Crossref Citations
This article has been cited by the following publications. This list is generated based on data provided by
Crossref.
Johnson, David J.
and
Chopik, William J.
2019.
Geographic Variation in the Black-Violence Stereotype.
Social Psychological and Personality Science,
Vol. 10,
Issue. 3,
p.
287.
King, Rachel Ann
Scott, Katharine E.
Renno, Maggie P.
and
Shutts, Kristin
2020.
Counterstereotyping can change children’s thinking about boys’ and girls’ toy preferences.
Journal of Experimental Child Psychology,
Vol. 191,
Issue. ,
p.
104753.
Vasilyeva, Nadya
and
Lombrozo, Tania
2020.
Structural thinking about social categories: Evidence from formal explanations, generics, and generalization.
Cognition,
Vol. 204,
Issue. ,
p.
104383.
Westra, Evan
2020.
When is mindreading accurate? A commentary on Shannon Spaulding’s
How We Understand Others: Philosophy and Social Cognition
.
Philosophical Psychology,
Vol. 33,
Issue. 6,
p.
868.
Roberts, Steven O.
2022.
Descriptive-to-prescriptive (D2P) reasoning: An early emerging bias to maintain the status quo.
European Review of Social Psychology,
Vol. 33,
Issue. 2,
p.
289.
Cella, Federico
Marchak, Kristan A.
Bianchi, Claudia
and
Gelman, Susan A.
2022.
Generic Language for Social and Animal Kinds: An Examination of the Asymmetry Between Acceptance and Inferences.
Cognitive Science,
Vol. 46,
Issue. 12,
Lee, Kent M.
Lindquist, Kristen A.
and
Payne, B. Keith
2023.
Constructing Explicit Prejudice: Evidence From Large Sample Datasets.
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin,
Vol. 49,
Issue. 4,
p.
541.
Connelly, Brian S.
and
McAbee, Samuel T.
2024.
Reputations at Work: Origins and Outcomes of Shared Person Perceptions.
Annual Review of Organizational Psychology and Organizational Behavior,
Vol. 11,
Issue. 1,
p.
251.
Neufeld, Eleonore
Bosse, Anne
Del Pinal, Guillermo
and
Sterken, Rachel
2025.
Giving Generic Language Another Thought.
WIREs Cognitive Science,
Vol. 16,
Issue. 1,
Jussim is doing psychology a service by prompting careful thinking about a number of topics in his book Social Perception and Social Reality (Jussim Reference Jussim2012). We will focus our comments on his arguments about stereotypes, which he defines as “beliefs about the attributes of social groups” (Précis target article, sect 8.2, para. 1). Going against the seeming consensus in social psychology, Jussim suggests that stereotypes are largely accurate. Here, we unpack this claim using a conceptual distinction from the cognitive psychology of concepts (used widely in linguistics and philosophy as well): namely, the distinction between generic and statistical beliefs about a category (e.g., Carlson & Pelletier Reference Carlson and Pelletier1995; Cimpian et al. Reference Cimpian, Brandone and Gelman2010; Leslie et al. Reference Leslie, Khemlani and Glucksberg2011; Prasada Reference Prasada2000). Attending to this distinction allows a more precise analysis of the claim that stereotypes are accurate – an analysis that ultimately undermines this claim. As we explain below, if one defines stereotypes as generic beliefs about groups, then the evidence Jussim presents (all of which pertains to people's statistical estimates about various group attributes) is largely irrelevant to their accuracy. By virtue of their very structure, generic beliefs have only a weak relation to the statistical criteria that Jussim uses to define accuracy. On the other hand, if one defines stereotypes as statistical beliefs about groups, then one may no longer be speaking to the bulk of social judgments. The literature on concepts suggests it is generic – not statistical – beliefs that people use most readily when reasoning about categories and their members. Thus, regardless of how one unpacks Jussim's claims on this topic, the accuracy of people's judgments about groups is still in doubt. In what follows, we first outline the distinction between generic and statistical beliefs and then proceed to discuss its implications for Jussim's arguments.
