HISTORICAL BACKGROUND
In 1281, Archbishop Peckham laid down a programme of basic religious instruction that every parish priest was required to expound to his flock.Footnote 2 However, the need for any general provision of education did not exist then nor for centuries thereafter. Memorably, the programme of basic religious education contained in the Catechism provides for a confirmation candidate to identify as his duty to his neighbours ‘to do my duty in that state of life, unto which it shall please God to call me’.
In the static society envisaged by the Catechism, there was no need to read or write. Even after the French Revolution – and in some cases because of the French Revolution – there would still have been found those who, like Elizabeth Gaskell's Lady Ludlow, thought that the teaching of reading, writing and arithmetic was ‘levelling and revolutionary’.Footnote 3 However, early in the nineteenth century attitudes changed rapidly. In 1811, the National Society was founded – to give it its full name, The National Society for the Education of the Poor in the Principles of the Established Church.
Starting in 1812 with a school near Gray's Inn for 600 boys and 400 girls, the Society undertook an impressive programme for the provision of church schools.Footnote 4 By 1856 it was educating 988,276 children.Footnote 5 This is likely to have been the peak in terms of the proportion of the nation's children being educated. By 1870, the figure of nearly 900,000 children being educated in Church of England schools represented 70 per cent of the school population. In terms of numbers, the peak was in about 1890, when there were 11,922 Church of England Schools educating about 1.5 million children. But, by that time, this represented only 45 per cent of the school population.Footnote 6
The reason for the failure to educate all the nation's children was twofold. First of all, the cost of such extensive provision could not be sustained. Second, protestant dissenters and Roman Catholics did not want their children to be educated according to the principles of the established church and accordingly made their own provision.Footnote 7 But many children went without education altogether.
When, in 1870, the state decided to make elementary education compulsory, this was achieved by the provision by the state itself of a large number of additional schools. The state did not however ‘nationalise’ the pre-existing schools provided by the Church of England and the other churches. Rather, it continued to subsidise them.Footnote 8 Thus, from 1870 onwards, compulsory education was provided by means of a dual system of what we would now call faith schools and community schools. Note that the duality as it was conceived was not between Christian schools on the one hand and secular schools on the other. In 1870, hardly anyone was in favour of secular education.Footnote 9 The non-church-sponsored schools were required to give a Christian education but it was to be related to a Christianity not distinctive of any particular denomination.Footnote 10
The complicated history of the involvement of the churches with education in the period after 1870 can be found elsewhereFootnote 11 and the detail of it need not concern this article. There was a surge of new school building by the churches after 1870.Footnote 12 However the strain could not be borne and by the beginning of the Second World War the number was in decline. The present settlement dates from 1944 and the Education Act of that year, in which the churches surrendered some control of their schools in return for increased funding. Putting the matter broadly, the Church of England and Roman Catholic Church have continued to maintain church schools, although the position now is that the majority of the costs are met by the state.Footnote 13
FAITH SCHOOLS TODAY
In January 2007, there were 17,361 primary schools in England maintained by the state. Of these, 4,441 (25 per cent) were Church of England schools and 1,696 (10 per cent) were Roman Catholic schools. There were 26 Methodist schools and 58 schools sponsored by other Christian denominations. There were 28 Jewish schools, 4 Muslim schools and 1 Sikh school. In total, primary school population was 4.1 million. Of this population, 767,000 (19 per cent) were being educated in Church of England schools and 404,360 (10 per cent) in Roman Catholic schools.
In the same month, there were 3,343 secondary schools in England maintained by the state. Of these, 201 (6 per cent) were Church of England schools and 342 (10 per cent) were Roman Catholic schools. There were 30 schools sponsored by other Christian denominations. There were 9 Jewish schools, 3 Muslim schools and 1 Sikh school. The total secondary school population was 3.2 million. Of this population, 172,110 (5 per cent) were being educated in Church of England schools and 317,890 (10 per cent) in Roman Catholic schools.
