1. Introduction.
Recently, several philosophers have argued that an adequate understanding of evolutionary theory after the Modern Synthesis calls for “a radical revision of received conceptions of causal relations in evolution” (Matthen and Ariew Reference Matthen and Ariew2002, 57). Contrary to the traditional view held by both biologists and philosophers of biology, natural selection is not a cause of evolutionary change. Rather, it is a statistical trend, a “formally characterized phenomenon, a statistical property of physical substrates that possess certain metrical properties” (Matthen and Ariew Reference Matthen and Ariew2002, 68–69, emphasis in original). According to this purely statistical interpretation, the only causal processes in evolution are at the level of biological individuals (or below), and none of these can be identified with metrical properties like selection and drift (Walsh, Lewins, and Ariew Reference Walsh, Lewens and Ariew2002, 453; cf. Matthen and Ariew Reference Matthen and Ariew2002, 69).
These authors single out for critique what they call the dynamical interpretation of natural selection, according to which natural selection theory is understood as a theory of forces analogous to Newtonian mechanics. Some responses to this critique have defended parts of the Newtonian analogy (Stephens Reference Stephens2004). Others have argued that natural selection is an individual-level causal process, according to which “selection [is] a contingent causal process in which individual fitnesses are the causes and subsequent population differences are the effects” (Bouchard and Rosenberg Reference Bouchard and Rosenberg2004, 710; see also Rosenberg and Bouchard Reference Rosenberg and Bouchard2005). Still others have argued that natural selection is a population-level causal process in which variation in heritable abilities to survive and reproduce causes differential reproductive success and, when a population is not in equilibrium, changes in genotype and/or phenotype frequencies (Millstein Reference Millstein2006; see also Reisman and Forber Reference Reisman and Forber2005).
I think that the dynamical interpretation is flawed; there are too many important differences between forces like gravity and phenomena like natural selection and drift for the analogy between Newtonian mechanics and evolutionary theory to be particularly helpful. For instance, distinct evolutionary factors do not in general decompose and recombine like vectors. Of course, even if natural selection is not a force, it may still be a cause (cf. Stephens Reference Stephens2004). Further, there are powerful arguments that natural selection must be population-level causal process, if it is a causal process at all (see Millstein Reference Millstein2006; Glymour Reference Glymour1999; Sober Reference Sober1984). After the modern synthesis, evolutionary theory is a probabilistic theory that abstracts away from the contingencies and vicissitudes of individual organisms’ life histories.
Thus, the view of natural selection as a population-level causal process is attractive. However, there is a fundamental question that faces any such view: namely, what I call the grounding question.
Grounding Question. How are population-level causal processes related to the causal processes that occur at the level of individual organisms, and how is this relation compatible with the causal nature of population-level processes?
All sides of the debate agree that there are causal processes that (exclusively) involve properties of individual organisms. Further, as I discuss below, proponents of the population-level causal process view acknowledge that the causal processes involving individual organisms are somehow responsible for, determine, or are the basis for the process of natural selection.
Given this consensus, the grounding question is structurally similar to the so-called “causal exclusion problem” in the philosophy of mind (see, e.g., Kim Reference Kim1989, Reference Kim1998). Indeed, some authors have argued that the individual-level causal processes (events or properties) preempt or screen off the population-level processes (events or properties) that they determine, in the same way that the physical realizers of mental properties allegedly preempt the causal efficacy of those mental properties (if they are held to be distinct from their realizers) (see Walsh Reference Walsh2000, especially p. 139 and p. 150; Walsh Reference Walsh2004).Footnote 1 Given that individual-level events are causally sufficient for the evolutionary fate of a population, it seems that one must either abandon the causal efficacy of population-level phenomena like selection (i.e., adopt the statistical view) or identify selection with an individual-level causal process. Thus, it looks like the population-level causal view is unstable, just as Kim has alleged that nonreductive physicalism about the mind is unstable.
The grounding question has not been addressed in the literature on natural selection, and the main goal of this paper is to redress this. I show how a metaphysical framework normally discussed in debates in the philosophy of mind can be fruitfully employed in philosophy of biology. Thus, this paper is a first step toward fleshing out the similarities between metaphysical debates in these areas that have been noted in passing by others (e.g., Fodor Reference Fodor1997, 162–163, n. 7; see also Shapiro and Sober, Reference Shapiro, Sober, Wolters and Machamerforthcoming). In particular, I use a version of the realization relation, which has been put forth as the relation between mental and physical properties, to address issues about the causal status of natural selection. The realization relation is commonly defined as follows: an entity (property, state, object) P realizes another entity (property, state, kind, predicate/formula) Q if and only if P satisfies the condition (fills the role) that is definitive of Q. P is a realizer of the realized entity Q. There are, of course, various ways of making this account more precise by specifying the nature of the condition or role (e.g., whether it is causal, computational, mathematical, or folk-theoretic) and what one takes ‘filling’ that role to consist in. Below, I discuss two such ways; one involves causal relations, while the other is purely formal.
