Hostname: page-component-69cd664f8f-wvgvr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-03-13T06:03:22.038Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Citizens All? Citizens Some! The Making of the Citizen

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 November 2003

Immanuel Wallerstein
Affiliation:
Yale University
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Extract

Inequality is a fundamental reality of the modern world-system as it has been of every known historical system. What is different, what is particular to historical capitalism, is that equality has been proclaimed as its objective, and indeed as its achievement—equality in the marketplace, equality before the law, the fundamental social equality of all individuals endowed with equal rights. The great political question of the modern world, the great cultural question, has been how to reconcile the theoretical embrace of equality with the continuing and increasingly acute polarization of real-life opportunities and satisfactions that has been its outcome.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
© 2003 Society for Comparative Study of Society and History

Inequality is a fundamental reality of the modern world-system as it has been of every known historical system. What is different, what is particular to historical capitalism, is that equality has been proclaimed as its objective, and indeed as its achievement—equality in the marketplace, equality before the law, the fundamental social equality of all individuals endowed with equal rights. The great political question of the modern world, the great cultural question, has been how to reconcile the theoretical embrace of equality with the continuing and increasingly acute polarization of real-life opportunities and satisfactions that has been its outcome.

For a long time, for three centuries from the sixteenth to the eighteenth, this question was scarcely mooted in the modern world-system. Inequality was still considered natural, indeed ordained by God. But once the revolutionary upsurge of the late eighteenth century transformed the language of equality into a cultural icon, once challenges to authority everywhere became commonplace, the disparity of theory and practice could no longer be ignored. The need to contain the implications of this cultural claim, and thereby to tame the now “dangerous classes,” became a priority of those who held power. The construction of the liberal state was the principal framework that was built to limit the claim. The elaboration of modern ideologies was in turn an essential mechanism in the construction of the liberal state.

The great symbolic gesture of the French Revolution was the insistence that titles no longer be used, not even that of Monsieur and Madame. Everyone was to be called “Citoyen” (Citizen). This gesture was intended to demonstrate the repudiation of traditional hierarchies, the incrustation of social equality in the new society that was being constructed. The French Revolution came to an end. Titles were reinstituted. But the concept of “citizen” (if not its use as a title of address) survived. It did more than survive—it thrived. It became adopted everywhere, to the point that by 1918 the world found it necessary to invent the concept of “stateless” persons, to describe the relatively small portion of humanity who were unable to claim citizenship anywhere.

The concept of citizen was intended to be inclusive—to insist that all persons in a state, and not just some persons (a monarch, aristocrats) had the right to be included in the process of collective decision-making in the political arena and the right to receive the social benefits the state might distribute. Since that time, the existence of rights that are guaranteed to citizens has comprised the minimal definition of what constitutes a modern “democratic” state, which virtually every state now claims to be.

But the other face of the inclusiveness of citizenship was exclusion. Those who were not citizens of the state had become by definition aliens—citizens, perhaps, of some other state, but not of this state. Still, for any given state, even the exclusion of aliens within their boundaries did not limit very much the number of persons theoretically included. In most cases, more than 90 percent of the residents of the country were citizens—legally citizens, that is, for citizenship had now become a matter of legal definition.

And this was precisely the problem faced by the states after the French Revolution. Too many persons were citizens. The results could be dangerous, indeed.1

“A specter haunted most publicists at the beginning of the nineteenth century: that of social dissolution. . . . At the heart of these common preoccupations lay the wish to circumvent the model of popular sovereignty. . . . It was the numbers that were frightening” (Rosanvallon 1985:75–76).

The story of the nineteenth century (and indeed of the twentieth) has been that some (those with privilege and advantage) have been attempting to define citizenship narrowly and that all the others have been seeking to validate a broader definition. It is around this struggle that the intellectual theorizing of the next 200 years centered. It was around this struggle that the social movements were formed.

The way to define citizenship narrowly in practice, while retaining the principle in theory, is to create two categories of citizens. The effort started with Abbé Siéyès, just six days after the fall of the Bastille. In a report he read to the Constitutional Committee of the National Assembly on 20–21 July 1789, Siéyès proposed a distinction between passive and active rights, between passive and active citizens. Natural and civil rights, he said, are rights “for whose maintenance and development society is formed.” These are passive rights. There also exist political rights, “those by which society is formed.” These are active rights. And from this distinction, Siéyès drew the following conclusion:

All inhabitants of a country should enjoy in it the rights of passive citizens; all have the right to the protection of their person, of their property, of their liberty, etc. But all do not have the right to play an active role in the formation of public authorities; all are not active citizens. Women (at least at the present time), children, foreigners, and those others who contribute nothing to sustaining the public establishment should not be allowed to influence public life actively. Everyone is entitled to enjoy the advantages of society, but only those who contribute to the public establishment are true stockholders (actionnaires) of the great social enterprise. They alone are truly active citizens, true members of the association (Siéyès 1789:193–94).

On 29 October 1789, the National Assembly translated this theoretical concept into a legal decree that defined active citizens as those who paid a minimum of three-days wages in direct taxation. Property became the prerequisite of active citizenship. As Rosanvallon (1985:95) points out, “If reason is sovereign, men cannot invent laws. They must discover them. . . . The notion of capacity finds its logic in this framework.”

The attempt to circumscribe the meaning of citizenship took many forms, all of them necessarily involving the creation of antinomies that could justify the division into passive and active citizens. Binary distinctions (of rank, of class, of gender, of race/ethnicity, of education) are ancient realities. What was different in the nineteenth century were the attempts to erect a theoretical scaffolding which could legitimate the translation of such distinctions into legal categories that served to limit the degree to which the proclaimed equality of all citizens was in fact realized.

The reason is simple. When inequality was the norm, there was no need to make any further distinction than that between those of different rank, generically between noble and commoner. But when equality became the official norm, then it was suddenly crucial to know who was in fact included in the “all” who have equal rights, that is, who are the “active” citizens. The more equality was proclaimed as a moral principle, the more obstacles—juridical, political, economic, and cultural—were instituted to prevent its realization. The concept, citizen, forced the crystallization and rigidification—both intellectual and legal—of a long list of binary distinctions which have formed the cultural underpinnings of the capitalist world-economy in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries: bourgeois and proletarian, man and woman, adult and minor, breadwinner and housewife, majority and minority, White and Black, European and non-European, educated and ignorant, skilled and unskilled, specialist and amateur, scientist and layman, high culture and low culture, heterosexual and homosexual, normal and abnormal, able-bodied and disabled, and of course the ur-category which all of these others imply—civilized and barbarian.

To be sure, the concept of citizenship was meant to be liberating, and it did indeed liberate us all from the dead weight of received hierarchies claiming divine or natural ordination. But the liberation was only a partial liberation from the disabilities, and the new inclusions made sharper and more apparent the continuing (and new) exclusions. Universal rights turned out in actual practice to be somewhat of a linguistic mirage, an oxymoron. The republic of virtuous equals turned out to require the rejection of the non-virtuous.

Liberalism, which would become the dominant ideology of the modern world, preached that virtue could be taught, and it therefore offered the managed progression of rights, the managed promotion of passive citizens to the status of active citizens, a road for the transformation of barbarians into the civilized. Since the process of legal promotion was thought to be irreversible, it had to be handled carefully, prudently, and above all gradually. On the other hand, those social movements that were being created to champion the interests of those whose rights were not fully recognized were always debating what might be done to end this. There were those who insisted that the movements should be antisystemic, that is, that they must seek to destroy the existing historical system which made possible the travesties of equality. And there were those who were essentially integrationist, that is, who believed that the role of the movements was to speed up the liberal program of managed acquisition of rights.

The story, as we have already seen, began with the French Revolution itself. The National Assembly and then the Convention were faced with three concrete issues about citizenship: women, Blacks, and workers. The record of the French Revolution was mixed, but in each case, there were exclusions that left bitterness.

In the case of women, the whole matter started out badly. The royal decree summoning the Estates-General edicted that women who held seigniorial fiefs had to choose male proxies to represent them in the Electoral College—nobles for lay women, clergy for nuns (Landes 1988:232, fn. 5). It is well known that women played a major role in various popular demonstrations during the French Revolution, most crucially in the so-called October days in 1789, when the Parisian market women (along with national guardsmen) marched on Versailles and forced the royal couple to come to the capital to reside. But a mere two months after these riots, on 22 December 1789, the National Assembly formally excluded women from the right to vote.2

Condorcet did write a famous pamphlet in 1790 calling for women to have droit de cité, but his voice was not heeded.

The Constitution of 1791 renewed the exclusion, and this was reiterated in a vote of the Convention on 24 July 1793, specifying that women were excluded from all political rights.3

It should be noted that this is a regression over the historic situation in France. “When Philip the Fair solemnly convened the first Estates-General . . . in 1302, he received an assembly chosen by both men and women. For over five centuries, privileged women of all estates retained the vote, both local and national. Then in the 1790s, the revolution that proclaimed the rights of man abolished the political rights of women” (Hause with Kenney 1984:3).

Some improvements in women's rights were instituted, it is true. Marriage and divorce became civil processes. Primogeniture was abolished, and the rights of illegitimate children and their mothers to financial support created. A law was passed permitting women to be witnesses in documents related to the état civil, although this matter continued to be controversial (Abray 1975:55). And in the heated atmosphere of the Jacobin period, women began to organize. They began to play a much larger role in the popular societies. They stood outside the doors of the Convention, trying to control who would enter. They packed the galleries and shouted their views (Landes 1988:139–40).

On 5 May 1793, the Society of Republican-Revolutionary Women was formed. They pushed vigorously the demands of women for bread. Their language had distinctly feminist overtones. They were allied to the enragés (George 1976–1977:420), who were critical of the Jacobins from the left. But above all, they were women, organized women, who insisted on being heard. When women in one Paris section petitioned for the right to bear arms, Fabre d'Eglantine sputtered in the Convention: “After the bonnet rouge, which the Républicaines wore during their meetings, comes the gun belt, then the gun” (Abray 1975:56). The Committee on Public Safety appointed a committee, headed by André Amar, to consider whether women should exercise political rights and whether they should be allowed to take part in political clubs. The answer to both would be no. The committee deemed that they did not have the “moral and physical qualities” to exercise political rights, and furthermore, it was the aristocracy which wanted women to have these rights “in order to put women at odds with men” (George 1976–1977:434).

