe. How can we use this insight in our investigation about what makes John’s utterance true?
Here is my proposal, which I claim does the best job in relieving the tension between the bodily and the experiential conceptions of pain without generating any error on the part of the experience:
(6i) Whether or not John’s toe has any physical disturbance in it, John has a subjective experience that presents his toe in a certain way—“painfully.”
Or, equivalently: Footnote 20
(6ii) Whether or not John’s toe has any physical disturbance in it, John has a subjective experience that makes his toe feel or appear to him in a certain way—“painfully.”
Before turning to the question of how to implement (6) in the next section and further argue for its superiority, I would like to revisit the tension between bodily and experiential conceptions of pain in light of the options discussed in this section. The important thing to note is that all of them except (2) are capable of resolving the tension if they turn out to be adequate otherwise. Option (2) is the only one about how to understand bodily pain that will make it incompatible with the experiential conception. Option (1) is to be rightly put aside; its coherence is dubious. Option (3) is extensionally not adequate as it leaves out referred pain attributions. Option (4) is metaphysically mysterious. Options (5) and (6), when interpreted in a naturalistic framework, work best to solve the puzzle of pain attributions and show that there is no real tension or incompatibility between the bodily and experiential conceptions, and that the dominant conception is the experiential one. Indeed, according to these options, a pain in a body part of a person is just the instantiation of an inverse intentional or quasi-intentional property. However, I’ve argued that all the representationalist options in (5) suffer from further problems and have undesirable consequences that (6) is free of. I’ll continue to elaborate on the superiority of (6) in the next section.
3. How to implement option (6)
What follows is a rough outline of how to implement (6) in a naturalist framework that comports well with the core traditional understanding of pains as both locatable items and subjective experiences. The proposal is weakly intentionalist, qualia-friendly, but fully naturalist, which has close affinities with adverbialism in philosophy of perception as is clear from the formulation of (6).Footnote 21
The fundamental insight behind (6) is that there is a quasi-intentional structure to the subjective experience, which the IASP definition identifies with pain. Like most (perhaps all) sensory experiences, pain experiences have a syntactic structure with a reference/predicate divide. John’s pain in his toe is an experiential presentation of his toe. This is the referential aspect of his experience. John’s pain experience presents his toe to him in a certain way. What way this is is determined by the predicative structure of his experience. In genuinely perceptual/sensory experiences—as arising, for instance from visual, auditory, and tactile modalities—the predicative structures function as property-attributive devices and the properties they attribute are the sensible objective features of the (usually) distal stimuli. But the claim here is that the predicative structure of pain experiences does not attribute any real properties or qualities to the distal stimuli (bodily parts) they refer to. Or to state the same point differently: it attributes only dummy properties. Thus, unlike the sensory experiences arising in most other modalities, pain experiences are not perceptual nor are they fully representational.
The talk of a reference/predicate divide in the structure of sensory experience might be disorienting since the distinction is usually made regarding linguistic or sentential syntactic structures. It need not be: we do have applications of this sort of syntactic structure in nonsentential or nondiscursive representational media. As an example, think of a paper marine chart of a certain marine region (say, the Burrard Inlet). The points or regions on the paper chart as fixed by the horizontal/vertical side coordinates of the chart (as labeled in terms of meridians of latitude and longitude) will pick out or refer to actual points or regions in the inlet. This is the referential aspect of the representational medium (paper chart). What colors, lines, or marks there are on those points or regions of the paper chart will then tell us what oceanographic or geographic properties (e.g., depth, currents rates or directions, submerged rocks, etc.) are true of the corresponding places in the inlet. This is the predicative aspect. Here we have a representational vehicle (the paper chart) with a syntactic structure roughly corresponding to referential and predicative functions. The claim is that sensory and perceptual experiences as intentional structures have a similar referential/predicative divide.Footnote 22 Despite the presence of a predicative structure, however, the representational format of sensory experiences is not conceptual, similar to the way the marine chart is not a discursive or sentential representation.