After discussing how the grounding question is related to the exclusion problem in Section 2, I sketch a causal account of realization in Section 3. I argue that a causal account of realization can be used to provide an adequate answer to the grounding question. If the population-level properties involved in the process of selection are realized in this way, then they are grounded in individual-level causal properties so that the exclusion problem does not arise. In Section 4, I consider in detail the case of adaptive melanism in rock pocket mice and show how the causal account of realization applies to it. I use this example to argue that the formal account of realization sketched by Matthen and Ariew cannot completely capture the phenomenon of natural selection. I conclude in Sections 5 and 6 by presenting and responding to an argument for the claim that natural selection cannot provide unified causal explanations.
2. The Grounding Question and the Exclusion Problem.
According to Millstein, the proponent of the population-level causal view does not “deny that populations are composed of individuals or that causes are acting on those individuals. Nor [does she] deny that individual-level causal events (living, dying, and reproducing) are in some sense responsible for selection. What [she denies] is that such individual-level causal events constitute the selection process itself” (Reference Millstein2006, 650). In claiming that individual-level causal events are “in some sense responsible for selection,” Millstein rightly rejects a strong emergentist view according to which natural selection is a novel force that appears in populations of organisms. Yet this appears to sit uneasily with the claim that these individual-level causal events do not ‘constitute’ the selection process. The apparent tension in this passage suggests a crude version of the exclusion problem; if individual-level causal events are responsible for selection, what ‘causal work’ is left for the distinct population-level process of selection to do?
In order to state the problem more precisely, note that individual-level causal events (as long as they are individuated partially in terms of the environment in which they take place) must constitute (determine or ground) the selection process. Otherwise, the population-level causal view would violate plausible completeness and exclusion principles.Footnote 2 In this context it is not the completeness of physics that is salient but what might be called the completeness of Darwinian biology.
Completeness of Darwinian Biology. Every evolutionary outcome is completely determined by a causal process that involves only births, deaths, mutations, genetic recombination events, etc.Footnote 3
Yet this completeness principle alone does not rule out a strong emergentist view of selection, for it is compatible with the existence of a novel, completely distinct force of selection that acts independently of Darwinian events in the production of evolutionary outcomes. So we also need an exclusion principle.
Exclusion Principle. Barring cases of overdetermination, there cannot be two or more causal processes responsible for a given evolutionary outcome.
If these two theses are accepted, then it appears that one cannot consistently claim that natural selection is a population-level causal process that is not identical to any individual-level causal process. Just as the exclusion problem in the philosophy of mind is supposed to force a choice between the reduction or causal impotence of mental properties, we seem to be forced to claim that natural selection is either an individual-level causal process or an epiphenomenal population-level process.
Upon reflection, it is apparent that the reasoning behind the exclusion problem plays two roles in the metaphysics of evolution. The first is laudable and sound: to rule out strong emergentism regarding selection and drift—for instance, it rules out the view that individual-level causal events are ‘responsible for’ selection in that they cause selection which in turn causes evolutionary change. The second role is pernicious and unsound: to force a choice between epiphenomenalism and reduction to individual-level processes—thus leading to the claim that the grounding question rests on a mistake and should be given a deflationary response by denying that there is a population-level causal process that is distinct from the individual-level causal processes that are taking place in the population.
In the next section, I spell out in what sense individual-level causal properties/relations are ‘responsible for’ and ‘constitute’ the properties involved in population-level causal processes like selection. I argue that natural selection is a causal process that is realized by, but not identical to, the individual-level causal processes occurring in a biological population. This allows me to endorse the first role of exclusionary reasoning while rejecting the second. Thus, I preserve the grain of truth in the statistical interpretation while rejecting radical, anticausal claims that are an integral part of it.
3. A Causal Account of Realization Provides an Answer to the Grounding Question.
First of all, I believe that supervenience does not provide substantive answer to the grounding question for reasons similar to those that have convinced many philosophers to reject supervenience-based formulations of physicalism (see, e.g., Horgan Reference Horgan1993; Wilson Reference Wilson2005). Supervenience requires only covariation between a set of supervenient properties and a set of base properties. Thus, it is compatible with a variety of metaphysical positions that fail to answer the grounding question (and thus run afoul of the exclusion problem), e.g., emergentism and dualist occasionalism. Supervenience is also compatible with a deflationary treatment of grounding question since ‘metrical properties’ (mere averages, variances, etc.) supervene on individual-level properties and events. These compatibilities obtain because supervenience is silent about the metaphysical ground of the covariation relations it implies. In particular, there is no reason to think that the supervenient properties need even be eligible for causal efficacy.