1. The distinction between generic and statistical beliefs about categories
To begin, consider the statements below:
1. Fewer than 1% of mosquitoes carry the West Nile virus.
2. Mosquitoes carry the West Nile virus.
3. The majority of books are paperbacks.
4. Books are paperbacks.
Statements (1a) and (2a) are statistical: They express a belief about a certain number or proportion of the members of a category. Statements (1b) and (2b) are generic: They express a belief about the category as a whole rather than a specific number, quantity, or proportion. (An easy way to check the latter claim is to try out each of these statements as an answer to a “How many?” question. Only the statistical statements will sound appropriate.)
The fact that generic claims – and the beliefs they express – are not about numbers or quantities has a crucial consequence: It severs their truth conditions from the sort of statistical data that one could objectively measure in the world. In other words, whether people judge a generic belief about a category to be true does not straightforwardly depend on how many members of that category display the relevant attribute. This point is illustrated by the examples above. Both (1a) and (1b) are considered true: Although very few mosquitoes actually carry the West Nile virus, participants judge the generic claim (that mosquitoes,Footnote 1 as a category, carry the West Nile virus) to be true as well (e.g., Prasada et al. Reference Prasada, Khemlani, Leslie and Glucksberg2013). In contrast, even though (2a) is true – paperbacks are indeed very common – few believe that books, as a category, are paperbacks (i.e., [2b] is false). Notably, these are not isolated examples. The literature is replete with instances of generic claims that either are judged true despite unimpressive statistical evidence or judged false despite overwhelming numbers (e.g., Carlson & Pelletier Reference Carlson and Pelletier1995; Leslie Reference Leslie2007; Reference Leslie2008). In fact, the rules that govern which generic beliefs are deemed true and which are deemed false are so baroque and so divorced from the statistical facts that many linguists and philosophers have spent the better part of 40 years debating them (e.g., Carlson & Pelletier Reference Carlson and Pelletier1995; Lawler Reference Lawler1973; Leslie Reference Leslie2008).
Importantly, all of the foregoing applies to beliefs about social groups as well (e.g., Cimpian & Markman Reference Cimpian and Markman2011; Cimpian et al. Reference Cimpian, Mu and Erikson2012; Gelman et al. Reference Gelman, Taylor and Nguyen2004; Leslie Reference Leslie2008; in press; Prasada & Dillingham Reference Prasada and Dillingham2006; Reference Prasada and Dillingham2009; Rhodes et al. Reference Rhodes, Leslie and Tworek2012). The distinction between statistical and generic beliefs is operative regardless whether these beliefs concern mosquitoes, books, and other categories of non-human entities, or women, African Americans, Muslims, and other categories of humans. This means that generic beliefs about social groups, just like other generic beliefs, are typically removed from the underlying statistics. For example, more people hold the generic belief that Muslims are terrorists than hold the generic belief that Muslims are female (see Leslie, Reference Lesliein press; Leslie et al. Reference Leslie, Khemlani and Glucksberg2011). However, there are vastly more Muslims who are female than there are Muslims who are terrorists. Most of us would even be able to report these statistics, as Jussim's own data suggest; yet, awareness of the statistics has little bearing on endorsement of the respective generic beliefs. Again, this is not an isolated example. Compare, for instance, “Asians are really good at math” and “Asians are right-handed.” Many more people would agree with the former generic claim than with the latter, while simultaneously being aware that the statistics go the opposite way.
In summary, people's beliefs about categories are of two types: generic and statistical. Although the accuracy of statistical beliefs depends solely on the data available in the world (e.g., how many Muslims are terrorists vs. women), the judged truth of generic beliefs does not. Rather, generic beliefs can be – and often are – largely discrepant with the reality on the ground.
2. Implications for the argument that stereotypes are accurate
We now go on to spell out the implications of this body of work for Jussim's argument. Regardless of which sort of belief (generic or statistical) he had in mind when claiming that stereotypes are largely accurate – and we will discuss each possibility in turn – the force of his argument is considerably weakened by attending to the evidence presented above.
2.1. Stereotypes as generic beliefs
Let's first assume that stereotypes are generic beliefs about groups. Based on our reading of the literature, this is how many social psychologists conceive of stereotypes, even though they understandably don't use the term generic. (Actually, at least one social psychologist we know of did use the term: Bob Abelson, whose research team published some fascinating work on “generic assertions” about social groups in the 1960s [e.g., Abelson & Kanouse Reference Abelson, Kanouse and Feldman1966; Gilson & Abelson Reference Gilson and Abelson1965].)