Of the Church of England primary schools, it should be noted that 2,446 were voluntary controlled schools and 1,956 were voluntary aided schools. Of the Church of England secondary schools, 53 were voluntary controlled.Footnote 14
The worship in a faith school will be that of the sponsoring faith.Footnote 15 Subject to what is said below about voluntary controlled schools, faith schools teach the faith, that is, the religious education will be in accordance with that of the sponsoring faith.Footnote 16 As regards admissions, a faith school may adopt an admissions policy applicable in the event of oversubscription that gives a higher priority to pupils who are members of or who practise the faith or denomination.Footnote 17 As regards staffing, subject to what is said below about voluntary controlled schools, preference may be given to teachers who profess or practise the faith.Footnote 18
Voluntary controlled schools do not enjoy as much freedom as voluntary aided schools. Because the local education authority will be responsible for the admissions policy of these schools, they are unlikely to give preference to members of the Church of England,Footnote 19 while the religious education provided is likely to be non-denominational. They have only limited power to make teaching appointments with reference to the religious beliefs of applicants.
The lesser degree of autonomy enjoyed by voluntary controlled schools reflects their funding arrangements. Although the site of a voluntary controlled school will be owned by the Church of England, its funding will be entirely provided by the local education authority. In contrast, the faith sponsor will have to provide 10 per cent of the cost of external repairs to a voluntary aided school and 10 per cent of the costs of new buildings.Footnote 20
Non-faith schools are required to teach REFootnote 21 and to have a daily act of collective worship of a broadly Christian character.Footnote 22 However, in secondary schools at least, these requirements are attenuated in practice.Footnote 23 Accordingly, whereas historically the contrast would have been between (Christian) denominational schools and schools providing non-denominational Christian education, today the contrast is between faith schools (in the number of which those sponsored by faiths that are not Christian are beginning to feature) and schools that are essentially secular in ethos.
Of the two main providers of faith schools, the approaches of the Church of England and the Roman Catholic Church to admissions are different. Seeking to ensure social inclusiveness, the Church of England considers that, where one of its schools is oversubscribed, some places should be reserved for children of other faiths and of no faith.Footnote 24 As regards new schools, it will give priority in respect of 25 per cent of the places with no requirement that the children should be from practising Anglican families.Footnote 25 The Roman Catholic Church's primary concern is to provide schools to meet the needs of Roman Catholic parents.Footnote 26 The other faiths have not articulated policies in this regard.
The most recent statement of the Government's position as regards faith schools is one of unqualified support:
The Government continues to support the benefits to society that [the dual system of voluntary schools supported by faith organisations and schools without a religious character] brings for parental choice and diversity and with the changes in society, it is only fair that pupils of all faiths and none have the opportunity to be educated in accordance with the wishes of their parents.Footnote 27
OBJECTIONS TO FAITH SCHOOLS
Funding of religion by the state
In 1870, and for long thereafter, protestant dissenters were wholly opposed to the state providing any funding to the schools of the established church. They did not object to non-denominational religious teaching, of course, but they strongly objected to such teaching according to the tenets of the Church of England. Their criticism was the more intense in circumstances where a church school was the only one available.Footnote 28 This objection is now voiced by secularists, who are opposed in principle to any teaching of religion being funded by the state.Footnote 29 It is a weighty objection and I would suggest that it can only be met by pragmatic arguments. The only entirely coherent justification for special treatment would surely be for that special treatment only to be given to the established church, as reflecting its special relationship to the state: and this is an argument that has not been heard since 1870.
As a matter of history, the justification by the state for its funding of church schools was indeed pragmatic – its provision of community schools was originally only augmenting the substantial pre-existing provision of religious schools. The present justification, as has been seen, is now based essentially on choice. This is only completely satisfactory if sufficient resources are available to satisfy all reasonable parental choices. Moreover, rather obviously, parental choice is generally capable of working contrary to other government objectives such as social and racial inclusiveness. As will be seen below, there are specific issues relating to faith schools in this regard.