But if supervenience fails to provide an answer, why think that there is a substantive answer to the grounding question at all? According to the statistical interpretation, there is not. The core claim of the statistical interpretation is that natural selection is a mere ‘trend’, a change in ‘stochastic properties’—ones that are mathematical (not nomic or causal) consequences of the individual-level properties of organisms in that population (Matthen and Ariew Reference Matthen and Ariew2002, 81). Stochastic properties belong to statistical populations and are not causally efficacious. For example, it is perfectly mathematically or formally legitimate to calculate stochastic/metrical properties of the statistical population of all the moths alive in 1945 or 1951 in Australia or England. If natural selection is merely a stochastic trend, then the grounding question can be dismissed as misguided. For, there would be no causal process of natural selection to ground in the first place.
However, there is good reason to think that such ‘stochastic’ properties are not the kind of ‘population-level’ properties that are involved in the process of natural selection. Evolutionary processes involve causal properties of a biological population of organisms that are realized by the properties of individual organisms and their relations to other organisms and their environment. Examples of such properties of biological populations include a population's size, rate of migration/gene flow, and variation in phenotypic traits (which result in variation in ability to survive/reproduce) within a population. In the next section, I show how some of these properties are realized in a particular case and argue that they are not ‘mere averages’; they are not stochastic properties of a statistical population of organisms.Footnote 4
If stochastic properties alone fail to capture certain features of a population undergoing natural selection (cf. Millstein Reference Millstein2006, which makes similar points), then it is clear why the statistical interpretation misses this. It conflates two notions of ‘population’: (1) a mathematical notion of population—an abstract, mathematical object used in statistics whose membership conditions can be biologically arbitrary, and (2) an empirical, biological notion of population, “a group of conspecific organisms that occupy a more or less well defined geographic region and exhibit reproductive continuity from generation to generation” (Futuyma Reference Futuyma1986, 554–555).Footnote 5 Importantly, organisms in a biological population are bound together or unified by causal processes such as mating, competition, niche construction, and being subject to common ecological circumstances (e.g., floods, fires, droughts). Further, biological populations plausibly fit into the levels of organization in nature that are ordered by the part/whole relation (e.g., subatomic particles, atoms, molecules, cells, individual organisms, populations of organisms).
It is important to note there can be statistical populations at any level of organization within the latter hierarchy, e.g., the average mass of a kind of cell (a cellular-level property). Hence, even if the statistical interpretation were correct, it would imply nothing about the level of organization at which causal processes occur. The core claim of the statistical view does not show that all realized properties of a biological population are causally inefficacious, any more than it shows that all realized properties of a cell are causally inefficacious, assuming that there is no reason to claim that realized properties, in general, are causally inefficacious.
Yet Matthen and Ariew sketch and utilize a formal account of realization, according to which realized properties are causally inefficacious.Footnote 6 According to this view of realization, (1) realizers of more abstract selection formulae are produced by the logical operation of conjunction, (2) it is solely the ‘formal character’ of natural selection theory that accounts for the fact that natural selection is multiple realizable, and (3) what unifies all of the realizers of a single realized property is their formal, not causal, structure (see Matthen and Ariew Reference Matthen and Ariew2002, 74–77, 71–72, 81). If this account of realization were the only one available, then the realized properties of a biological population of organisms would be merely metrical or ‘stochastic’. Thus, the only causally efficacious properties would be the basic, unrealized properties at the level of individual organisms (if any; perhaps such properties would only be found at the fundamental physical level).
However, there is a notion of realization that is not purely formal and which does not lead to the conclusion that selection is not a causal process. Roughly, according to this kind of realization, a property X of entity o is realized by properties
$Y_{1},\,\ldots ,\,Y_{n}$
of o's parts and their environment if and only if X bestows causal powers to o in virtue of the fact that
$Y_{1},\,\ldots ,\,Y_{n}$
bestow causal powers to o's parts, and not vice versa (see Gillett Reference Gillett2002).Footnote 7 I think that it is at best a programmatic sketch of a complete account of realization. But the details of such an account will not matter for the debate about selection or for answering the grounding question. Alternatively, one could adopt something like Shoemaker's account (Reference Shoemaker2003) of microrealization, except that in the biological case the realizers will not be states of affairs involving microphysical entities propertied and related in certain ways but rather states of affairs involving individual organisms (and their environment) propertied and related in certain ways.