If stereotypes are generic beliefs, the evidence Jussim presents – all of which is about people's statistical estimates concerning group attributes – does not legitimize the claim that stereotypes are accurate. As explained above, generic beliefs depend only in a loose sense on the statistics available in the world. As a result, one cannot justifiably claim that generic beliefs are accurate, at least using the commonsense notion of accuracy that Jussim himself operates with. Is it accurate to believe – as most people do – that mosquitoes carry the West Nile virus but not that books are paperbacks? Is it accurate to believe that Asians are good at math but not right-handed? Sure, these beliefs may be “accurate” in the sense of being endorsed by many people, but agreement is a poor substitute for accuracy. The accuracy of a belief about a group is more legitimately assessed, as Jussim does, in terms of whether it matches the world statistically.
Based on these considerations, it seems reasonable to claim that, if stereotypes are generic beliefs, then they are often inaccurate – out of touch with the statistical reality. This is, of course, what many social psychologists have been claiming all along, and their claims appear justified under this definition of stereotypes. To further drive home this point, we briefly lay out four types of evidence suggesting considerable inaccuracy in people's (generic) stereotypes.
2.1.1. GENERIC BELIEFS ARE OFTEN ENDORSED ON THE BASIS OF SCANT STATISTICAL EVIDENCE
As already illustrated, many common generic beliefs are about attributes that are infrequent (e.g., Muslims are terrorists). Notably, generic beliefs based on limited statistical evidence have also been observed in more controlled settings – for example, in laboratory studies where participants were given information about the prevalence of various traits in unfamiliar categories and then tested for their endorsement of the corresponding generic beliefs (e.g., Brandone et al. Reference Brandone, Gelman and Hedglen2015; Cimpian et al. Reference Cimpian, Brandone and Gelman2010). Thus, several types of evidence (obtained with participants spanning the range from 4-year-olds to adults) suggest a disconnect between endorsement of generic beliefs and the underlying statistical facts.
2.1.2. GENERIC BELIEFS ARE RESISTANT TO COUNTEREVIDENCE
Related to the point about weak dependence on statistical evidence, once a generic belief is adopted, it is not easily falsified by exposure to evidence that contradicts it. The generic belief that mosquitoes carry the West Nile virus is not discarded as soon as a mosquito bite – or tens, or hundreds – fails to infect us. (The same goes for law-abiding Muslims and Asian people who aren't good at math.) Experimental work supports this conclusion as well. For example, 4-year-olds who first heard that pagons (an unfamiliar category) are friendly and were then shown a counterexample ended up generalizing this trait to novel pagons as frequently as children who did not see the counterexample (Chambers et al. Reference Chambers, Graham and Turner2008), which suggests that the counterexample had no effect on their endorsement of the generic belief.
2.1.3. GENERIC BELIEFS GIVE THE IMPRESSION OF STRONG STATISTICAL SUPPORT
Even though generic beliefs are often adopted on the basis of little statistical evidence, they nevertheless suggest – for example, when expressed in conversation – that the relevant attributes are almost always present (Brandone et al. Reference Brandone, Gelman and Hedglen2015; Cimpian et al. Reference Cimpian, Brandone and Gelman2010). For example, imagine a person who wasn't familiar with how the West Nile virus is transmitted. What would this person infer if they heard that mosquitoes carry it? Would they assume that fewer than 1% of mosquitoes in the affected areas are carriers, or perhaps that many more – even a majority – are? The evidence supports the latter possibility. In fact, most participants assume prevalence levels of greater than 90% when exposed to unfamiliar generic facts (Cimpian et al. Reference Cimpian, Brandone and Gelman2010). There is thus a stark asymmetry at the core of generic beliefs: Although they are largely independent of the underlying statistics at the stage when they are initially formulated, they immediately take on the appearance of being rooted in strong statistical uniformities. For anyone who has little firsthand familiarity with the actual facts, this asymmetry can lead to largely mistaken impressions about the state of the world.