As for participating in political associations, Amar was quite explicit as to why women should not be allowed to be members:

If we consider that the political education of men is at its beginning, . . . then how much more reasonable is it for women, whose moral education is almost nil, to be less enlightened concerning principles? Their presence in popular societies, therefore, would give an active role in government to people more exposed to error and seduction. Let us add that women are disposed by their organization to an over-excitation which would be deadly in public affairs and that interests of state would be sacrificed to everything which ardor in passions can generate in the way of error and disorder (cited in Landes 1988:144).

To be sure, the exclusion of women was often put forward as a temporary provision. An earlier report by Lanjuinais in April 1793 called for the exclusion of women from political rights “for the time that it will take to remedy the vices of women's education.” As Cerati remarked acerbically: “[These vices] must have been terribly tenacious since it took a century and a half to overcome them” (1966:170).4

Why it was the women's clubs that became the first victim of the Law of Suspects has been a matter of considerable debate. Whatever the explanation, the situation did not change after the downfall of the Jacobins. In 1795, after the journée of ler Prairial, the Convention excluded women from the hall entirely, unless accompanied by a man with a citizen's card (Abray 1975:58). And in 1804, the Napoleonic Code regressed over even the Ancien Régime. Previously, at least aristocratic women were allowed to handle property and legal matters. Now, in the more egalitarian mood of the French Revolution, all women were treated equally, all having no rights whatsoever (Levy et al. 1979:310).

The story of Blacks was not too different. There were of course few Blacks in France proper at the time of the Revolution. But there were the colonies, and above all St.-Domingue, and this was the subject of a major debate in Paris. St.-Domingue had had a clear system of social stratification before the Revolution. There was a small White stratum, most of whom were planters. There was a stratum of free mulattos. But the largest group were the Blacks, and the Blacks were almost all slaves. This was an ordinal social ranking. But none of these groups had political rights. The French Revolution was thus received enthusiastically by all three strata, because they all hoped for political liberation. However, the Whites did not wish social equality to be granted to the free mulattos, and neither the Whites nor the free mulattos wanted the enfranchisement of the slaves. Once again, the norm of equality raised the question of who is to be included.

The emancipation of the slaves in 1793 was not the fruit of the egalitarian impulses of the French revolutionaries. It was imposed by the power of Toussaint L'Ouverture, leader of the slave rebellion in St.-Domingue, and merely ratified by the Convention (Decree No. 2262 of 4 Feb. 1794), a decree that would be revoked by Napoleon in 1802 after Toussaint had been imprisoned (and not reenacted until 1848). What is more revealing, however, is the prior debate on the rights to be accorded to free mulattos. Pushed by the Amis des Noirs and opposed by the Club Massiac, which represented the interests of the White planters, the Assembly decided “unanimously” on a curious compromise. After the adoption of the decree granting the vote to free men of color, Dupont de Nemours presented a “declaration” of the Whites explaining their assent on the grounds that the vote was only being given to “qualified mulattos of free parents” and was not being accorded, could not be accorded, “to unfree persons, or freedmen, since these were members of a ’foreign nation'” (Blackburn 1988:187–88). The poor Whites on St.-Domingue opposed any property qualification, since that would give the vote to some free mulattos while not to them. They used the same argument, that the free mulattos were “a species of foreigner with no entitlement to political rights” (Blackburn 1988:177). Thus what was being argued is that not only slaves but even the free mulattos were by definition not part of the “nation”; they could not therefore be citizens.

As for French workers, the concept of active citizenship, by creating a property-based definition of political rights, resulted in excluding them, was intended to exclude them. In the heady revolutionary atmosphere, however, workers began to seek improvement of their situation by organizing. The Assembly had abolished the guilds. The rapid rise of prices plus the collapse of the paper money, the assignats, fueled worker effervescence, peaking in the spring of 1791 just before the flight of the king and the enactment of the Constitution. Strikes and disorders seemed beyond the control of the Paris municipality, and led to calls for action by the Assembly. While maintaining the inegalitarian standards for voting, the Assembly sought to use the ideology of equality against the possibility of workers to organize by enacting an “anti-cabal” law. The notorious Loi Le Chapelier, adopted on 14 June 1791, outlawed any workers' combination, and on 20 July this proscription was extended to the compagnonnages, the mutual benefit societies (Wallerstein 1989:107, and fn. 248).

The French Revolution appealed to nature, which was a universal phenomenon, belonging to everyone. But it also appealed to virtue, which was only a potential (but not necessarily the actual) characteristic of everyone. From these concepts, it derived the existence of human rights. Since there could be multiple capacities and then for some multiple “natures,” the discourse had an “ambivalent quality” (Landes 1988:123). Scott sums up “the persistent question of the relationship of specific, marked groups to the embodied universal” quite well: “how could the rights of the poor, of mulattos, blacks, or women be figured as the rights of Man? The general answer is: with difficulty” (1989:2).

The great socially unifying concept of the citizen thus led to the formalization of multiple cross-cutting binary categories and to the binary tension of political life—the split between right and left, the Party of Order and the Party of Movement—a split that centrist liberalism would devote all its efforts to minimize. The result was an intense zigzagging of public life, energized by the juggernaut of a belief in progress, and distorted by the continuous and increasing social and economic polarization of real life within the world-system.

In the nineteenth century, the so-called middle classes came to dominate the Western world, and Europe came to dominate the world. When one has achieved top position, the problem is no longer how to get there but how to stay there. The middle classes nationally, and the Europeans globally, sought to maintain their advantage by appropriating the mantle of nature and virtue to justify privilege. They called it civilization, and this concept was a key ingredient of their effort. In the Western world, it was translated into education, and education became a way of controlling the masses.5

See Thompson's summary (1997:23): “Attitudes towards social class, popular culture, and education became ’set' in the aftermath of the French Revolution. For a century and more, most middle class educationalists could not distinguish the work of education from that of social control: and this entailed too often a repression of or a denial of the validity of the life experience of their pupils as expressed in uncouth dialect or in traditional cultural forms. Hence education and received experience were at odds with each other. And those working men who by their own efforts broke into the educated culture found themselves at once in the same place of tension, in which education brought with it the danger of the rejection of their fellows and self-distrust. The tension of course continues still.”

And on the global scene, starting with Napoleon (but adopted subsequently by all the other European powers), “the concept of civilization as an ideology . . . became unashamedly a form of cultural imperialism” (Woolf 1989:119).

The French Revolution would come to a definitive political end and become thereafter merely a political symbol and a cultural memory. It left however a legacy to the whole world-system: Sovereignty now belonged to the people, the nation; and political debate and political change were their normal consequence. The privileged strata of the world-system had to come to terms with this legacy, to try to incorporate it institutionally in ways that would contain its potential for the radical dislocation of existing hierarchies.

This process of containment took three forms. The first was the crystallization of what came to be called ideologies, which claimed to be philosophical constructs but were actually primarily political strategies (Wallerstein 1995). The second was the elaboration of conceptual categories as a new discourse with which to describe the world. This was initially and primarily, as we have said, the work of the dominant strata, who hoped thereby to frame the debate and justify the limiting of citizenship. Eventually, this work of creative conceptualization became transformed and institutionalized in the structures of knowledge known as the social sciences (Wallerstein et al. 1996:ch. 1). And the third was the establishment of a network of social movements, initially primarily the work of the dominated strata, which were to serve however not only as agents of furthering change but also as mechanisms of limiting change.

From this time forward, those who were not considered active citizens demanded to become so. And they encountered resistance every step of the way. But it is also true that those who created the organizations with which to demand this inclusion always themselves resisted the concepts of “citizens all.” They promoted the rights of the particular group they represented and tended to be silent about, often directly opposed to, the struggle of other excluded groups, seeing them as rivals, at least as rivals in priority. They tended to act as though they wished to secure a place on a lifeboat called citizenship, but feared that adding others after them would overload it. The nineteenth century would see this melodrama acted out in the principal liberal states of the world-system by the three main groups that organized in this period—the workers, the women, and the Blacks.

The conflicts of the social movements—not only with the powers that be but also with each other—occurred within the context of the crystallization of ideologies that occurred after 1848. The period from 1815 to 1848 had been one in which all and sundry seemed to be moving uncertainly in this transformed political terrain. The reactionaries tried to turn the clock back, to undo the cultural earthquake that was the French Revolution. They discovered that this was not really possible. The dominated (and repressed) strata, for their part, were in search of appropriate and effective modes of organizing. And the emergent liberal center was unsure of how it should, or could, construct the appropriate political base to get the turmoil under control. They concentrated on constructing liberal states, first of all, and most importantly, in the most powerful countries, Great Britain and France.

It would be the world revolution of 1848 and its immediate aftermath that would require resolving these uncertain searches and efforts, in order to stabilize the world-system and restore a certain degree of political equilibrium. The movement for socialism6

In 1948, socialism was still “a big head on a very small body, a body that was not even autonomous. The tail, a lively tail, of the movement for bourgeois democracy” (Willard 1978:39).

would now separate itself clearly from centrist liberalism (Lichtheim 1969:vii; Lehning 1970:171; Bruhat 1972:505; Kocka 1986:333). The revolutions of 1848 constituted the first world revolution of the modern world-system. It is not that it occurred in all parts of the world-system, since it did not. Nor is it that the revolutionaries achieved their objectives, since everywhere the revolutions were defeated politically. It is that the multiple revolutions centered around the same issue, the issue of exclusion, exclusion from the benefits of citizenship. It was in 1848 that we first see clearly that there would be two kinds of antisystemic movements, two separate ways of dealing with this exclusion in terms of immediate objectives: more rights within the nation (the social revolution); separating one ethno-national group from another dominant one (the national revolution). Whether overcoming the exclusions was a sufficient objective or whether they should be truly against the (modern world-) system as such would of course become a continuing internal debate of these movements.

And it was in 1848 that the question of long-term strategy first became clearly posed. From 1815 to 1848, the ideological struggle had been considered to be one between liberals and conservatives, between the heirs of the spirit (if not of all the tactics) of the French Revolution and those who fervently sought to restore the order derived from an older way of viewing the world. In this struggle, “democrats” and “radicals” had little place. Anathema to the conservatives, an embarrassment to the liberals, they played a gadfly role, pressuring the liberals to be more daring (without much success, be it noted). What the revolutions of 1848 did was to open up the possibility that these democrats/radicals would do more than be a gadfly, that they would organize mass action separate and distinct from the liberal center.