Given this account of how properties realize other properties, one can provide a derivative account of how causal processes realize other causal processes (where a causal process is a sequence of causally related property instantiations). Suppose we have a causal process ψ in which the instantiation of property C is causally sufficient for the instantiation of property E. If φ is a causal process in which the instantiation of
$Y_{1},\,\ldots ,\,Y_{n}$
is causally sufficient for the instantiation of
$Z_{1},\,\ldots ,\,Z_{n}$
, then φ realizesP ψ if and only if C is realized by
$Y_{1},\,\ldots ,\,Y_{n}$
and E is realized by
$Z_{1},\,\ldots ,\,Z_{n}$
(in the sense given in the previous paragraph). The claim that natural selection is a realizedP causal process is thus shorthand for the claim that the population-level properties, C and E, which are the cause and effect in the process of natural selection are realized by properties of and relations between the individuals in the population, and the properties/relations that realize C are causally sufficient for those that realize E. In what follows, I drop the subscript from process-realization.
If we can show that properties of biological populations are realized in this way by individual-level properties, then we will have provided a substantive answer to the grounding question. First, this account of realization clearly allows causal properties (and causal processes in which they are involved) to be realized by other causal properties (and processes). Second, these population-level properties are more abstract and more modally flexible than their realizers—they may be instantiated when their realizers are not (i.e., they may be multiply realizable). Hence, they are arguably not identical to their realizers.Footnote 8 Third, and most importantly, realized population-level properties are compatible with the completeness of Darwinian biology. They do not compete with their realizers for causal sufficiency because the properties they involve are abstract ‘logical parts’ of the properties that realize them (in the same way that being red is part of being scarlet or being translucent is part of being water).Footnote 9 In this way, they are not something in addition to the causal processes involving Darwinian events. Further, since they are not independent of the individual-level properties that realize them, they do not violate any exclusion principle that would rule out strong emergentism or dualism regarding selection. There are not two independent causal processes that result in a single outcome. That is, the exclusion principle, as stated above, is too strong. It should be reformulated so that it allows for cases in which simultaneous causal processes are related by the causal realization relation.
Of course, if natural selection is captured equally well by a formal realization relation, then all of this is neither here nor there. In the next section, I spell out in detail how the causal realization framework applies to a particular case of natural selection: the evolution of melanism in rock pocket mice. And I argue that a formal realization relation cannot completely capture biologically important features of this case.
4. Natural Selection for Melanism in Rock Pocket Mice.
The rock pocket mouse, Chaetodipus intermedius, lives in rocky areas of the desert southwest. Most of their habitat consists of light-colored rocks, and the mice typically have light-colored pelage. However, on several dark lava flows separated from each other by hundreds of kilometers, the overwhelming majority of mice have dark fur. It is believed that melanism in these mice is an adaptation against predation. Owls are one of their major predators, and earlier experiments have shown that owls prey differentially on light and dark mice.
Coat color in mice, and in mammals generally, is determined by the amount of two forms of melanin: eumelanin, which is brown or black, and phaeomelanin, which is yellow to dull red. The relative amount of these pigments is controlled by the interaction of the melanocortin-1 receptor (MC1R), a seven transmembrane G-protein-coupled receptor expressed at high levels in melanocytes, and the agouti signaling protein which is an antagonist of MC1R.
Nachman, Hoekstra, and D'Agostino (Reference Nachman, Hoekstra and D’Agostino2003) found that four, nonsynonymous single-nucleotide polymorphisms (at nucleotide positions 52, 325, 478, and 699) were responsible for charge-changing amino acid polymorphisms (Arg-18-Cys, Arg-109-Trp, Arg-160-Trp, and Gln-233-His). These polymorphisms were found only in the population of dark mice at Pinacate, Arizona and were in complete linkage disequilibrium with one another.Footnote 10 Of the 17 dark mice caught at this site, 11 were homozygous for the dominant, dark (D) allele, while six were heterozygous, resulting in an allele frequency of 28/34, or approximately 82%. Nachman, Hoekstra, and D'Agostino claim that one or more of these amino acid mutations is responsible for the melanic phenotype in the Pinacate population. Hence, they conclude that this locus is under disruptive natural selection across the two habitats (i.e., the dark lava flow and surrounding light rocky areas).Footnote 11 This conclusion is supported the fact that the perfect association found between phenotype and genotype is extremely unlikely in a panmictic population with no assortative mating unless the given gene (or a tightly linked gene) is responsible for the phenotype (Nachman, Hoekstra, and D'Agostino Reference Nachman, Hoekstra and D’Agostino2003, 5271).Footnote 12 Further, the possibility that a linked gene is responsible for the melanic trait is unlikely given (1) that no other genes in pigmentation pathways are linked to the Mc1r locus in humans or mice, and (2) that other amino acid substitutions in Mc1r have been shown to be responsible for melanic phenotypes in mice and other organisms, including geese, bananaquits, and dogs.