Suggested indoctrination and proselytism
Some object to faith schools on the basis that they indoctrinate their students and aim to convert to the faith those students who, when they join the school are not of the faith. ‘Indoctrinate’ is here being used in a sense which is akin to ‘brainwash’.
One can be confident that no supporter of faith schools would do so on the basis that they afford opportunities for indoctrination, a process which is antipathetic to concept of true education.Footnote 30 However, the providers of faith schools are committed to ensuring that they ‘nurture young people in the faith of their family’.Footnote 31 Faith schools will teach the faith as truth, and clearly a secularist (or a member of a different faith) may object to this.
The process of nurture, applied to a person not of the faith, can be described as proselytism. In The Way Ahead, the Church of England expressed the view that church schools should be at the centre of the mission of the church to the nation, that mission being summarised as being ‘to proclaim the gospel … to bring others into the faith’.Footnote 32 The present Archbishop of Canterbury, Rowan Williams, has said, however, that ‘To speak of the religious “mission” of the church school is not to define its task as being recruitment – an easy misunderstanding, but a very serious one’.Footnote 33
The Archbishop's argument rebutting the criticism and in support of faith schools is as follows:
For those who want their children to undertake the experiment of living in a climate of commitment, such a school offers, not a programme of indoctrination but the possibility of a new level of emotional and imaginative literacy through the understanding of how faith shapes common life. And this matters for the lives of individuals, agnostic or even atheist as much as believing; as it matters in a world where not to understand how faith operates leaves you at sea in engaging with the other, the stranger, at home or abroad.Footnote 34
On this basis it seems that it would be best if all education was in faith schools.Footnote 35 It also draws no distinction between different faiths.Footnote 36
Note that proselytism is not a charge that can be levelled directly at Roman Catholic schools. This is because, as has been seen, the Roman Catholic Church primarily aims to provide schools to educate the children of Roman Catholic parents.
Suggested social exclusivity
The general criticism is frequently made that church schools are not socially inclusive; that is, the assertion is that their social composition does not reflect that of the area in which they are placed. This might be, of course, a reflection of the fact that the social composition of the faith community does not reflect the social composition of the community at large. However a further specific criticism is often articulated.
Church schools do generally have excellent academic records and this encourages high levels of applications. Parents with high aspirations for their children, who tend to be middle class, want to get their children into church schools. They take steps to meet the selection criteria for the relevant church school. This is undesirable as it produces a school that is selective by class, as well as ‘tempting parents to public hypocrisy about their beliefs’.Footnote 37 The hypocrisy is probably less a matter of concern than its results.
The evidence is not decisive. A study carried out by Professor David Jesson for the National Society looked at 373 of the 400 secondary schools in London. Of the pupils at these schools, 23 per cent were entitled to free school meals.Footnote 38 In Church of England schools, the comparable figure was 22 per cent. Writing in the Church Times, Professor Jesson remarked that ‘These findings, related to social deprivation, demolish the myth that C of E schools are socially divisive; the data shows clearly that they almost exactly mirror the communities they serve.’Footnote 39
On the other hand, a study of 3071 secondary schools by the Bedford Group for Lifecare and Statistical Studies at the Institute of Education, University of London, indicated that, of the 480 voluntary aided secondary schools in its sample, 30 per cent were ‘cream skimming’Footnote 40 when eligibility for free school meals was considered.
There are other such studies.Footnote 41 It cannot be said that any are decisive. It seems likely that the effect about which concern is expressed does exist. What is more difficult is forming a judgment about how significant the effect is.
Enforcement of ‘mono-culturalism’
A more recent concern is highlighted by the report into the disturbances that occurred in Oldham, Burnley and a number of other places in the spring and early summer of 2001. These resulted in the destruction of property and attacks on the police. They had the common feature that they involved large numbers of people from different cultural backgrounds. One response was that the Home Office established a Community Cohesion Review Team to consider the position and make recommendations.