This was a terrifying prospect not merely to the conservatives but to the liberal center. And both reacted accordingly. Suppression became the order of the day, not merely in the Russian and Austro-Hungarian empires, and among the various regimes in the Germanies and Italies, but in the liberal states of France and England. The suppression would be effective, but not long-lasting, for all these movements would re-emerge in a decade or two, and in far stronger forms. What was lasting were the conclusions that the proponents of the three classical ideologies of the nineteenth century—conservatism, liberalism, and socialism—would draw as the lessons of 1848.

The liberals drew two lessons. One was that they were in many ways closer to the conservatives than they had thought, and that alliances with radical elements were often dangerous to their interests. But secondly, they determined that they had to elaborate better theoretical justifications of the distinctions that they continued to wish to make among the citizenry, between the active and passive citizens à la Siéyès, if they wished to sustain this distinction.

The conservatives drew a different lesson. The strategy of Metternich (really of de Maistre, Bonald, et al.) would not work. They were impressed that only Great Britain did not have an uprising, even though it had been the country where radical forces had been the strongest. They noticed that Great Britain had been the only country where conservatives had followed a more centrist path, ready to make some concessions, in order to absorb and co-opt at least middle class forces into the arena of political decision-making. And they noticed that this policy had succeeded, by cutting “the very ground from under democracy,” as The Times put it.7

The leader in The Times, published on 26 February 1848, is worth reading at length: “During the remarkable period [since 1830] the Sovereigns and Governments of England have been steadily improving and popularising all the institutions of the country. They have immensely expanded the basis of representation. They have evidently and deliberately increased the power of the Commons. They have opened the municipalities. They have qualified and destroyed the monopolies of companies and of classes. They have liberated manufactures and commerce. But why need we linger on details? In a word, they have thrown themselves into the arms of the people. They have cut the very ground from under democracy by satisfying, one by one all its just desires. Let any one, who has not yet attained to the midday of life, compare the popular agitations of the present kind and that preceding the last French revolution. England was then incessantly disturbed by clamour for organic change. The peerage, the church, the rights of property, law, monarchy, and order itself, were to disappear. Mark the change which has come upon that turbulent scene. Popular agitation is in these days of a purely rational, and, so to speak, legislative character. Thousands and tens of thousands meet to impress upon their representatives their opinion—and generally their wise opinion—on a pending question, not concerning the fundamentals of society or the reconstruction of the state, but some minor and debatable point. The discussion is lawful in its subject, and regular in its tone” (cited in Saville 1990:229; italics added).

The conservatives would now be ready to go down the path of pursuing some version of centrist liberalism, albeit a somewhat more conservative one, what historians have come to call “enlightened conservatism.”

Socialists and nationalist-revolutionaries (erstwhile democrats and radicals) drew a still different conclusion. It was that spontaneity was not enough.8

They already knew that conspiracy would not work. The utter failure of Blanqui's uprising in 1839 was telling. In 1846, Karl Schopper, on behalf of the London Communist Correspondence Committee wrote in a letter: “[A] conspiracy has never been of benefit to anyone except our enemies. . . . We are certainly convinced that one cannot avoid a grand revolution, but to bring about such a revolution through conspiracies and silly proclamations . . . is ridiculous” (cited in Ellis 1974:42). But now the conclusion went beyond doubting the value of conspiracies to doubting the sufficiency of spontaneous rebellion.

What was needed was systematic and long-term organization, in order to be in a position to have a major political impact. This would lead the “movements”—an ephemeral concept—down the path of bureaucratic organizations, with members and officers, with finance and newspapers, with programs, and eventually with parliamentary participation. What 1848 led the movements to see was that the “people” were unlikely to do anything that mattered to the state without their prior uniting in organizational form. This would inevitably make them focus on the state, the national political level. It would also eventually and inevitably call into question the degree to which these movements continued to be antisystemic and not simply a variant of centrist liberalism, albeit a somewhat more impatient one.

The story of the rest of the nineteenth century, and indeed of a good part of the twentieth century, was that the centrist liberals would theorize, the anti-systemic movements (both of the socialist and the national liberation variety) would organize, and the enlightened conservatives would enact the compromises.9

A good example would be what happened in Germany. In the period between 1848 and 1870, the Liberals achieved substantial political power in the City Councils of the larger urban areas. In the Kaiserreich after 1871, controlled essentially by conservatives, universal male suffrage was instituted for Reichstag elections, one of the major expressions of “enlightened conservatism.” The Liberal municipalities resisted copying this idea, maintaining what in Prussia was called the Three-Class system, and for good reason. Universal suffrage was a threat to control of the City Councils by the Liberals. Sheehan notes: “Long after [the Liberals] had been seriously weakened [in the Reich-stag and most state parliaments] they remained a formidable if often beleaguered force in local institutions. The most important reason for this was the restricted suffrage for local elections. . . . For those who saw the cities as the last refuge of liberalism it became crucially important to protect urban institutions from the ravages effected on the national scene by the democratization of political life” (1971:131, 134).

And in the process, they seemed to compromise the antisystemic movements. It was, however, the theorizing of the liberals about citizenship that would make this scenario possible. It is this story we shall now tell.

In the liberal states, the strongest demand for inclusion in citizenship came from the urban working classes. Neither bourgeoisie nor proletariat are eternal essences. They were social creations, reflecting to be sure a certain social reality, but reified. And as with all such concepts, it was the dominant not the dominated stratum that began the process of reification, contrary to subsequent beliefs. Even before the July monarchy, Guizot elaborated the concept of class, a concept he had taken from Saint-Simon. He did this, of course, in order to justify the political role of the bourgeoisie as opposed to the aristocracy. But he did this as well, in order to situate the bourgeoisie (which he felt would in time assimilate the aristocracy) vis-à-vis the proletariat, and to distinguish between the two (Botrel and LeBouil 1973:143). If he was seeking droit de cité for the bourgeoisie, and ultimately total political control, he was specifically opposed to the inclusion of the proletariat. The droit de cité was to be reserved to active, that is, propertied, citizens.10

And when, later on, workers had achieved droit de cité, as in the Kaiserreich, theorists of enlightened conservatism did not lose sight of class as a basic component of political life. Steinmetz (1993, ch. 5) describes the rise of what he calls the “Bismarckian paradigm,” the basis of Germany's “worker policy,” which stemmed, he says, primarily “from the specific fear of the organized socialist movement” (p. 144).

As the bourgeoisie slowly became that much vaguer and more inclusive category of the “middle class” or “classes,” so eventually the proletariat evolved into that vaguer and more inclusive category of the “working class” or “classes.” There was a great deal of resistance to explicit class language by many politicians and social scientists, because the use of such language came to be identified with a particular political position, that of Marxism, and using it therefore came to signify for many people accepting Marxist analysis and politics.11

England has always been a notable exception to this queasiness about class language. Jones (1983:2) notes the unusual “pervasiveness . . . of class vocabulary” in England, and offers the following explanation: “Unlike Germany, languages of class in England never faced serious rivalry from a pre-existing language of estates; unlike France and America, republican vocabulary and notions of citizenship never became more than a minor current . . . ; unlike the countries of southern Europe, vocabularies of class did not accompany, but long preceded, the arrival of social democratic parties and were never exclusively associated with them.”

But the retreat to vaguer language did not eliminate the antinomy. If anything, it strengthened it, by making it easier for individuals to pass quietly over the line, while at the same time maintaining the line firmly. For those who passed, the important thing was that there be a line, one that might keep others from passing as well and thereby undermining the newly-acquired privileged position of full citizenship of those who managed to pass.

During all this time, as indeed throughout the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, “fear of the masses, the concern with order, was the motif . . . always underlying the actions of the ruling class” (Moorhouse 1973:346). The question always remained for the dominant strata as for the working classes: which tactics were optimal? From the point of view of the dominant strata, repression had its merits, but it also stoked the fire that was brewing, and eventually would breed revolt. So, in the late 1860s, both Napoleon III and the British Conservative Party felt the need to loosen the constraints, to make it more possible for there to be workers' organizations and perhaps to expand a bit the de facto definition of citizenship.

The situation would evolve in the last third of the nineteenth century. There seems to have been a considerable “radicalization” of class conflict, starting with the Paris Commune, and followed by the rise of socialist parties and trade-unions, at least in all the more industrialized, wealthier zones of the world- system. “In 1880 [socialist parties] barely existed. . . . By 1906 they were . . . taken for granted” (Hobsbawm 1987:116–17). But is now also a truism that, after 1890, there was a general deradicalization of these movements (Geary 1981:109), culminating in 1914 with the war votes of all the socialist parties (with the notable exception of the Bolsheviks).12

The ambiguous debates in the period immediately preceding the declarations of war are to be found in Haupt (1965). The essential point is that virtually all the parties promised to refuse participation in the war but, when war actually broke out, virtually everyone voted the war credits.

The picture that is offered us by most historical writing on the subject is one of a curve of militancy that went upward via popular mobilization and then downward via reformist sagacity (or betrayal, if one prefers that rhetoric). This is undoubtedly true in its crude outlines, although the upward part of the curve may never have been as great as some believe.13

As Michèle Perrot says of so-called revisionism among the socialists of late nineteenth-century France, “In order that there be a ’revision,' there first has to be something to revise” (1967:702).

The question is where lie the roots of this so-called radical political upsurge that, in the end (by 1914), no longer seemed to threaten any of the encrusted social structures of the modern world-system. It seems reasonable to interpret this as a clash about citizenship, that is, about who is to be included in the privileges and derived benefits of being designated the kind of citizen (active) who had these rights. It was a material issue, to be sure, but it was also a question of identity and identification. The narrowness of the prevailing definitions of real citizenship in the period 1815–1848 (justified by the premise that the workers were uneducated and propertyless, and therefore could have no reason to maintain social order) provoked a “world revolution,” which appalled the middle strata (since it threatened to go too far), and led to repression. When the pluses of repression were exhausted in twenty years, there came to be more political space for popular maneuver. On the one hand, the liberal center urged the “education” of the working classes. And on the other hand, the working classes pushed for their own “education.”