However, this evidence is not conclusive, for population structure (e.g., isolation by distance) could be responsible for the observed phenotypic variation. That is, the perfect association between melanic phenotype and the D allele at the Mc1r locus could be spurious; the Mc1r gene could not be involved in the production of the phenotype at all. Further, even if the Mc1r locus is responsible for the melanic phenotype, this does not imply that selection was responsible for the phenotypic and genotypic polymorphism. Although “the reduced variability seen among the dark Mc1r alleles [as compared to the light haplotypes] is the expected pattern if selection has recently fixed an adaptive substitution” (Nachman, Hoekstra, and D'Agostino Reference Nachman, Hoekstra and D’Agostino2003, 5272), “two standard tests of neutrality [the McDonald-Kreitman test and the HKA test] fail to detect selection on Mc1r in the Pinacate population, either in the total sample or in the subpopulations on light and dark substrate” (5273).
If demographic history or population structure caused the observed variation, one would expect all loci in the genome to have been equally affected. Thus, if population history or structure were responsible for the habitat-restricted variation, then variation at neutral loci should be expected to correlate with variation in phenotype. This hypothesis was tested by sequencing two neutral mitochondrial DNA (mtDNA) loci, COIII and ND3 and using these data to construct a phylogeny (Nachman, Hoekstra, and D'Agostino Reference Nachman, Hoekstra and D’Agostino2003). Haplotypes from light and dark mice were found to be haphazardly distributed on this phylogeny; there was no correlation between variation at these neutral sites and phenotypic variation, supporting the claim that selection, not population structure and history, was the cause of the spread of the dark allele and phenotype on the lava flow.Footnote 13
Using a larger sample size, Hoekstra, Drumm, and Nachman (Reference Hoekstra, Drumm and Nachman2004) confirmed the absence of population structure in the Pinacate population; there was no correlation between mtDNA haplotype and either geography or color phenotype (see also Hoekstra, Krenz, and Nachman Reference Hoekstra, Krenz and Nachman2005). Using estimates of migration rates and Mc1r allele frequencies and a simple model of migration-selection balance, Hoekstra, Drumm, and Nachman (Reference Hoekstra, Drumm and Nachman2004) estimated selection coefficients of 0.013–0.390 against light mice/alleles on dark rocks and of 0.0002–0.0200 against dark mice/alleles on light rocks. “Together these results suggest that natural selection acts to match pocket mouse coat color to substrate color, despite high levels of gene flow between light and melanic populations [at Pinacate]” (Hoekstra, Drumm, and Nachman Reference Hoekstra, Drumm and Nachman2004, 1329).Footnote 14
Several population-level causal processes are occurring in the Pinacate population: selection against the d allele on the dark lava flow, somewhat weaker selection against the D allele on the light rocks surrounding the lava, and asymmetric migration/gene flow between the subpopulations on the lava flow and on the surrounding light rock. These processes are distinct, and gene flow is opposing selection in this population. If selection were not occurring (or were weaker), then the population would likely become more homogenous; if gene flow were not occurring (or were weaker), then the differences between the subpopulations in the two habitats would likely become greater.
Further, the properties involved in these processes are realized by different properties of and relations between individual mice and their environment. In selection, the property variation in camouflage ability (X) of the population of mice (which, in turn, in part realizes variation in the mice's abilities to survive/reproduce) is causally efficacious. This property is realized by the coat colors of the individual mice in that population, together with their relation to the substrate on which they live, their relations to other mice on that substrate (with respect to coat color/reflectance), and their relations to predators like owls and other mammals (
$Y_{1},\,\ldots ,\,Y_{n}$
). By contrast, other properties of the individual mice and their environment will realize the properties involved in the process of gene flow, such as the speed and agility of individual mice, their ‘attractiveness’ to potential mates, and the availability of food resources on the different substrates.
Assuming that the camouflage ability of individual mice can be quantified (relative to a substrate), the variance of a randomly selected sample of mice will be an estimate of variation in camouflage ability within the population. However, neither this estimate, nor the mathematical property of the true population variance, can be identified with variation in camouflage ability in the mice population. To do so would be to conflate a mathematical population with a biological one. The same variance could be possessed by a spatiotemporally and causally diffuse set of mice, but in such a case, it would not contribute the causal powers that variation in camouflage ability contributes to the Pinacate population, e.g., the power to adapt to a dark substrate. (See the discussion of temperature below.) Variation in camouflage ability contributes this power to the population of mice in virtue of the fact that the light coat color of some mice in the population enables them to blend into the sand while the dark coat color of other mice enables them to blend into the lava. Similar claims will be true for any other powers contributed by variation in camouflage ability. Thus, variation in camouflage ability is causally realized by the individual-level properties and relations in the mice population.