The team concluded that:
In terms of community cohesion, however, a significant problem is posed by existing and future mono-cultural schools, which can add significantly to the separation of communities described above. The development of more faith based schools may, in some cases, lead to an increase in mono-cultural schools but this problem is not in any way confined to them. We believe that all schools owe a responsibility to their pupils to promote, expand and enrich their experience, by developing contacts with other cultures (also set out below), or by ensuring that, as far as possible, they are represented within the school intake.Footnote 42
This conclusion led to a general proposal:
We would therefore, propose that all schools – whether faith or non-faith based – should seek to limit their intake from one culture or ethnicity. They should offer, at least 25%, of places to reflect the other cultures or ethnicities within the local area. We recognise that it is difficult to discriminate on the grounds of culture or ethnicity (the latter would be subject to legal challenge) and, in any event, the school may be less attractive to parents and children from other cultures. Indeed, the local culture or ethnicity may be the same as that of the predominant culture of the school. Nevertheless, schools can and must make themselves attractive to other cultures and ethnicities from a wider area (many parents are prepared for travel of some distances at present to schools of their choice) over a period of time. This will be difficult at first but the offer of places on a more inclusive basis is the first step and a positive action programme will be necessary to underpin it.Footnote 43
Against this background should be seen the team's specific proposals in respect of faith schools:
Faith schools should adopt exactly the same positive approach as that set out above for all schools. However, they have some special arrangements which allow them to address the matter in different ways. Some faith schools presently attract students from different cultures or ethnicities either because that faith community is presently inclusive of them, or by limiting the school to a maximum from that faith (ie accepting a pre-dominant, rather than single faith basis for the school). We believe that either, or both, of these approaches should now be adopted by all existing and proposed faith schools. Indeed, they have the means to achieve this directly, as whilst it is not possible in practical terms, to define ‘culture’ and nor is it possible to discriminate on the grounds of ethnicity under present legislation, it is possible to determine intake by reference to faith, or denomination. This is the gift of the church and faith leaders, who could advise both independent and state sector schools to open a proportion of their places, say a minimum of 25%, to other, or non faith, students. This would be entirely consistent with their stated desire to promote religious tolerance and understanding.Footnote 44
The political response to criticism of faith schools
If, as is the case, faith schools have been positively encouraged by the Labour governments that have been in power in Britain since 1998 as well as being supported by spokesmen of the Conservative Party, it is to be expected that faith schools will continue to receive political support. However, in the debates in Parliament on what became the Education and Inspections Act 2006, Lord Baker of Dorking proposed that a 25 per cent quota of non-faith pupils should be mandatory for new faith schools. This proposal was apparently principally aimed at new Muslim schools:
I say to the leaders of the Muslim community: is it really wise to promote the proliferation of exclusively Muslim schools in Muslim communities? Let us suppose that four primary schools are set up quite quickly in a Muslim community, to be followed by two or three secondary schools. Supported by their mosques that community will become very closed and inward looking. Children from outside will not be welcomed or, if they are welcome, will not want to go in. That strongly reinforces separateness in our society.Footnote 45
The resistance to this proposal shows the resilience of the existing system. Lord Baker's proposal raised a storm of protest from the Roman Catholic Church, and the government, which had begun by accepting the principle of the amendment, changed its mind about it. Instead, there is now a duty on all schools to promote community cohesion.Footnote 46
The matter is evidently a hugely sensitive one. It is not reasonable to criticise the non-Christian faiths for wanting to utilise the advantageous provisions that exist for the establishment of new faith schools. But Lord Baker and others may properly be concerned that the re-enforcement of faith through the educational system is potentially divisive.Footnote 47 It will be instructive to see how faith schools in mono-cultural areas will promote community cohesion in practice.