This is turn led to the creation of serious organizations which sought to force the pace of inclusion of at least the male, urban working classes. These organizations had to make their demands somewhat loudly in order to be taken seriously, both by the dominant classes and by those they were hoping to mobilize politically. Thus we heard a “radical” rhetoric. This rhetoric was effective, and the dominant strata reacted by various kinds of concessions—extension of the suffrage, the expansion of economic benefits (including the nascent welfare state), and inclusion in the “nation” via the exclusions resulting from racism and imperialism. Of course, this gave the results intended—the maintenance of the system in its major outlines, and the “moderation” of the workers' rhetoric. One does not need to intrude concepts of errors of judgment (false consciousness), self-interest of a leading, bureaucratic stratum (betrayal, the iron law of oligarchy), or the special interest of the better-paid workers (aristocracy of labor) to account for a process which seems more or less pandemic, more or less inevitable in retrospect, and which occurred in quite similar form throughout the world (the more industrialized, richer parts of the world) in the period 1870–1914, despite all the national variations in the details, variations that proved ultimately to be of minor importance.14

There is a sense in which the “radicalism” of the post-1870 period was actually a lot less radical in spirit than the “radicalism” of the pre-1848 period. As Jones (1983:237–38) puts it: “One of the most striking features of the social movements between 1790 and 1850 had been the clarity and concreteness of their conception of the state. . . . It had been seen as a flesh and blood machine of coercion, exploitation and corruption. . . . The triumph of the people would replace it by a popular democracy of a Leveller or Jacobin sort . . .” The concrete program however was “republicanism, secularism, popular self-education, co-operation, land reform, internationalism,” and all these themes had by now become part of the litany of the liberal center, at least of its more progressive flank. The late nineteenth-century movements would shift their emphasis “from power to welfare,” and with that, they were encased in a “defensive culture.” In a sense, however radical the post-1870 movements, they were less angry than the pre-1848 movements. The lure of the reward of citizenship was becoming too strong.

The period running from the 1870s to the First World War saw the first substantial organization of the working classes into political movements (primarily socialist and anarchist) and into trade-unions. It therefore became the period of a major debate about strategy. The question that preoccupied all those who organized was how the working classes might achieve their goals, and in particular how they should relate to the existing states and parliaments. This was the debate between Marxists and anarchists. The heart of it was that the anarchists regarded the state as an implacable enemy, with which there could be compromise, whereas the Marxists essentially had a two-stage theory of social transformation: obtain somehow state power, and then transform the world. There was the cross-cutting debate between so-called revolutionaries and so-called reformists, which came to divide the Marxist camp severely. These were real debates, and absorbed a good deal of organizational energy and time. What is striking, when one reviews the debates in the various countries, is how amazingly similar they were, despite all the important and oft-noted historical specificities of each national situation, and despite the differences in rhetorical labels which are usually used to describe them. In the end, however, these debates turned out often to be less consequential debates than people at the time and even since have usually assumed.

The “model party”15

The phrase “model party” is the title of chapter 3 of Haupt (1986), in which he discusses the influence of the SPD on the various parties of southeastern Europe. Victor Fay says that “the dream” of all the Russian socialists, including even the Bolsheviks, was “to transpose onto Russia soil the German model, both in terms of organization and in terms of the relations of trade unions to the party” (1981:187).

in the world social/labor movement would now be, up to the First World War, the German Social-Democratic Party (SPD). It was the most powerful party in the Second International. It was the only party with a true mass base. It was the party of the most intense theoretical debates. When in 1877, the SPD was able to get sixteen deputies elected to the German Reichstag, this resulted in increased repression (the anti-socialist laws of 1878) but at the same time in the deflation of the anarchist case (Ragionieri 1961:57–62), and in the acceptance at the Erfurt Congress in 1891 of Marxism as the official doctrine of the SPD.16

Schorske (1955:3) says that the German movement turned to Marxism in reaction to the “fury” that Bismarck had unleashed against them. “Marxism” as a doctrine was a product of the 1890s, “at the very moment when its exact nature began to be debated among the various tendencies and schools of Marxism” (Hobsbawm, 1974:242).

From this point forward, the SPD became the locus of the grand debate between Bernstein and Kautsky. How important was this theoretical debate? The result of the debate in the end was “radical theory and moderate practice” (Roth 1963:163). And the basis of it was “deterministic Marxism,” in its two variants (Bernstein and Kautsky).17

See Bebel at Erfurt (cited in Mathias 1971, I: 178): “The bourgeois society is striving vigorously toward its own destruction; we need only wait for the moment to seize power as it slips from their hands!” Marxism, as Hobsbawm reminds us, was not necessarily equated with “revolutionary” doctrine: “Between 1905 and 1914 the typical revolutionary in the west was likely to be some kind of revolutionary syndicalist who, paradoxically, rejected marxism as the ideology of parties which used it as an excuse for not trying to make revolution. This was a little unfair to the shades of Marx, for the striking thing about the western mass proletarian parties which ran up his banner on their flagpoles was how modest the role of Marx actually was in them. The basic beliefs of their leaders and militants were often indistinguishable from those of the non-Marxist working-class radical or jacobin left” (1987:134).

The key shift was not in the terminology, but in the fact that, from the 1870s on, the socialists began to demand protective legislation. After 1871, the working classes “entered into a close relationship with the nation-states” (van der Linden 1988:333). Nolan calls this a shift from “politics to social policy” (1986:386). In Germany, they were responding to “an agenda that Bismarck had set.” This had to lead over time to “a general integration of the working-class into the state” (Mathias 1971, I:181).18

Roth (1963:8, 315) calls this “negative integration,” which he defines as allowing “a hostile mass movement to exist legally, but prevent[ing] it from gaining access to the centers of power.” Kaiser Wilhelm I repealed the antisocialist legislation in 1890 and called for an international conference to promote international labor legislation (Ragionieri 1961:159). He gained the sobriquet of Arbeiterkaiser, by making various small “reformist concessions,” although he continued to vacillate by occasional “recourse to further repressive legislation” (Hall 1974:365). Roth wants to see this as quite different from what happened in Great Britain and the United States. I agree that the rhetoric was more strident in Germany, but were the ultimate results so different? Heywood (1990:ch. 1) calls the Spanish socialists “decaffeinated Marxists.” The Dutch party and trade-unions “were clearly moving in a reformist direction” (Hansen 1977:199). The Italian party pursued an “edulcorated version” of the program of the German SPD (Andreucci 1982:221), and its great expansion in 1901–1902 occurred “under the aegis of reformism” (Procacci 1972:163).

Everywhere the pattern is one of organizing with some difficulties in the light of state repression, rhetoric that is often radical combined with practice that is on the whole moderate, and a sort of “negative integration” into the national communities. In France, the heavy repression after the Commune eased up after 1875, the government recognizing the wisdom of a “social policy directed at the working class” (Schöttler 1985:58). In any case, all the parties seemed to follow the path of de facto reformism, that is, integration (even if negative) into the political structures of their respective countries.

As for the United States (and Canada), which Lipset (1983:14) insists are different because the absence of a feudal past “served to reduce the salience of class-conscious politics and proposals,” one merely needs to change a bit of the rhetoric to see the similarities. Herberg (cited in Dubofsky 1974:275) showed the degree to which the relationship of the IWW (“with its stress on proletarian direct action”) to the craft unionism of the AFL was parallel to the relationship of Bernstein's “reformism” to Kautsky's “orthodox Marxism.” Laslett (1974:115–16) makes the same point essentially about the American Socialist Party. Foner (1984:74), responding to the literature on “why is there no socialism in the U.S.?,” says that the question should really be posed as “why has there been no socialist transformation in any advanced capitalist society?” The most striking difference in the United States (and Canada) from the west European states was the ability of the Democratic Party in the United States (and the Liberal Party in Canada) to remain the prime vehicle of working-class politics (Shefter 1986:270; Kealey 1980:273), something which might be explained more by the role of the city machines in incorporating immigrant workers than by anything else.

What was crucial to all the social/labor movements in the end was their drive to participate in the nation. The workers regarded themselves as the working classes. The upper strata tended to think of them as the dangerous classes. A large part of the tactical struggle on the part of the workers revolved around how they could lose the label of “dangerous” and acquire that of citizens. In Germany, after 1871, the Social-Democrats had been accused on being “enemies of the nation” and “Vaterlandlose” (without a fatherland) (Groh 1966:17). They needed to overcome this label. One key, widely used mechanism was to distinguish between workers by the categories of ethnicity or of nationality. Racism internally and imperialism/colonialism externally served the function of displacing the label of dangerous to a subcategory of workers. To the extent that this was persuasive, some workers could become active citizens whilst others remained passive citizens or even non-citizens. Once again, inclusion was being achieved by exclusion.

The story of the feminist/women's movement in the nineteenth century is similar in very many ways to the story of the social/labor movement. There were of course a few voices who saw the two struggles as not merely compatible but intertwined. Flora Tristan in the pre-1848 period spent her life preaching this. She was, it must be said, a voice in the wilderness.19

As was Aline Vallette, disciple of Guesde, who wrote in L'Harmonie sociale on 15 March 1892 that “to renovate society, it is necessary that the two oppressed groups of society, women and proletarians, unite” (cited in Zylberberg-Hocquard 1978:89).

The problem, from the point of view of the male worker in urban wage-work, was quite straightforward. Women were paid less, before 1914 “considerably” less (Guilbert 1966:21), and this posed a threat to the level of wages in general. The issue was raised in meeting after meeting (Guilbert 1966:188). The First International was divided on the question. At the first congress in Geneva in 1866, the final resolution compromised by saying that women's work was to be regarded positively, but criticizing its conditions under capitalist production (Frei 1987:39). The workers' organizations would now push on three fronts: equality of wages, the family wage, and dangerous workplace conditions.

Equality of wages (for equal work) is a standard and obvious demand of trade unions. But it was frequently the secret hope that, if wages were made equal (for women, for minorities and immigrants, for workers in other countries), the hierarchically dominant worker (the male citizen worker of the ranking ethnic group) would then be employed in preference, if only for cultural-historical reasons.20

Notice, for example, the language of the resolution in the Ninth Congress of the French C.G.T. in Rennes in 1898: “That in all areas of life we seek to propagate the idea that the man must nourish the woman; that for the woman, widow or young girl, necessarily obliged to provide for herself, it shall be understood that the formula, for equal work equal pay, shall be applied to her. . . . Keep men from taking jobs and work that belong to women, and reciprocally, keep women from taking work away from men that are their natural province (cited in Guilbert 1966:173).