These sketches of the realization relations that obtain in the mice population reveal that the formal account of realization is unable to capture the phenomenon of natural selection. In order for natural selection to be realized, it is crucial that the population of mice be spatiotemporally and causally unified. Since the relation between stochastic realized entities and their realizers is purely formal or mathematical, it leaves out these interactions between mice, predators, and their environment which are required for the realization of natural selection.
To see this more clearly, it may help to consider a somewhat simpler example. A particular sample of water can be thought of as a causally unified population of molecules and ions. Population-level properties of the sample, like translucence, electrical conductance, temperature, and viscosity, are realized by properties of and relations between the molecules and ions. But the formal account of realization is unable to distinguish between these causally efficacious population-level properties and mere ‘stochastic’ population-level properties. For instance, the same average kinetic energy, and thus the same ‘temperature’, could be formally realized by a sample of water in the glass on my table and by a motley assortment of H2O molecules scattered across the solar system.
5. Causal Explanation and Natural Selection.
According to the causal view of realization, a number of properties are simultaneously realized in the Pinacate population: variation in genotype, variation in coat color, variation in camouflage, and variation in ability to survive/reproduce. If the discussion in Sections 2 and 3 is correct, these properties do not compete for causal sufficiency since each is causally realized by the properties of and relations between individual mice (and their environment). However, even if this discussion provides an answer the metaphysical issue raised by the grounding question, these population-level properties arguably still compete in the context of causal explanations (cf. Yablo Reference Yablo1992, 273ff.). That is, if the above discussion is correct, it shows that an exclusion principle regarding causal processes (or causal sufficiency) is too strong. However, one might still accept an exclusion principle regarding causal explanation, to the effect that there cannot be two or more independent causal explanations of a given evolutionary outcome. Given such a principle, which of these properties should be used in explanations cited in a biologically general theory of natural selection? In the last section, I left this unclear, as have previous defenses of the population-level causal view.Footnote 15
In fact, there is a powerful dilemmatic argument the upshot of which is that, no matter what properties appear in it, a suitably general natural selection theory cannot offer causal explanations. On the one hand, fairly specific, fine-grained population-level properties either will not be sufficient for selection or will miss objective biological similarities between populations. On the other hand, abstract, coarse-grained properties will be either too causally heterogeneous (too disjunctive) or too ‘causally thin’, and hence will be unprojectible and useless for empirical, causal explanations.
I think that the first horn is incontrovertible. For instance, in three other melanic populations of mice living on dark lava flows in New Mexico, none of the four amino acid substitutions in Mc1r were observed (Hoekstra and Nachman Reference Hoekstra and Nachman2003). Further, the polymorphisms that were observed at the Mc1r locus in these populations were not associated with coat color. This suggests that: “Adaptive melanism has evolved independently in different populations of Chaetopidus intermedius and has done so through changes at different genes” (Hoekstra and Nachman Reference Hoekstra and Nachman2003, 1191). If these other mutations had subsequently occurred in a few mice in a population that was already fixed for the D allele at the Mc1r locus, there would be no further selection for melanism because the mice would be (virtually) indistinguishable to predators. Thus, not just any specific variation in genotype is causally sufficient for selection.Footnote 16
Further, the same is true of variation in phenotype. Suppose that the D allele has pleiotropic effects so that all mice with this allele are slightly more sensitive to pain and suppose that this trait has no consequences for survival and reproduction. Then, variation in sensitivity to pain will be perfectly correlated with variation in coat color, but although there will be selection of mice who are sensitive to pain there will not be selection for sensitivity to pain (see Sober Reference Sober1984). Thus, not just any heritable variation in phenotype is causally sufficient for selection.
Finally, such properties like variation in genotype and variation in phenotype are unable to capture certain biological similarities. Consider the rock pocket mice again. Hoekstra and Nachman (Reference Hoekstra and Nachman2003) showed that there were no significant differences between rock color among four lava flows in New Mexico and Arizona. And, although there were minor phenotypic differences between populations—melanic mice in the New Mexico populations were slightly, but significantly, darker than those in the Arizona population—it is clear that similar selection pressures existed in these different populations (Hoekstra and Nachman Reference Hoekstra and Nachman2003). Despite differences in causal processes occurring in these populations at the genetic level, it is biologically important to recognize that the same type of relatively abstract, causal natural selection process acted in each population. Variation in camouflage ability (which must include relations to the environment and not just the coat color of mice) caused changes in phenotypic and genotype frequencies over time. Finer-grained population-level properties (like variation in genotype) are unable to capture this important biological similarity. Further, this similarity with respect to selection processes is distinct from other causal similarities that might obtain between populations: e.g., similar amounts of gene flow, similar population structure/history.