The idea in (6) is that pain experiences present body parts in a certain way—painfully, in all the phenomenally determinate ways our body parts are presented to us in pain. The qualitative or phenomenal character of pain experiences (like in all other perceptual experiences) is determined by their predicative structure.Footnote 23 This view is not only compatible with but naturally invites a qualia-friendly treatment of the subjective qualities of sensory experiences. Pain qualia are implemented by the proprietary predicates of the nociceptive system but are not representational in that they don’t function to attribute any quality to the body parts presented in the same experience. Pain qualia are the phenomenally determinate ways in which our body parts are presented to us or appear to us.Footnote 24
It is instructive to compare (6) to different versions of (5) above. The options in (5) are all representationalist: they claim that John’s subjective experience represents his toe as instantiating a certain quality P. According to (5i), this quality is some sort of physical disorder in the toe. According to (5ii) and (5iii), P is a sui generis primitive quality represented to be instantiated in John’s toe. Option (5ii) takes P to be instantiated nowhere—P lives only in the representational content of pain experiences. Option (5iii) takes P to be instantiated in John’s pain experience: P, we may say, is the pain quale instantiated in the pain experience and determines John’s pain phenomenology. This part of (5iii) is compatible with (6).Footnote 25 But (5iii) makes the further claim that P is a self-representational quality: it represents itself as instantiated in John’s toe when in fact nothing of this sort can be instantiated in toes or other bodily parts. Thus (5ii) and (5iii) make pain experiences commit massive error at all times—even though, at the end, this error doesn’t affect the assignment of correct truth-conditions to L-utterances (thus, showing the frivolousness of representationalism). Option (6) is like (5iii), but is not (fully) representationalist. There is a pain quale instantiated in the experience which presents John’s toe to John in a certain way: this is a way John’s toe appears to John without making any claim on the condition of his toe. John may come to believe or judge that something is (physically) wrong with his toe as expected. But this is not a proper perceptual judgment directly based on the pain experience—it’s inferential but usually quite habitual. It’s very different than the genuine perceptual judgment [this is red] directly formed on the basis of having a visual experience of a red apple under normal circumstances. P is a phenomenal way of appearing—it presents body parts “painfully” without attributing a quality (objective or otherwise) to those body parts.
Our discussion of John’s pain in his toe and his utterance has revealed the remarkable peculiarities of L-utterances and L-judgments. Pain scientists and clinicians like everybody else routinely use this language without suffering from the apparent conflict it seems to present in light of the IASP definition of pain as a subjective experience. Option (6) gives us the truth-conditions of L-utterances by making essential use of the phenomenal character of pains as subjective experiences—as the IASP definition presupposes.Footnote 26 If we take the bodily conception of pain to be denoting the pains reported in L-utterances—i.e., pains located in body parts—then the bodily conception of pain turns out to be perfectly compatible with the experiential conception of pain as stressed by the IASP definition. Indeed, they are not only compatible, but (6) requires the experiential conception.
As with options in (5), it is possible to express (6) in terms of the language of inverse intentional properties. With his true utterance, John locates a bodily pain in his toe. Under (6), the “property” located is the inverse property of [the toe’s] appearing a certain way to John (“appearing painfully to”). Under the naturalistic implementational framework I prefer, this amounts to his toe’s instantiating the inverse property of being the referential target of John’s pain experience with respect to which a proprietary predicate (implementing the same experience) is being activated in John’s nociceptive system. We noted before that in having a pain in his toe, John is confronted with an appearance-dependent quality of his toe, and indeed he himself would take this quality to be appearance-dependent (at least after reflection) and to be metaphysically independent of any physical condition of his toe.Footnote 27 Option (6) tells us how this can be so—making the bodily conception harmonious with the experiential conception of pain as embodied in the IASP definition.