The “family wage” became a central demand of the trade-union structures. The family wage was a simple idea. The minimum wage an adult male should receive for his waged work should be a sum sufficient to sustain him, his wife, and his non-adult children. This concept had wide appeal. It was strongly endorsed by the labor movement (Lewis 1984:49). It appealed to many employers, since it seemed to promise stability of the work force (May 1982:418). It fit in with the nineteenth-century value of the “responsibility” of men to care for their family (Evans 1983:281). It appealed therefore not only to the labor movements but to centrist politicians of all stripes. Only feminists objected to the concept (Offen 1957:183).21

The same was more or less true about the concept of special “protective” legislation for women workers. Rowbotham (1977:114) says it was always a “thorny issue.” It seemed a virtuous idea, and it was long a preoccupation of the socialist movement (Guilbert 1966:413). Anarchists did not like it, because it involved government intervention. Middle-class feminists opposed it in the name of equality. The women workers themselves often feared that it would result in reduced wages. And, in fact, the socialist movement was somewhat divided. The Catholic Zentrum in Germany endorsed it as part of their search for a more social capitalism. For most male workers, it served as an alibi for their unwillingness to see an equal role for women in the workplace, and hence in political society.

From 1890–1920, feminists and socialists remained “at arm's length,” and indeed “became bitter enemies” (Kennedy and Tilly 1985:36). For working-class women the basic choice seemed always to be: “Sisters or citizens?” (Sowerwine 1982:1). And in the end, working-class women who were politically active were not allowed to refuse the choice.

The women's/feminist movement must not however be seen primarily through the prism of the social/labor movement. It had its own dynamic, albeit one that was parallel in many ways. Still, the story didn't really start with the women, but with the men. As O'Neill says of Victorian men (but was more generally true throughout the nineteenth-century European world), the men “taught women to think of themselves as a special class. . . . [They] created The Woman, where before there had only been women” (1971:6).

In 1848, feminism reasserted itself as part of the social revolution in France and elsewhere. But with the exception of a few tiny Communist groups, these demands were met by a “wave of puritanism” (Devance 1976:92). In the United States, the only expression of the world revolution was the Seneca Falls Convention, generally regarded as the founding moment of U.S. feminism. Its famous Declaration of Sentiments of 19–20 July 1848, echoing the Declaration of Independence, begins: “We hold these truths to be self-evident: that all men and women are created equal.” Among the grievances listed on 18 August were that women were deprived of “the first right of a citizen, elective franchise,” a franchise that was given (this complaint foreshadowing future conflicts) to “ignorant and degraded men—both natives and foreigners” (Rossi 1973:416).

In Europe, after the June Days in France, repression was severe, not merely of the socialists but of the feminists as well. This did not however draw the two “pariah” groups together. Rather, they would now go, for the most part, their separate organizational ways. The housewife had now become the dominant cultural image of the role the woman was supposed to play in the modern world. In the nineteenth century, the distinction between public and private spheres of life became central to the geoculture. It was being hailed as one of the great advances of modernity, and was the logical consequence of the demand for rationality, in which “good social organization” seemed to require “a stricter definition of spaces, roles and tasks” (Perrot 1986:35), which in turn “served as a justification for the assignment of personal characteristics and social roles to males and females” (Allen 1991:29). This has been called the “gendering of the public sphere” (Landes 1988:2).22

Nye (1993:47) asserts that this gendering of the public and private spheres became legally sanctioned in the period 1789–1815, and connects this with scientific theorizing: [A] biomedical model of male and female was constructed by medical scientists in this era that made the sexes ’naturally' suited for their respective social and familial roles. The sexed bodies that emerged from this process were so constituted as to be both ’opposite' and ’complementary.' Because the public and private spheres of the bourgeois cosmos were delineated so sharply from one another, only two wholly different beings could occupy them.”

Feminist movements were from the beginning caught in the conceptual dilemma that had been created for them. On the one hand, they were heirs to the universalist, and individualist, tradition enshrined in the French Revolution. But when they asked for their full rights as active citizens, they found these refused on grounds of their difference from men in some important ways. On the other hand, when they decided alternatively to seek “equality in difference,” they were fitting in with the “new scientific representation of the body” that saw male and female bodies “as a series of binary oppositions” which were incommensurable (Poovey 1988:6). In doing this, they were in effect acceding to their role as passive citizens, accepting if you will the role men had assigned themselves of “benevolent patriarchs” (Offen 1983:257).

Navigating the channel between Scylla and Charybdis was not, is not ever, easy, and it is rarely done successfully. Feminism had to make its way in a world in which sexism was not merely legitimate but openly and aggressively argued, and therefore had an impact on any and all potential allies.23

Rebérioux speaks of “the force of ’cultural' antifeminism common to all European societies in the nineteenth century and shared as well by the socialists: the [socialist] parties could function as the anti-State, but not as the anti-Society” (1978:154).

Neither the scholars24

In England, Herbert Spencer's early support for feminism (derived from his individualist ideas) was transformed into anti-feminism by his discovery of the principle of Darwinian selection (Paxton 1991). Michelet's La Femme (1981[1859]: 49) includes an incredibly sexist dialogue of two men about the limitations of women, who are “brought up to hate and disdain what all Frenchmen love and in which they believe”—that is, secular values, science, the Revolution of 1789.

nor the publicists nor the political leaders were of much help. The search for political integration into the states became virtually the only political issue of a movement that had an “overwhelmingly middle-class composition” (Evans 1977:34). How does one demand to be an active citizen? The answer seemed simple enough: organize, ask that laws be changed, lobby for these changes. And that is what feminists did. And if one asked why was it important to become a citizen? The answer would be parallel to the two-stage theory of Marxism: first the vote, then everything else.25

“Classical feminism . . . finally came to focus on the vote as the capstone of emancipation in the West. This does not mean that the vote was seen as the end of feminist aspirations. The evidence is clear enough that most feminists envisioned political equality as a means, a continuance of the emancipation process at a higher level: female voters would elect women; women would effect the desired reforms not only for their own sex (law, divorce, education, and the rest) but also (via an argument for female sensitivity that sometimes contradicted mainstream feminist rhetoric) contribute to national regeneration, and ensure the abolition of such evils as alcoholism, prostitution, and war” (Stites 1978:xviii). Bidelman sums up the viewpoint of French feminists thus: “without a permanent liberal answer to the ’first stage' political question, there could be no answer to the ’second stage' woman question” (1982:190). See the defense by Dubois of this strategy: “[I]t is a mistake to conclude that the women's suffrage movement was a useless distraction in women's struggle for liberation because the vote did not solve the problem of women's oppression. . . . It was the first independent movement of women for their own liberation” (1978:17–18).

The question was how to get the vote. It required organization, organization as women. The French feminists called the two possible alternative tactics the “politics of the breach” and the “politics of the assault.” The issue was whether to give priority to civil emancipation or to political emancipation (Bidelman 1982:chs. 3, 4). As a debate about tactics, this was not too different from the reformist-revolutionary debate among the German social-democrats. In general, the politics of the breach was dominant.26

“Almost everywhere, the radicals (i.e. above all those who demanded feminine suffrage) were a minority, often strongly opposed by the ’moderate' majority of feminists” (Evans 1977:37).

The usual explanation of the moderation of feminist movements is that they were dominated by middle-class women with bourgeois values (Hause with Kenney 1981:783; Rover 1967:61; Evans 1976:272). But some feminists did move on to more radical tactics. The aggressive tactics took hold particularly in Great Britain and the United States.27

“The [British] suffragettes smashed the image of woman as a passive, dependent creature as effectively as they smashed the plate-glass windows of Regent Street” (Rover 1967:20). Chafetz and Dworkin argue that it was precisely this militancy and “narrowing the issue to suffrage” that enabled the U.S. [and British] movements to achieve a “mass following” (1986:112). If this did not happen in France, Moses says, it was not because the French movement “burned itself out” but rather because “repressive governments repeatedly burned feminism” (1984:230).

The feminists who led the struggle for suffrage were faced with groups of organized women who placed other objectives ahead of suffrage, either as a goal or as a priority. The suffragists saw these other movements as essentially less militant, more socially conservative.28

The question is what is “conservative.” McLaren (1978b: 107) argues the ambiguities of the discussion on birth control: “The early birth control ideology was a curious amalgam. Its ’progressive' dimensions were exemplified by its interest in women's rights and medical self-help; its conservatism, by its adherence to neo-Malthusian economics.” And then the eugenicists entered the debate, and this “shifted attention from the rights of the mother to those of the state; from the quantity of the work force to its quality” (p. 154).

The social feminists were in fact as concerned with political questions (that is, questions of the law), as were the political feminists who concentrated on suffrage. For the law impinged on women's rights and possibilities in countless ways.29

The illegalization (as opposed to the social disapproval) of abortion was an early nineteenth-century action (Rendall 1985:226). And its legalization has been a women's issue ever since (McLaren 1978a; Evans 1977:108). So has been birth control. So was, especially in the United States, the issue of temperance, in which movement many suffragists participated. “Participation in the [Women's Temperance] Crusade by . . . suffragists was possible because an area of agreement existed between the two movements. Not only were both movements by and for women, but both also asserted women's right to be active in the public sphere” (Blocker 1985:471). And when German feminists argued for kindergarten education, it was in pursuit of their model of a liberal state, based on Rechtsstaat, “which required an active role for government not just in protecting individual freedoms but in positively encouraging a sense of community.” Kindergartens were thought to promote this goal “by stimulating the child's early instinct for self-activity” (Allen 1991:65).

We have seen that the social/labor movements had great difficulty in accepting the legitimacy of the women's/feminist movements in their demands for the rights of active citizenship. In a similar manner, the women's/feminist movements had great difficulties in accepting the legitimacy of the ethnic/racial movements in the latters' demands for the rights of active citizenship. It was as though there were not enough room on the ship to accommodate every one. Or perhaps the better metaphor is the unwillingness to accept the idea of a one-class ship—citizens all, citizens equal. In the nineteenth century, this second organizational conflict was to be found primarily in the United States, where the oppression of the Blacks played such a central role in political tensions and therefore gave rise to Black social movements.30

The struggle for Irish rights in Great Britain posed a parallel issue, except that it included a demand for political separation which was largely absent in the case of the Blacks in the United States.