For similar reasons, one should not claim that the various selection pressures acting on a population are identical to an instance of the causal process of natural selection. Rather, the abstract causal selection process is realized by the various selection pressures acting on different populations. As Walsh, Lewens, and Ariew (Reference Walsh, Lewens and Ariew2002, 467) argue, in what I call the identity argument, identifying selection pressures such as predation and sunlight exposure with natural selection would lead to the untenable conclusion that natural selection is identical to drift (or that selection constitutes drift), since in certain cases these selection pressures lead to drift. Thus, on this proposal the causal interpretation allegedly “short-circuits itself”; there is no “causal (or explanatory) work for drift to do” (Walsh, Lewens, and Ariew Reference Walsh, Lewens and Ariew2002, 467).
Using the mice example again, we can avoid this conclusion by claiming that what one might call the ‘maximal realizer’ (i.e., the individual-level properties of all of the mice in the population and the entire habitat) simultaneously realizes both selection and drift. (Just as the microstructure of a sample of water simultaneously realizes its transparency, conductivity and viscosity.) Realized processes, like selection and drift, are different ways of abstracting away from the details in the maximal realizer by focusing on different causally relevant aspects of that realizer (heritable variation in a trait that is causally relevant reproductive success, and, perhaps, population size, respectively).
These considerations raise a problem for Millstein's (Reference Millstein2006) defense of the population-level causal view. In her argument, she focuses on the causal basis of a particular selection pressure (and corresponding adaptation). Hence, it is not clear that her discussion of how biologists established the ‘causal basis of selection’ at a certain locus completely succeeds in showing that natural selection is a causal process. Rather, it seems that it instead shows how differences in willow leaf beetles’ ability to withstand extreme temperatures are realized (partially) in a polymorphism at the PGI locus. That is, it spells out the details of a particular instance of the general realization framework presented here. I do not, of course, object to Millstein's naturalistic use of real biological examples to make a metaphysical point. And I agree that the physiological work done to uncover the ‘underlying mechanism’ supports the ecological claim that the ability to withstand extreme temperatures is the relevant adaptation for these beetles. However, this does not show how natural selection as a population-level causal process is related to the individual-level causal processes that occur (the account of realization given here is needed to do that). Without providing this—without answering the grounding question—the population-level causal view is undermined. Further, Millstein's discussion does it tell us whether the specific variation in ability to withstand extreme temperatures or the more abstract variation in ability to survive/reproduce is the property that should be cited in a causal, selectional explanation in this case.
However, if it is the more abstract property of heritable variation in the ability to survive and/or reproduce that is employed in natural selection explanations, then the second horn of the dilemma outlined above comes into play. For, variation in the ability to survive and/or reproduce looks suspiciously similar to variation in fitness. Elliott Sober (Reference Sober1984) has argued that fitness is not causally explanatory because it is a (heterogeneous) disjunctive property—that is, because fitness is multiply realizable and there is no causal process that unites all of the various realizers. Different realizers of fitness produce differential reproductive success/failure via different causal processes. Even if one argues that ability to survive and/or reproduce is not identical to fitness (as suggested by some passages in Millstein [Reference Millstein2006]), the same argument applies to the former as to the latter.
Another way of pushing this horn of the dilemma arises out of Matthen and Ariew's understanding of multiple realizability (Reference Matthen and Ariew2002). They take Lawrence Sklar's understanding (Reference Sklar1999) of what makes quantities in statistical thermodynamics, like entropy and temperature, multiply realizable and suggest that it applies to the properties that appear in natural selection theory as well. According to this picture, it is the formal character of statistical thermodynamics that accounts for its ‘universal applicability’ to heterogeneous domains. A quantity like temperature is not a (sparse) physical property but “a way of characterizing ensembles” (Sklar Reference Sklar1999, 195). Statistical thermodynamics “mathematically demonstrates a phenomenon that occurs regardless of [the] physical details of the system” (Matten and Ariew Reference Matthen and Ariew2002, 80). Similarly, “natural selection is the consequence of heterogeneous processes in substrates sharing only a formal structure” (81, my emphasis).Footnote 17
According to this view, natural selection theory does not provide causal explanations because the predicates that appear in it do not pick out sparse properties. Thus, because the theory of natural selection only captures formal unity, one should not expect all of the satisfiers of a selection formula to have any properties in common other than those that are mathematically definitive of the natural selection formula. Any generalizations of natural selection theory are a priori or conceptual once an adequate selection formula is determined.Footnote 18