LEGAL ARGUMENTS AFFECTING FAITH SCHOOLS
If, accordingly, the dual system looks safe from political challenge, is there any basis on which it might be at risk from legal challenge?
In his consideration of whether faith schools indoctrinate, the Archbishop of Canterbury posed the question ‘Do they infringe the rights of our children by inducting them into damagingly false and irrational habits of mind, habits which no normal adult would freely adopt?’Footnote 48 As we have seen, the Archbishop answered this question in the negative, although not everybody will have been convinced by his argument. However, whatever view is taken of what actually goes on in faith schools, the question evidently proceeds from two prior assumptions, namely that indoctrination as he defined it would be wrong and that it would infringe the rights of the child. Does a child indeed have a right not to be indoctrinated?
Article 26 of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights begins ‘Everyone has the right to education’. Article 2 of the First Protocol of the European Convention on Human Rights begins ‘No person shall be denied the right to education’. Although negative in form, the Article has the heading ‘Right to Education’ and it has been held that it does confer a positive right.Footnote 49 Further, Article 14(1) of the United Nations Convention on the Rights of the Child provides that ‘States Parties shall respect the right of the child to freedom of thought, conscience and religion’.Footnote 50 Putting these rights together, one can begin to articulate a legal argument against indoctrination.
In Canada, indeed, the Supreme Court of Ontario has held that the RE curriculum of a Board of Education did amount to indoctrination (as the court defined it).Footnote 51 The teaching thus infringed the freedom of conscience and religious provisions of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms.Footnote 52
This was a case where the parents of a child objected to religious teaching. However, it is difficult to articulate rights of the child in opposition to the rights of his or her parents. Thus Article 2 of the First Protocol of the Convention on Human Rights set out above continues: ‘In the exercise of the functions which it assumes in relation to education and teaching, the State shall respect the right of parents to ensure such education and teaching in conformity with their own religious and philosophical convictions.’ Article 14(2) of the UNCRC provides:
State parties shall respect the rights and duties of parents and, where applicable, legal guardians, to provide direction to the child in the exercise of his or her right in a manner consistent with the evolving capacities of the child.
Historically, courts have been hostile to the assertion of the rights of a child in opposition to his or her parents,Footnote 53 and, although in Gillick v West Norfolk and Wisbech Area Health Authority Lord Scarman held that the true principle was that ‘parental right yields to the child's right to make his own decisions when he reaches a sufficient understanding and intelligence to be capable of making up his mind on the matter requiring decision’,Footnote 54 this begs the question as to the point at which a child reaches a sufficient understanding so as to be allowed to make his or her own decisions.
In Re R (A Minor) Footnote 55 a 10 year old wished to live with his grandparents, members of the Plymouth Brethren,Footnote 56 rather than his father, who had been excluded from that body. His wishes were a factor to be taken into account but were not, surely correctly, viewed as overriding.
Moreover, even if the views of the child and of his parents coincide, this does not mean that the child's rights, properly considered, are being respected. Thus, in the Denbigh High School case,Footnote 57 a school pupil made a claim under Article 9 of the European Convention on Human Rights, alleging infringement of her right to manifest her religious belief by wearing a jilbab.Footnote 58 The claim was rejected. Among the complex considerations that Baroness Hale said needed to be examined was the fact that ‘A mandatory policy that rejects veiling in state institutions may provide a crucial opportunity for girls to choose the feminist freedom of state education over the patriarchal dominance of their families.’Footnote 59
Thus there may be cases where the child's assertion of her rights in conformity with the views of her guardians may be contradicted by the state.Footnote 60 So, in an appropriate case, what may appear to be the rights of the child may be trumped by his parents or by the state asserting that they or it knows best. The rights of the child are ensured by not allowing him to make his own decisions. It is submitted that rights analysis in this area is particularly difficult and probably unhelpful.