The first formal exclusion of women from the vote was in the Reform Bill of 1832, which was intended to enfranchise some who did not have the franchise before. But in doing this, the bill specified “male persons,” a phrase that had never before been found in English legislation. This phrase “provided a focus of attack and a source of resentment,” (Rover 1967:3) out of which British feminism would grow. This was the kernel of the debate over the Thirteenth, Fourteenth, and Fifteenth Amendments to the U.S. Constitution following the end of the Civil War. President Lincoln had emancipated the slaves on 1 January 1863 (actually not quite all the slaves, but most of them). The Fourteenth Amendment, passed in 1868, said that if the right to vote were denied in any states to citizens over twenty-one who were “male inhabitants” of that state, the basis of representation of that state would be reduced in Congress. The feminists saw the Fourteenth Amendment as a “political setback” because, for the first time the word “male” was included, parallel to what had happened with the Reform Act of 1832. The women of course argued that extending the suffrage should be done for all that were excluded. But Wendell Phillips, one of the leaders of the U.S. abolitionist movement said in May 1865 that the demands of women's suffrage should not be pressed at the moment, for “this is the Negro's Hour.” The women suffragists did not stand by mute. Elizabeth Stanton and Susan B. Anthony supported the campaign of George Francis Train, a known racist, who however advocated women's suffrage.31

Frederick Douglass, the Black leader, denounced the association of Stanton and Anthony with Train (Dubois 1998:187). Hersh (1978:70) says it was only a “brief association.” But Dubois (1998:95–96) argues that “by turning to Train [Anthony and Stanton] gave substance to the charges of anti-feminist Republicans that the women's suffrage movement was a tool that the Democratic party used against the freedmen.” Douglass had long been a supporter of women's suffrage. He attended the Seneca Falls meeting in 1848 and he renewed his support in the 1870s. “But in the vital years of 1866–9 he withheld his support,” believing that adding women's suffrage to the package would endanger obtaining the vote for the freedmen, and that the latter was more vital and urgent (Evans 1977:48).

Not all women leaders took the Stanton-Anthony position.32

Lucy Stone argued that “if the women could not win their political freedom, it was well that the Negro men could win theirs” (Kraditor 1965:3).

The outcome was a profound split in the feminist movement. As the women's movement became more conservative on all social/labor issues in the second half of the nineteenth century, so did it on all ethnic/racial issues within countries (as in the United States)33

In the United States, “by the closing years of the century it was commonplace in the South for racist arguments to be used in support of women's suffrage” (Banks 1981:141).

or colonial issues (as in Great Britain).34

“[F]eminist argument, no less than imperialist apologia, was preoccupied with race preservation, racial purity, and racial motherhood. This was in part because it had to be. One of the most damaging attacks made against the case for female emancipation was that it would enervate the race” (Burton 1990:299).

In the course of this conservative shift, many feminists abandoned the natural rights argument. In the United States, they began to argue that women be given the vote “to balance the impact of the foreign born” (Berg 1978:269). When the National American Woman Suffrage Association (NAWSA) in 1903 came out for an “educational requirement” for the vote (to the notable but lonely dissent of Charlotte Perkins Gilman), they had shifted from campaigning to extend the franchise to a proposal “to take the vote away from some Americans—Negroes in the South and naturalized citizens in the North” (Kraditor 1965:137; see Flexner 1975:316).35

In a parallel way, the British feminist movement was divided on the issue of property qualifications for the vote (Banks 1981:133–34).

At the height of this tension, some suffragists resorted to crude racism. For example, they issued a poster of a “brutish-looking Negro porter sitting next to a refined-looking White lady” with a caption that read “He can vote; why can't I?” (Kraditor 1965:31).

If citizenship—that is, active citizenship—was difficult to achieve for workers and women, it was even more difficult for persons of color (or other groups defined by some status-group characteristic and treated as somehow inferior). The intellectual justification for this had been building up since the beginning of the capitalist world-economy (Poliakov et al. 1976:52). But it was only in the nineteenth century that the theme of superior and inferior “races” was constantly elaborated and considered by Whites to be virtually self-evident.36

“Beginning in the nineteenth century, . . . implicitly or explicitly, there was a rupture in humanity; groups ’are' and no longer have a mobile status” (Guillaumin 1972:25).

The racial divide was made almost inevitable from the beginning by the forms in which class ideology evolved (Balibar in Balibar and Wallerstein 1988:chs. 12, 13). When commoners asserted their rights to citizenship both in England and in France, one of the arguments they sometimes used was that the aristocrats were “strangers” and not of native origin. This was the theory of the Norman Yoke, put forward in England since the seventeenth century37

The theory of the Norman Yoke is that the Norman conquest of 1066 deprived the Anglo-Saxon inhabitants of their heritage as “free and equal citizens” and that the struggle of the people was to reconquer ancient rights. On the Great Seal of the Commonwealth, created in 1651, was the inscription that freedom was “by God's will restored.” As Hill notes, this theory “also stirred far profounder feelings of English patriotism and English Protestantism. Herein lay its strength” (1958:67).

and the theory of the distinction between the “race gauloise” and the “race franque” in France, which had been bruited for some time but became prominent during the French Revolution.38

During the French Revolution, the “race gauloise” became identified with the bourgeoisie (and hence with the “people”) and the “race franque” with the “aristocracy” (Poliakov et al. 1976:69). They cite the earlier arguments of Boulainvilliers, Montesquieu, and the Comte de Montlosier. And Guizot later explicitly used this distinction as part of his effort to justify the French Revolution for the cause of his version of liberalism and the bourgeoisie (Poliakov 1974:32).

A parallel argument emerged in Italy with Etruscomania (Poliakov 1974:65–66). But if the aristocrats were to be excluded from active citizenship on the grounds of their foreign origins, how much more obviously would persons of color be so excluded? Jus sanguinis as opposed to jus soli is by definition exclusionary and inevitably racist.39

Still, if there existed the theme of the racial superiority of commoners, there was of course an even stronger one of aristocratic “blue blood” and its natural rights. “The dreams of racism actually have their origin in the ideology of class, rather than in those of nation: above all in claims to divinity among rulers and to ’blue' or ’white' blood and ’breeding' among aristocrats. No surprise then that the putative sire of modern racism should not be some petty-bourgeois but Joseph Arthur, comte de Gobineau” (Anderson 1991:149).

If race became a theorized concept in the nineteenth century, and racism an institutionalized practice, it was the result primarily of the centrality of the concept of citizenship. For citizenship as a concept had two logical consequences. It led states to emphasize and to predicate and insist on homogeneity as the only sound basis on which to justify the theoretical equality of all citizens. And it led states to justify their political domination of other states on the grounds that their particular homogeneous quality incarnated a higher degree of civilization than that of the dominated state, equally homogeneous but inferior.

The organic quality of the nation is inherent in what we have come to call Jacobinism, the key concept of which is that there should exist no intermediary bodies between the state and the individual. All individuals being equal, they have no public (or state-relevant) qualities other than that of being a citizen. Groups, however formed, no matter what their basis, do not have legal or moral standing as such. It would not be difficult or even illogical to transform the concept of organic qualities into different ones for each nation, and more generally, for the civilized (European) nations taken together versus all the others. The slide from a created homogeneity to a culturo-genetic organic reality, which could not be easily changed, was not difficult either.40

A good example is that of Gustave Le Bon who, in his 1886 work on race psychology, defined the greatest danger to the organic nation as that of assimilation—of criminals, of women, of ethnic groups, of colonials (Nye 1975:49–50).

Thus did we go from an organic whole that legitimated the equality of all citizens to an organic reality that justified a hierarchy among these citizens. Once again, from citizens all to an active/passive distinction. At which point, those excluded had the choice of insisting on inclusion or embracing the negatives—as angry riposte, rhetorical ploy, or organizer of identification.

The nineteenth century was the apogee of Europe in the world. “[N]ever did white men of European descent dominate [the world] with less challenge” (Hobsbawm 1975:135).41

Hobsbawm specifies the moment as the third quarter of the nineteenth century. This view of an apogee was shared by one of the major racist books of the twentieth century, The Rising Tide of Color against White World-Supremacy, by Lothrop Stoddard, who said: “1900 . . . was the high-water mark of the white tide which had been flooding for four hundred years. At that moment the white man stood on the pinnacle of his prestige and power. Pass four short years, and the flash of Japanese guns across the murky waters of Port Arthur revealed to a startled world the beginning of the ebb” (1920:153).

This was based on their military power, no doubt, but it was secured by their ideological constructs. “Europe had been ’Europeanized' by the construction of a unifying grid of civilization, against which all other cultures could be measured and classified” (Woolf 1992:89). As the states sought to create homogeneous nations of citizens, they simultaneously sought to create a White (European) race, in the “crusade against the backward areas of the world” that had already been advocated by Saint-Simon (Manuel 1956:195). The concept of a racial hierarchy received the legitimation of science, itself the great cultural icon of the nineteenth century. Science did this by the “confusion of sociological reality and biological reality,” (Guillaumin 1972:24),42

She notes how this confusion was a new phenomenon of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. In the eighteenth century, “evolution [was] a phenomenon internal to the social mechanism” and the origin of differences was “either geographical, or psychological, or pure social mechanism, but in all cases foreign to biology” (pp. 24–25). Similarly, Lewis argues: “When all of its limitations have been noted it remains true the [the] reputation [of the eighteenth century] as the ’age of reason' was not an empty one. It was ready and eager to look at non-European peoples in a spirit of genuine curiosity. It no doubt tended to romanticize these peoples. . . . But it was willing to listen to black and brown voices, and to recognize that there were cultural and spiritual values in the non-European civilizations absent in Europe” (1978:74–75). What intervened was the universalism of the French Revolution and the dilemmas of citizenship.

Poliakov et al. (1976:67) also date the moment of shift of emphasis as that of the French Revolution. The reverse side of the principles of liberty, equality, and fraternity, scarcely noticed at the time they say, was “the new scientific mentality [which] tended to emphasize the determining character of biological elements. It substituted for ancient religious and cultural classifications new ones derived from observing physical characteristics (skin color, etc.). The latter were considered to be unchangeable, and affected, it was thought, the behavior of the individuals in question.” To be sure, Poliakov also says that racism “in its modern form, as a value-judgment bailed out by science, goes back to the eighteenth century” (1978:74–75).