6. Causal Processes, Disjunctive Properties, and Empirical Generalizations.
In this section I argue that the second horn of the dilemma can be blunted. It is not heritable variation in ability to survive and/or reproduce that is distinctive of causal selection explanations, but the more specific property of heritable variation in ability to survive/reproduce due to the interaction of a particular trait and the environment.Footnote 19 The focus on a particular trait ensures that this population-level property is not `wildly' disjunctive at the level of biological individuals. It is the causally efficacious (population-level) property that biologists attempt to measure by calculating trait fitness. This is reflected in the fact that the simplest models in population genetics simply assume that all of the fitness differences are determined by a single locus. Also, when calculating trait fitness by averaging over the survival/reproductive success of all organisms with a given trait, one attempts to determine the mean ability or advantage bestowed by that single trait. That is, it is assumed that with a large enough sample the advantages and disadvantages (abilities and disabilities) bestowed by other traits will ‘average out’ yielding a normal distribution. Of course, this process can always be confounded by perfect correlations between traits (e.g., genetic hitchhiking). But in the absence of such problems, trait fitness will be a good measure in expectation of the ability conferred by that particular trait, which is a component of the organism's overall ability to survive and reproduce. And of course, variation in this component will be a population-level property.
This view of things nicely fits the practice and assumptions of biologists. Given that “elucidating the causes of population divergence is a central goal of evolutionary biology” (Hoekstra, Krenz, and Nachman Reference Hoekstra, Krenz and Nachman2005, 217), a complete understanding of those causes requires that “we identify traits that are ecologically important and have some understanding of how these traits affect fitness in different environments” (Nachman, Hoekstra, D'Agostino Reference Nachman, Hoekstra and D’Agostino2003, 5268).
This suggestion also handles “multiply beneficial traits”—traits that cause survival and reproductive success (or failure) via two or more distinct causal processes—perhaps as tusks and feathers do (for scientific examples see the references in Glymour [Reference Glymour1999]). Since such traits contribute to survival and reproductive success (or failure), they are part of a selection process. Further, while for some purposes it is obviously useful to distinguish between the distinct causal processes that lead to this outcome (e.g., defense against predators and attracting mates), there is no reason why there cannot be a more abstract causal process that incorporates each of these more fine-grained processes. In some cases, this kind of process will be hard to describe, but that does not make this an ad hoc maneuver. In fact, such an abstract, unifying process will be scientifically important whenever there are trade-offs between the various fine-grained processes. Even when each ‘component’ is beneficial, one will not always be able to find their net effect by adding the effects each would have in isolation. The more abstract causal process will include any interaction effects that obtain when the individual processes are coinstantiated.
It is, of course, an empirical matter what causal generalizations and processes are there to be found. For instance, there may be a causal process that is common to every case covered by the very general account of selection given by Hull, Langman, and Glenn (Reference Hull, Langman and Glenn2001). But such a causal process would be so abstract that it is doubtful that there are any novel, empirical generalizations to discover about it. That is, it is doubtful that there is an empirical science that covers all of the instances of the selection process sketched by Hull, Langman, and Glenn. Of course, the debate at hand is concerned solely with Darwinian natural selection in populations of biological organisms (what Hull, Langman, and Glenn [Reference Hull, Langman and Glenn2001] characterize as ‘gene-based selection’), and there is good reason to think that the trait-specific population-level properties that are involved in the causal process of selection are projectible. That they are is one reason why evolutionary biology is a unified subdiscipline. For instance, one can make predictions about how populations of different organisms will evolve based on abstract evolutionary similarities between them (e.g., if they are affected by similar selection pressures), even when the organisms are phylogenetically and ecologically quite different. Instances of convergent evolution are examples of this.
Finally, the discussion in this paper assumes that causal processes do not involve only interactions or quantities from fundamental physics. In particular, it is assumed that there can be causal processes involving chemical and biological properties (cf. n. 7). Of course, this is compatible with all such processes in the actual world being ultimately realized by interactions between fundamental physical properties. (Indeed, it is plausible that physicalists are committed to every causal process being so realized.) However, spelling out exactly how that realization would go and giving a general account of causal processes are tasks for another occasion.Footnote 20
7. Conclusion.
If natural selection is a population-level causal process, then it is a process whereby variation in heritable ability to survive/reproduce due to the interaction of a particular trait and the environment (e.g., variation in camouflage ability in the rock pocket mouse example) causes differential reproductive success. This causal process is compatible with the existence of causal processes at the level of individual biological organisms because the population-level properties involved in natural selection are causally realized by properties of and relations between individual organisms: variation in camouflage ability confers causal powers on the population of mice (e.g., the power to adapt to a dark substrate) in virtue of the fact that coat color confers causal powers on individual mice (together with relations to their environment). The formal account of realization proposed by defenders of a purely statistical interpretation of natural selection is unable to capture the phenomenon of natural selection and its relation to other evolutionary processes like gene flow and population subdivision. The causal realization framework captures these phenomena and also shows how natural selection theory is able to provide causal explanations and empirical generalizations and predictions.