In the Denbigh High School case, Lord Scott considered one particular situation that could arise:
Take the case of a faith school that required its pupils each day to participate in a form of collective religious worship. It may be assumed that each pupil on entry to the school would be content to participate in the daily religious service. If a pupil, having become a convinced atheist, decided that he or she could no longer in conscience take part in an act of worship that was inconsistent with the new beliefs that he or she had recently acquired and asked to be excused from attending the daily religious service, Strasbourg jurisprudence would not permit the school's refusal to accept this request to be represented as infringing the pupil's Article 9 rights unless, perhaps, the institution offered an essential service not obtainable elsewhere.Footnote 61
His analysis seems correctFootnote 62 and, of course, he was considering a situation absent of a potential complication, namely that the atheist child's parents, not having shared his conversion, might wish him to continue at the faith school.
It is submitted, however, that, without a right (of a pupil's parents at least) of withdrawal from collective worship and faith-based RE, there would be human rights concerns about faith schools. However, a right of withdrawal does exist, and the concerns articulated in the Canadian Civil Liberties Association case would be unlikely at the moment to impress an English or European Court.
Thus, even setting aside disagreements about what indoctrination is,Footnote 63 it does not look at the moment as if the rights of the child not to be indoctrinated could be articulated in a way so as to pose any threat to the existing arrangements for faith schools.
The funding arrangements for faith schools are at least potentially vulnerable to human rights attacks. In this context, it is necessary to consider Bishop of Roman Catholic Diocese of Port Louis v Suttyhudeo Tengur,Footnote 64 an appeal from the Supreme Court of Mauritius to the Privy Council.
The case concerned the admissions policy of 12 Roman Catholic secondary schools in Mauritius. All the schools were funded by the state, so that it could be said that the state bore responsibility for the admissions system, which indeed it had agreed with the Roman Catholic authorities. The effect of this was that the human rights provisions in the Constitution of Mauritius applied to the admissions system operated by the Roman Catholic authorities (the provisions of the constitution in respect of the actions of public bodies mirror those in respect of public authorities in the Human Rights Act 1998, and the Roman Catholic authorities were held to be a public body).
The admissions policy was that half the intake each year was of Roman Catholic children and half of non-Roman Catholic. All children competed for half the places on merit, and some would obviously go to Roman Catholic children. These latter would have first call on the Roman Catholic places, which would then be made up to half by the selection of those who had either failed or not taken part in the competition. The other half would be selected on merit. The details are not entirely clear, but it is possible to see that that a potential pupil had a better chance of getting in if he or she was a Roman Catholic.
This was differentiation based on creed. As Lord Bingham pointed out:
The giving of preference to one group of applicants necessarily works to the disadvantage of any group of applicants to whom preference is not given. In relation to reserved places, the appellants' avowed intention is to maintain the religious and moral character and ethos of the Catholic colleges by recruiting enough Roman Catholic pupils to leaven the whole loaf. Understandable and even admirable as this intention may be, it involves differentiating between one pupil and another.Footnote 65
But this is not necessarily enough to sustain a complaint of unlawful discrimination. As Lord Bingham explained, the discrimination may be justified as having a legitimate aim and having a reasonable relationship of proportionality between the means employed and the aim sought to be realised. As the authorities cited by him demonstrated, this is the position both under Mauritian law applying the Mauritian constitution and English law applying the European Convention.Footnote 66
In the Mauritian courts the argument had been about whether the arrangements described above did in fact exist, and no attempt had been made to justify them. Accordingly there was no material before the Privy Council on which it could find the discrimination justified.
As has been seen, there is a right to education under Article 2 of the First Protocol to the European Convention on Human Rights just as there is under the Mauritian constitution. Article 14 of the Convention provides:
The enjoyment of the rights and freedoms set forth in the Constitution shall be secured without discrimination on any ground such as sex, race, colour, language, religion, political or other opinion, national or social origin, association with a national minority, property, birth or other status.