Jordan notes the same shift in the United States: “What seems particularly to make the debate on the Negro's nature different after the Revolution than before was the rapid growth in Europe and America after 1775 of interest in anatomical investigation of human differences” and “the widespread interest in elucidating these differences with scalpels and calipers” (1968:xiii).

egregious for avowed racists like Gobineau but equally evident, if in milder form, among centrist liberals.43

“The true extent of scientific racism can best be grasped through its appeal to what is not normally seen as its constituency, namely to the liberals among the scientists” (Barkan 1992:177). He cites specifically Julian Huxley and Herbert Spencer. Poliakov (1982:55–56) speaks of the role of Voltaire, Kant, and Buffon in laying the groundwork for such ideas. Voltaire, the great symbol of civil liberties in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, was explicitly anti-Black and anti-Jewish.

As the European powers moved into a more active imperial expansion in the late nineteenth century, the racist ideas that had previously supported slavery were “dressed up in a new pseudo-scientific garb and given a popular mass appeal” (Davis 1993:73). The concept of the Aryan now became the justification of European domination of the non-European world. The concept of the Aryan then met up with the concept of the Oriental.

Racist theorizing bred anti-racist movements. But it must be admitted that such movements were in fact quite weak in the nineteenth century, much weaker than the social/labor movements and the women's/feminist movements. And, in the end, they got even less support from the liberal center than did the other kinds of movements. In part, this may reflect the even greater strength of racist ideology than of ideologies of bourgeois or male dominance. In part, it reflected the numerical weakness of those at the bottom of the racial hierarchy in Western countries. The only country of which this was not true was the United States, precisely where racist ideology was most deeply rooted, because it was the country first of slavery and later of Jim Crow.

The difficulty of the centrist liberals in confronting racism was their acceptance, fundamentally, of the active/passive distinction, which they framed as the difference between the inherent potential of all humans to be civilized (hence active citizens) and the current level of those who had not yet achieved their potential (hence passive citizens). They assumed that those with potential would take “generations—even centuries—to catch up, even given the most careful, paternalistic attention from benevolent Anglo-Saxons” (Bederman 1995:123).44

Lasch points out that, in the debate about the acquisition of the Philippines by the United States, the difference between the imperialist and anti-imperialist camp did not revolve around different views on equality, but merely that the anti-imperialists “refused to believe that [Anglo-Saxon] destiny required such strenuous exertions of the American people, particularly when they saw in these exertions the menace of militarism and tyranny” (1958:321).

Difference and inequalities of persons of different social origins—orders (Estates), class, gender, race, and education—were not invented in the nineteenth century. They had long existed and had been considered natural, inevitable, and indeed desirable. What was new in the nineteenth century was the rhetorical legitimacy of equality and the concept of citizenship as the basis of collective governance. This led as we have seen to the theorizing of the binary distinctions, the attempt to freeze them logically, to make de facto transiting across the boundaries not merely against the rules of society but against the rules of science. What was new as well was the social movements created by all those excluded by these binary reifications in order to secure their liberation, or at least a partial liberation, from the legal constraints. Each success of a particular group seemed to make easier by example and more difficult in practice the attempts of the next claimants of liberation. Citizenship always excluded as much as it included.

Footnotes

E. P. Thompson Memorial Lecture, University of Pittsburgh, 18 April 2002. This article was written while I was at the Netherlands Institute of Advanced Study in the Humanities and the Social Sciences (NIAS) at Wassenaar as Guest of the Rector in 2002. I wish to record my gratitude to the Rector and staff of NIAS for the wonderful and productive atmosphere, intellectual and social, which they provide to make possible the work of the Fellows.