2.1.4. GENERIC BELIEFS ARE ACCOMPANIED BY MISLEADING EXPLANATORY INTUITIONS
Generic beliefs have strong explanatory overtones. Specifically, generic claims are consistently interpreted as conveying deep, inherent properties of the relevant categories (e.g., Cimpian & Cadena Reference Cimpian and Cadena2010; Cimpian & Erickson Reference Cimpian and Erickson2012; Cimpian & Markman, Reference Cimpian and Markman2009, Reference Cimpian and Markman2011; Gelman et al. Reference Gelman, Ware and Kleinberg2010; Rhodes et al. Reference Rhodes, Leslie and Tworek2012; see also Cimpian & Salomon Reference Cimpian and Salomon2014). Thus, when we are exposed to generic beliefs about, say, women being bad at math or African Americans being violent, we are seldom neutral as to the source of the attributes described. Rather, we implicitly adopt an explanatory perspective on these attributes, viewing them as core, non-accidental aspects of what the relevant groups are like deep down. To the extent that many group characteristics are not actually due to their members’ biological makeup, this explanatory component of generic beliefs provides additional reasons to be suspicious of their match with the world.
In summary, if stereotypes are conceived as generic beliefs, then the evidence suggests they display a considerable amount of inaccuracy.
2.2. Stereotypes as statistical beliefs
What if we defined stereotypes as statistical beliefs instead? In this case, the evidence Jussim presents seems consistent with the idea that stereotypes are largely accurate. While that may be so, committing to a definition of stereotypes as statistical beliefs about groups may be problematic for another reason: A recent (yet already widely replicated) finding in the literature on concepts suggests that people often have difficulty reasoning with – manipulating, basing inferences on, etc. – statistical knowledge about categories (e.g., Gelman et al. Reference Gelman, Tapia and Leslie2016; Hampton Reference Hampton2012; Hollander et al. Reference Hollander, Gelman and Star2002; Jönsson & Hampton Reference Jönsson and Hampton2006; Khemlani et al. Reference Khemlani, Leslie and Glucksberg2012; Leslie et al. Reference Leslie, Khemlani and Glucksberg2011; Leslie & Gelman Reference Leslie and Gelman2012; Meyer et al. Reference Meyer, Gelman, Stilwell, Carlson, Hölscher and Shipley2011). In many circumstances, people tend to fall back on using generic representations, consistent with theoretical arguments that such representations are an easy “default” when reasoning about categories (e.g., Cimpian & Erickson Reference Cimpian and Erickson2012; Gelman Reference Gelman2003; Leslie Reference Leslie2008). Thus, even if people are at some level attuned to the statistical distributions of various attributes across various groups, such statistical knowledge may ultimately be less influential than people's generic beliefs about the same attributes.
We illustrate this point with data from Khemlani et al. (Reference Khemlani, Leslie and Glucksberg2012), who measured people's expectations about the traits of unfamiliar category members – a ubiquitous type of social judgment (e.g., how strongly do you expect the next Asian person you'll meet to be good at math?). Khemlani et al.’s goal was to compare the extent to which these expectations are rooted in participants’ statistical estimates (e.g., what percentage of Asian people do you think are good at math?) versus their generic beliefs (e.g., do you believe that Asians are good at math?).Footnote 2 The results highlighted the powerful influence of generic beliefs. Although participants’ statistical estimates did explain unique variance in their expectations about unfamiliar individuals, their endorsement of the relevant generic beliefs was considerably more predictive of these judgments (with an effect size that was 53% larger). Based on this and other similar evidence, we suggest that people's awareness of the statistical distributions of various traits may be less important to their social judgments than their generic beliefs are. Further research testing this (admittedly bold) claim would be in order, however.
In summary, if stereotypes are conceived as statistical beliefs, they may not provide as much insight into people's actual social judgments as one might expect.
3. Conclusion
Stereotypes are generic or statistical beliefs about the attributes of groups. If they are generic, they are likely not very accurate. If they are statistical, they may not be as influential as our (often inaccurate) generic beliefs about groups. Either way, one remains skeptical about the rationality of everyday social judgment.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
We are grateful to Joe Cimpian, David Yeager, Alice Eagly, and the members of the Cognitive Development Lab at the University of Illinois for helpful comments on previous drafts of this commentary. The writing of this commentary was supported in part by National Science Foundation grant BCS-1530669.