How does (6) compare to (4)? There is a deflationary way of reading (4) so that it becomes compatible with (6). Option (4) quantifies over a subjective quality in the toe outside of the scope of the intentional verb “sense” (or, “is aware of”), but then makes the instantiation of the quality metaphysically dependent on its being sensed. This generates an uneasy circularity. Whether the circularity is vicious depends on further claims one might want to make about the situation. One way to understand (4) is to identify the act of sensing with the instantiation of the pain quale P by the pain experience: the instantiation of P in John’s experience (in relation to his toe) is the act of his sensing the toe painfully. The act of sensing his toe painfully is then to be identified as a whole with the instantiation of a subjective quality in John’s toe. If we do this and tolerate the loose talk of John’s sensing this quality, then (4) and (6) become compatible indeed. But under this interpretation, it is loose talk to speak of sensing or being aware of a subjective quality in one’s toe: strictly speaking, John is not sensing any quality in the sense in which we use this phrase to talk about sensing sensible properties of extramental objects or events such as sensing the colors or vibration of objects or surfaces. Of course, when John reflects on its experience, it will seem to him that his toe has a subjective quality instantiated in it. But this is doxastic seeming immediately prompted by his experience. There is no other way for John to reflect on his own experience. But this is perfectly in line with the truth of his judgment (and L-utterance) when he locates pain in his toe just as (6) says: he is sensing his toe painfully, thus there is a subjective quality (a pain) instantiated in his toe, making his judgment or L-utterance true. Furthermore, John’s judgment is appropriately based on his so sensing the toe.
Before concluding this work, I would like to briefly discuss a peculiar attempt to save representationalism. Given the implementational framework I have in mind for (6), one might be tempted to say the following.Footnote 28 The proprietary predicate activated (with respect to John’s toe) in John’s nociceptive system represents the toe as being the (semantic) target of its own activation, which we identified with the toe’s having a pain in it. Let “#P(t)” denote the activation of this sensory predicate targeting the toe referred by the sensory referential device t. Then the suggestion becomes: #P(t) is true if and only if t successfully refers to John’s toe and is the filler of the argument place in #P( ). The truth of the right-hand side is what makes it the case that #P( ) represents itself as being instantiated with reference to John’s toe (thus, making #P(t) true): this in turn is what makes it the case that John has a pain in his toe. So, it seems like we can have our representationalist cake and eat it too if we tolerate self-representational and self-verifying sensory predicates.
I have various reasons for wanting to avoid taking this line. Three of them stand out as worthy of quickly mentioning here. First, I am very fond of an information-theoretic psychosemantics à la Dretske for sensory and perceptual mental predicates (see Aydede and Güzeldere Reference Aydede and Güzeldere2005). According to information-theoretic principles, no event can carry information about its own occurrence.
Second, and relatedly, for a psychosemantic naturalist like me, a self-verifying mental predicate is not only mysterious but is also an anathema to taking intentionality seriously enough to attempt to naturalize it: if you take the notion of (attributive) representation seriously, it ought to be the notion of something that can be misapplied, misattributed—a representation that cannot misrepresent is no representation at all.
Third, even if we put these worries aside, taking this line forgets what the primary impetus was behind representationalism about sensory experiences in the first place: namely, to avoid quantifying over “irreducibly psychic” items like sense-data or qualia. But a representationalist who claims that a pain in the toe is nothing but a self-representing and self-verifying mental quality instantiated in one’s experience semantically targeting the toe has to advert to a nonrepresentational quality of the experience (qua sensory predicate—not content—as should be clear from the statement of the biconditional above), which is anathema to any transparency claims that representationalists (as well as disjunctivists) are fond of making about sensory experiences (see my 2009, 2019). Moreover, any representationalist who likes to take this line with the intention of putting all bodily sensations on the same naturalist footing would make a mockery out of their claim that in a sensory experience like pain in the toe, John is detecting, sensing, feeling a condition of his toe, in the same way in which John would be detecting or sensing the vibration in his toe upon, say, starting the engine of his sailboat. On the other hand, there is a way of taking this representationalist proposal as representationalist only by courtesy: all that happens is that the sensory predicate #P( ) is activated with t as the filler of its argument place referring to the toe, and then it’s claimed that #P( ) represents the toe as being the target of its own activation. This sounds like a claim tucked at the last minute in virtue of one’s representationalist predilections, not quite clear what work it’s supposed to be doing. We don’t need to make this further claim to make sense of (6). It complicates things unnecessarily and has unwelcome consequences: if the implementational framework is generalized to all sensory experiences, as is my intention, it makes all sensory experiences have a layer of self-representational and self-verifying content that “mentions” nonintentional (“syntactic”) features of experiences that are epistemically available to sensing, perceiving, and introspecting agents of a certain complexity. This should be alarming to direct realists and (ironically) to naturalist representationalists themselves (see Aydede Reference Aydede2019).