References

Abray Jane 1975 Feminism in the French Revolution, American Historical Review 50 1 43 62Google Scholar
Allen Ann Taylor 1991 Feminism and Motherhood in Germany, 1800–1914. New Brunswick. N.J. Rutgers University Press
Anderson Benedict 1991 Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism, rev. ed. London Verso
Andreucci Franco 1982 The Diffusion of Marxism in Italy During the Late Nineteenth Century. R. Samuel and G. S. Jones Culture, Ideology, and Politics: Essays for Eric Hobsbawm London Routledge and Kegan Paul 214–27
Balibar Etienne Immanuel Wallerstein 1988 Race, nation, classe: Identités ambigües. Paris La Découverte
Banks Olive 1981 Faces of Feminism. A Study of Feminism as a Social Movement. Oxford Martin Robertson
Barkan Elazar 1992 The Retreat of Scientific Racism: Changing Concepts of Race in Britain and the United States between the World Wars. Cambridge Cambridge University Press
Bederman Gail 1995 Manliness and Civilization: A Cultural History of Gender and Race in the United States, 1880–1917. Chicago University of Chicago Press
Berg Barbara J 1978 The Remembered Gate: Origins of American Feminism. The Woman and the City, 1800–1860. New York Oxford University Press
Bidelman Patrick K 1982 Pariahs Stand Up! The Founding of the Liberal Feminist Movement in France, 1858–1889. Westport, Conn. Greenwood Press
Blackburn Robin 1988 The Overthrow of Colonial Slavery, 1776–1848. London Verso
Blocker Jack S. Jr 1985 Separate Paths: Suffragists and the Women's Temperance Crusade, Signs 10 3 (Spring) 460–76Google Scholar
Botrel J.-F. J. Le Bouil 1973 Sur le concept de ’clase media' dans la pensée bourgeoise en Espagne au XIXe siècle. La Question de la ’bourgeoisie' dans le monde hispanique au XIXe siècle Bibliothèque de l'Ecole des Hautes Etudes Hispaniques, fasc. XLV. Bordeaux Ed. Bière 137–51 [with discussion, 152–60]
Bruhat Jean 1972 “Le socialisme français de 1848 à 1871.” In J. Droz, dir., Histoire générale du socialisme, I. Des origines à 1875 Paris Presses University de France 501–34
Burton Antoinette M 1990 The White Woman's Burden: British Feminists and the Indian Woman, 1865–1915, Women's Studies International Forum 13 4 295 308Google Scholar
Cerati Marie 1966 Le club des citoyennes républicaines révolutionnaires. Paris Ed. Sociales
Chafetz Janet Saltzman Anthony Gary Dworkin 1986 Female Revolt: Women's Movements in World and Historical Perspective. Totowa, N.J. Rowman and Littlefield
Davis Mary 1993 Comrade or Brother?: A History of the British Labour Movement, 1789–1951. London Pluto Press
Devance Louis 1976 Femme, famille, travail et monde sexuelle dans l'idéologie de 1848, Romantisme 13–14 79 103Google Scholar
Dubofsky Melvin 1974 Socialism and Syndicalism. J. Laslett and S. M. Lipset Failure of a Dream? Essays in the History of American Socialism Garden City, N.Y. Anchor 252–85
DuBois Ellen Carol 1978 Feminism and Suffrage: The Emergence of an Independent Women's Movement in America, 1848–1869. Ithaca, N.Y. Cornell University Press
Ellis John 1974 Revolutionary Trends in Europe: A Historical Introduction, M. Elliott-Bateman, et al. Revolt to Revolution: Studies in the 19th and 20th Century European Experience Manchester Manchester University Press 31 57
Evans Eric J 1983 The Forging of the Modern State: Early Industrial Britain, 1783–1870. London Longman
Evans Richard J 1976 The Feminist Movement in Germany, 1894–1933. London, Beverly Hills Sage Publications
Evans Richard J 1977 The Feminists: Women's Emancipation Movements in Europe, America and Australasia, 1840–1920. London Croom Helm
Fay Victor 1981 In Madeleine Rebérioux et al., Jaurès et la classe ouvrière Paris Ed. Ouvrières 187–88
Flexner Eleanor 1975 A Century of Struggle. The Women's Rights Movement in the United States, rev. ed. Cambridge, Mass Belknap Press
Foner Eric 1984 Why is There No Socialism in the United States? History Workshop 17 (Spring) 57 80Google Scholar
Frei Annette 1987 Rote Patriarchen: Arbeiterbewegung und Frauen emanzipation in der Schweiz um 1900. Zurich Chronos
Geary Dick 1981 European Labour Protest, 1848–1939. London Croom Helm
George Margaret 1976–1977 The ’World Historical Defeat' of the Républicaines-Révolutionnaires, Science and Society 40 4 (Winter) 410–37Google Scholar
Groh Dieter 1966 The ’Unpatriotic' Socialists and the State, Journal of Contemporary History 1 4 (Oct.) 151–78Google Scholar
Gueniffey Patrice 1988a Introduction au texte et notes. A. Barnave De la Révolution et de la Constitution Grenoble Presses University de Grenoble 31 38 [and “notes,” passim]
Gueniffey Patrice 1988b Suffrage. F. Furet and M. Ozouf Dictionnaire critique de la Révolution française Paris Flammarion 614–24
Guilbert Madeleine 1966 Les femmes et l'organisation syndicale avant 1914. Paris Ed. du CNRS
Guillaumin Colette 1972 L'idéologie raciste. Genèse et langage actuel. Paris-La Haye Mouton
Hall Alex 1974 By Other Means: The Legal Struggle against the SPD in Wilhelmine Germany, 1890–1900, Historical Journal 42 2 (June) 365–86Google Scholar
Hansen Erik 1977 Workers and Socialists: Relations between the Dutch Trade-Union Movement and Social Democracy, 1894–1914, European Studies Review 7 2 (Apr.) 199 225Google Scholar
Haupt Georges 1965 Le Congrès manqué: L'Internationale à la veille de la première guerre mondiale. Paris François Maspéro
Haupt Georges 1986 Aspects of International Socialism, 1871–1914: Essays. Cambridge Cambridge University Press
Hause Steven C. Anne R. Kenney 1981 The Limits of Suffragist Behavior: Legalism and Militancy in France, 1876–1922, American Historical Review 61 4 (Oct.) 781 806Google Scholar
Hause Steven C. 1984 Women's Suffrage and Social Politics in the French Third Republic. Princeton, N.J. Princeton University Press
Hersh Blanche Glassman 1978 The Slavery of Sex: Feminist-Abolitionists in America. Urbana University of Illinois Press
Heywood Paul 1990 Marxism and the Failure of Organised Socialism in Spain, 1879–1936. Cambridge Cambridge University Press
Hill Christopher 1958 The Norman Yoke, Puritanism and Revolution: Studies in Interpretation of the English Revolution of the Seventeenth Century London Secker and Warburg 50 122
Hobsbawm Eric J 1974 La diffusione del Marxismo (1890–1905), Studi Storici 40 2 241–69Google Scholar
Hobsbawm Eric J 1975 The Age of Capital, 1848–1875. London Weidenfeld and Nicolson
Hobsbawm Eric J 1987 The Age of Empire, 1875–1914. New York Pantheon
Jones Gareth Stedman 1983 Languages of Class: Studies in English Working Class History, 1832–1982. Cambridge Cambridge University Press
Jordan Winthrop D 1968 White over Black: American Attitudes toward the Negro, 1550–1812. Chapel Hill, N.C. University of North Carolina Press
Kealey Gregory S 1980 Toronto Workers Respond to Industrial Capitalism, 1867–1892. Toronto University of Toronto Press
Kennedy Marie Chris Tilly 1985 At Arm's Length: Feminism and Socialism in Europe, 1890–1920, Radical America 19 4 35 51Google Scholar
Kocka Jürgen 1986 Problems of Working-Class Formation in Germany: The Early Years, 1800–1875. I. Katznelson and A. R. Zolberg Working-Class Formation: Nineteenth-Century Patterns in Western Europe and the United States Princeton, N.J. Princeton University Press 279 351
Kraditor Aileen S 1965 The Ideas of the Woman Suffrage Movement, 1890–1920. New York Columbia University Press
Landes Joan B 1988 Women and the Public Sphere in the Age of the French Revolution. Ithaca, N.Y. Cornell University Press
Lasch Christopher 1958 The Anti-Imperialists, the Philippines, and the Inequality of Man, Journal of Southern History 24 3 (Aug.) 319–31Google Scholar
Laslett John H. M 1974 Comment [on Danie1 Bell]. J. Laslett and S. M. Lipset Failure of a Dream? Essays in the History of American Socialism Garden City, N.Y. Anchor 112–23
Lehning Arthur 1970 From Buonarotti to Bakunin: Studies in International Socialism. Leiden E. J. Brill
Levy, Darline Gay et al. 1979 Women in Revolutionary Paris, 1789–1795: Selected Documents. Urbana University of Illinois Press
Lewis Gordon K 1978 Slavery, Imperialism, and Freedom: Studies in English Radical Thought. New York Monthly Review Press
Lewis Jane 1984 Women in England 1870–1950: Sexual Divisions and Social Change. Brighton Wheatsheaf Books
Lichtheim George 1969 The Origins of Socialism. London Weidenfeld and Nicolson
Lipset S. M 1983 Radicalism or Reformism: The Sources of Working-Class Politics, American Political Science Review 77 1 (Mar.) 1 18Google Scholar
Manuel Frank E 1956 The New World of Henri Saint-Simon. Cambridge, Mass. Harvard University Press
Mathias Eric 1971 The Social Democratic Working-Class Movement and the German National State up to the End of World War I. Mouvements nationaux d'indépendance et classes populaires aux XIXe et XXe siècles en Occident et en Orient Paris Armand Colin, I 175–83
May Martha 1982 The Historical Problem of the Family Wage: The Ford Motor Company and the Five Dollar Day, Feminist Studies 8 2 (Summer) 399 424Google Scholar
McLaren Angus 1978a Abortion in France: Women and the Regulation of Family Size, 1800–1914, French Historical Studies 19 3 (Spring) 461–85Google Scholar
McLaren Angus 1978b Birth Control in Nineteenth-Century England. London Croom Helm
Michelet Jules 1981 [1859] La Femme. Paris Flammarion
Moorhouse H. F 1973 The Political Incorporation of the British Working Class: An Interpretation, Sociology 7 3 (Sept.) 341–59Google Scholar
Moses Claire Goldberg 1984 French Feminism in the Nineteenth Century. Albany State University of New York Press
Moses Wilson J 1978 The Golden Age of Black Nationalism, 1850–1925. Hamden, Conn. Archon
Nolan Mary 1986 Economic Crisis, State Policy, and Working-Class Formation in Germany, 1870–1900. I. Katznelson and A. Zolberg Working Class Formation: Nineteenth-Century Patterns on Western Europe and the United States Princeton Princeton University Press 352–93
Nye Robert Allen 1975 The Origins of Crowd Psychology: Gustave Le Bon and the Crisis of Mass Democracy in the Third Republic. London Sage
Nye Robert Allen 1993 Masculinity and Male Codes of Honor in Modern France. New York Oxford University Press
Offen Karen 1957 Feminism, Antifeminism, and National Family Politics in Early Third Republic France. M. Boxer and J. Quataert Connecting Spheres: Women in the Western World, 1500 to the Present New York Oxford University Press 177–86
Offen Karen 1983 The Second Sex and the Baccalauréat in Republican France, 1880–1924, French Historical Studies 13 2 (Fall) 252–86Google Scholar
O'Neill William L 1971 Everyone Was Brave: A History of Feminism in America, with a new Afterword by the Author. New York Quadrangle
Paxton Nancy L 1991 George Eliot and Herbert Spencer: Feminism, Evolution, and Reconstruction of Gender. Princeton Princeton University Press
Perrot Michelle 1967 Les Guesdistes: Controverses sur l'introduction du marxisme en France, Annales E.S.C 22 3 (mai-juin) 701–10Google Scholar
Perrot Michelle 1986 On the Formation of the French Working-Class. I. Katznelson and A. R. Zolberg Working-Class Formation: Nineteenth-Century Patterns in Western Europe and the United States Princeton, N.J. Princeton University Press 71 110
Poliakov Léon 1974 The Aryan Myth: A History of Racist and Nationalist Ideas in Europe. London Sussex University Press
Poliakov Léon 1982 Racism from the Enlightenment to the Age of Imperialism. Robert Ross Racism and Colonialism: Essays on Ideology and Social Structure The Hague Martinus Nijhoff 55 64
Poliakov Léon Christian Delacampagne Patrick Girard 1976 Le racisme. Paris Ed. Seghers
Poovey Mary 1988 Uneven Developments: The Ideological Work of Gender in Mid-Victorian England. Chicago University of Chicago Press
Procacci Giuliano 1972 La lotta di classe in Italia agli inizii del secolo XX. Roma Ed. Riuniti
Ragionieri Ernesto 1961 Socialdemocrazia tedesca e socialisti italiani, 1875–1895. Milano Feltrinelli
Rebérioux Madeleine 1978 ”Préface,” to Charles Sowerwine, Les femmes et le socialisme Paris Presses de la FNSP xi xxiii
Rendall Jane 1985 The Origins of Modern Feminism: Women in Britain, France and the United States, 1780–1860. London Macmillan
Rosanvallon Pierre 1985 Le Moment Guizot. Paris Gallimard
Rossi, Alice 1973 The Feminist Papers, from Adams to de Beauvoir. New York Columbia University Press
Roth Guenther 1963 The Social Democrats in Imperial Germany: A Study in Working-Class Isolation and National Integration. Totowa, N.J. Bedminster Press
Rover Constance 1967 Women's Suffrage and Party Politics in Britain, 1866–1914. London Routledge and Kegan Paul
Rowbotham Sheila 1977 Hidden from History: 300 Years of Women's Oppression and the Fight Against It, 3d ed. London Pluto Press
Saville John 1990 1848: The British State and the Chartist Movement. Cambridge Cambridge University Press
Schorske Carl E 1955 German Social Democracy, 1905–1917: The Development of the Great Schism. Cambridge, Mass. Harvard University Press
Schöttler Peter 1985 Naissance des Bourses de travail: Un appareil idéologique d'état à la fin du XIXe siècle. Paris Presses University de France
Scott Joan Wallach 1989 French Feminists and the Rights of ’Man': Olympe de Gouge's Declarations, History Workshop Journal 28 (Autumn) 1 21Google Scholar
Sheehan James J 1971 Liberalism and the City in Nineteenth-Century Germany, Past and Present 51 (May) 116–37Google Scholar
Shefter Martin 1986 Trade Unions and Political Machines: The Organization and Disorganization of the American Working Class in the Late Nineteenth Century. I. Katznelson and A. Zolberg Working Class Formation: Nineteenth-Century Patterns in Western Europe and North America Princeton Princeton University Press 197 278
Siéyès Emmanuel-Joseph 1789 Préliminaire de la Constitution, lu les 20 et 21 juillet 1789, au Comité de Constitution. Receuil des pièces authentiques approuvés par l'Assemblée Nationale de France Genève I 178 200Google Scholar
Sowerwine Charles 1982 Sisters or Citizens? Women and Socialism in France since 1876. Cambridge Cambridge University Press
Steinmetz George 1993 Regulating the Social: The Welfare State and Local Politics in Imperial Germany. Princeton Princeton University Press
Stites Richard 1978 The Women's Liberation Movement in Russia: Feminism, Nihilism, and Bolshevism, 1860–1930. Princeton Princeton University Press
Stoddard Lothrop 1920 The Rising Tide of Color Against White World-Supremacy. New York Charles Scribner's Sons
Thompson E. P 1997 The Romantics: England in a Revolutionary Age. New York New Press
Van der Linden Marcel 1988 The Rise and Fall of the First International: An Interpretation. F. Holthoon and M. van der Linden Internationalism in the Labour Movement, 1830–1940 Leiden E. J. Brill, I 323–35
Wallerstein Immanuel 1989 The Modern World-System. III: The Second Era of Great Expansion of the Capitalist World-Economy, 1730–1840s. San Diego, Calif. Academic Press
Wallerstein Immanuel 1995 Three Ideologies or One? The Pseudo-Battle of Modernity. After Liberalism New York New Press 72 92
Wallerstein Immanuel et al. 1996 Open the Social Sciences: Report of the Gulbenkian Commission on the Restructuring of the Social Sciences. Stanford Stanford University Press
Ware Vron 1992 Beyond the Pale: White Women, Racism, and History. London Verso
Willard Claude 1978 Socialisme et communisme français, nouv. éd. revue. Paris Armand Colin
Woolf Stuart 1989 French Civilization and Ethnicity in the Napoleonic Empire, Past and Present 124 (Aug.) 96 120Google Scholar
Woolf Stuart 1992 The Construction of a European World-View in the Revolutionary-Napoleonic Years, Past & Present 137 (Nov.) 72 101Google Scholar
Zylberberg-Hocquard Marie-Hélène 1978 Féminisme et syndicalisme en France. Paris Anthropos