Consider now a non-faith parent of a child who lives close to a faith school with an excellent academic record. His child is not admitted to the faith school. He may say ‘I care nothing for the ethos of this school, although I have no objection to my son attending acts of religious worship and classes of religious instruction. I do however want my son to attend the best local school’. It may be possible to demonstrate that, had his son met the faith-based requirements of the faith school, he would have been admitted to it. As it is, his son attends a school with a markedly poorer academic record than the faith school. Additional matters could be added to the hypothetical facts. Analysis might show, for example, that the proportion of those entitled to free school meals is markedly less than would be the case if it drew its pupils from those eligible living nearest to it; and that those potential pupils who would be entitled to free school meals tend to be from an ethnic minority of a particular faith. This might support the argument on religious discrimination, and add to it the possibility of discrimination on the grounds of race.Footnote 67 Against this it would be argued that, if the situation were properly analysed, no discrimination would be found; and, further, that any discrimination that there might be would be justified.
As a matter of principle, it can indeed be said that the facilitation of choice by the provision of both faith schools and non-faith schools does not involve discrimination. Why is it unlawful discrimination to exclude a child not of the faith from a school provided for those who are of the faith? In the Denbigh High School case (not a case argued on the basis of discrimination), the House of Lords held, by a majority, that there was no interference with the claimant's right to manifest her religion, because she could readily go to another school that would allow her to wear the jilbab. It would no doubt be strongly argued, even on the facts postulated, that the child could readily be educated elsewhere. Nonetheless, on the basis of those facts, the argument that there is no discrimination does not seem altogether convincing.Footnote 68 Nor, on those facts, can it be said that the discrimination is justified by the ability of the child to go to an equally good school elsewhere.
As regards justification, some assistance is provided by X v United Kingdom.Footnote 69 In that case, parents in Northern Ireland wanted to set up a non-denominational school. To do so they would have been required to provide part of the funding. They claimed that the existing state schools in Northern Ireland (which were entirely funded by the state) were essentially Protestant in character and that the failure of the state to provide all the funding for a non-denominational school was contrary to Article 2 of the First Protocol. They did not argue a case based on Article 14. However, the Commission considered the point and held as follows:
In its determination whether there is discrimination within the meaning of Article 14 in the present case, the Commission considers that it is legitimate for the State to exercise substantial control in the ownership and management of schools for which it provides a full 100% subsidy. Conversely, the Commission is of the opinion that it is reasonable for the State, in relation to bodies that seek ownership and decisive control over management policy in voluntary schools, to require some degree of financial contribution. The Commission does not consider that the requirement of a 15% contribution capital costs [sic] is an unreasonable or disproportionate requirement, taking into consideration that ownership of the school would be vested in trustees representative of the body concerned and the exercise of two thirds control in the governing body.
Accordingly, the complaint was declared inadmissible.
The assumed facts and reasoning are not altogether clear, but the point seems to be that the state can justify a system whereby the amount of funding is related to degree of control exercised by the state. Applying this to the dual system in England and Wales, the state does not provide all the funding in respect of faith schools, and the quid pro quo for that is a lesser degree of control by the state.Footnote 70
The school that was the subject of challenge in the hypothetical case postulated above would no doubt emphasise its duty of promoting community cohesion, and seek to argue that any discrimination is an indirect and unintended consequence of a reasonable selection policy. One may predict that it would win, but it cannot be said that the outcome is self-evident. As with many human rights cases, even ones raising important points of principle, the outcome would be heavily fact reliant.
CONCLUSION
Criticism of faith schools, which has been shown to be long-standing, is not going to go away. Accordingly, legal challenges are to be expected. This is an interesting area because it gives rise to profound questions as to the proper scope of education in a liberal society as well as to difficult questions of social justice. In the political arena, these questions are answered by arguments based on pragmatism. Accordingly, it may be said that they are not very well suited to adjudication with reference to legal rights. The proper scope of human rights law lies beyond the scope of this paper, although it is hoped that it will help to inform the discussion of that issue.