Finally, as we’ve seen, referred pains cause problems for many proposals discussed above. In particular, (2) through (3) and the Shoemaker’s version of (5iii) are unable to explain the truth of sincere L-utterances ascribing referred pains to otherwise healthy and functioning body parts. Other versions of (5) can accommodate referred pain ascriptions but they make pain experiences semantically mistaken, even though, as we’ve seen, these mistakes do not at the end affect the assignments of correct truth-conditions to L-utterances reporting referred pains. Option (6) has none of these problems. If John’s pain in his toe is a referred pain, then John’s sincere utterance is true and there is no semantic mistake in John’s experience. The referential term in John’s experience, t (perhaps realized in the “toe” part of the somatosensory homunculus in John’s primary somatosensory cortex), successfully refers to his toe: it presents his toe to John. The somaesthetic informational channel necessary to referentially connect his toe to John’s cortex is intact, and there is, for the most part, a good amount of information flowing through this channel despite the glitch in John’s lower spine. This glitch causes the referential device, t, to activate a neural pattern, #P (realizing the pain quale P), which makes John’s toe appear to him painfully. The experiential reference to the toe is successful, but it’s unfortunate that the experience presents this toe in the way it does: this presentational way (the instantiation of P) in this particular case doesn’t carry any information about the physical condition of the successfully presented toe. So, John’s experience is misleading but not mistaken.Footnote 29
4. Concluding remarks
There are various virtues of (6). Unlike representationalist or perceptualist accounts, it frees pain experiences from committing mistakes or error. Unlike the projectivist options in (5ii) and (5iii), there are no representational mistakes anywhere in John’s pain system according to (6) and the implementational framework I prefer. One robust mark of projectivism, as we’ve seen, is that it makes experiences under consideration massively illusory or somehow mistaken. Nothing of this sort happens with (6). So (6) is not projectivist. Indeed (6) comports well with the traditional understanding of pain as not representational. In all these respects, the account of pain attributions to body parts both in language and thought provided by (6) is superior to its competitors. It solves the puzzle with which we started this essay, and it does that without attributing deep confusion or incoherence to the folk or to pain scientists or clinicians. There is no real paradox in the ordinary, clinical, or scientific understanding of pain, just a conceptual tension of the sort a careful philosophical analysis would clarify and relieve.
The importance of pain experiences, as in other intransitive bodily sensations, is that their peculiarities tell us something very important about the metaphysics of the conscious sensory experience in general, something that the contemporary philosophy of mind, with its heavy reliance on representationalism and visual perception, has lost sight of.Footnote 30
Acknowledgments.
Different versions or portions of this work were delivered at the University of Oxford and the University of Reading. I would like to thank the audiences. In particular, many thanks to Mike Martin and Emma Borg for their helpful comments and questions on these occasions. Thanks also to Adam Bradley, Laurenz Casser, Jonathan Cohen, Linda Davies, Matt Fulkerson, Joshua Gert, Adam Shriver, Andrew Wright as well as two anonymous reviewers for their insightful comments on earlier versions of this work.
Murat Aydede received his Ph.D. from the University of Maryland at College Park in 1993. He was a faculty member in the philosophy departments of the University of Chicago (1994–2001) and the University of Florida (2001–2007). He has been a professor in the philosophy department of the University of British Columbia since 2007.