Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-lrblm Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-05T22:40:09.892Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Beauty, virtue, and religious exemplars

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 December 2015

IAN JAMES KIDD*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Nottingham, University Park, Nottingham, NG7 2RD, UK
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article explores the beauty of religious exemplars – those special persons whose conduct and comportment marks their life out as one that exemplifies a religious life. Such exemplars are consistently described as beautiful, but it is not clear how or why. I suggest that we can make sense of the aesthetic aspect of religious exemplarity by adopting a ‘virtue-centric’ theory of beauty that understands the beautiful in terms of the expression or manifestation of virtues. Religious exemplars are those who have cultivated their virtues to an advanced degree and are beautiful for that reason. Attending to the beauty of religious exemplars can enrich exemplarist virtue theory, the aesthetics of character, and our understanding of the nature of a religious life.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2015 

Introduction

Every religious tradition recognizes certain persons as being exemplars of a religious life. Such people are the monks, nuns, saints, gurus, yogis, bodhisattva, or daoshi who exemplify a life of aspiration to, and attainment of, spiritual goodness. Such religious exemplars are described within the terms of their respective traditions as godly, saintly, wise, enlightened, or ‘attuned to dao’, but also as being beautiful. If so, one can look for beauty in religion not only in objects and practices – songs or statues, art or architecture – but also in certain persons. In this article, I explore and defend the claim that beauty in religion can be found in exemplary religious persons. What follows is, then, an exercise in the aesthetics of religion, the study of the place and significance of aesthetic values and experiences in religious lives and traditions. Much of the current interest in the aesthetic and the religious is inspired by the work in ‘theological aesthetics’, such as that of Hans Urs von Balthasar, but it also includes a growing body of work by philosophers, including Roger Scruton and Mark Wynn.Footnote 1 I specifically want to secure the possibility that religious beauty can be found in these exemplars, as well as in the artistic practices and material culture of religion. If that is correct, then it is not only religious art and icons that, in Scruton's phrase, can act as ‘concrete images of transcendent truths’, through which the faithful can ‘understand their Creator’ – for, if I am right, then exemplary religious persons can do so, too.Footnote 2

Religious exemplars

Instead of speaking of ‘religious exemplars’, I will speak more simply of ‘sages’, a term less irredeemably associated with any specific tradition, while still connoting a high degree of moral and spiritual attainment. Such inclusiveness is needed because I want to recognize a range of religious exemplars from culturally diverse traditions. A sage, in my sense, could be a Christian saint, a Hindu yogi, or a Daoist daoshi, and can appear in traditions that are western or Asian, theistic or non-theistic, and so on. But what unites such sages is their status in their respective traditions as exemplars of an advanced stage or form of religious life – of the ‘enlightened’ life, ‘liberated’ from the ‘wheel of suffering’, sought by Buddhists and Hindus, say. Such sages are, then, those whose conduct and character reflect the cultivation of what David E. Cooper calls a religious sense.Footnote 3 This has two aspects: first, a sense of there being something (although not necessary an object or entity) transcendent of the world as ordinarily experienced – God, Brahman, or śūnyata, perhaps. Second, it has an allied sense that it is possible, desirable, or even imperative to align or attune or assimilate one's life to that which transcends the ordinarily experienced world. Think of the Daoist's ideal of a way of life that ‘follows the way of dao’, or a Buddhist's enlightened life illuminated by the Four Noble Truths, or the theistic comportments that Kierkegaard described as being ‘in the truth’. The sage is an exemplar in so far as their life cultivates and expresses a religious sense to an advanced or superlative degree.

Sages are aesthetically, as well as morally and spiritually, impressive. The idea that they are beautiful personages connects aesthetics of religion with two other debates. The first concerns the ‘aesthetics of character’, the idea that a good moral character is itself aesthetically pleasing, an idea Plato developed as the ‘beautiful soul’. This idea has been revived, after centuries of neglect, not least thanks to a renewed appreciation of the artificiality of rigid distinctions between the ethical and the aesthetic.Footnote 4 Second, sages are related to the ‘exemplarist’ theories of virtue, recently defended by Linda Zagzebski.Footnote 5 As the name suggests, central to those theories is the idea that moral and spiritual learning essentially involves encounters with exemplars of virtue (or vice). By attending to the conduct and character of exemplary people, one comes to admire and emulate their admirable qualities – their virtues – and so gain a practical mastery upon which moral theorizing can proceed. Sages are religious exemplars who inspire and teach others to follow a spiritual path, such as Jesus or the Buddha, and thinking about their beauty can bring together exemplarism and the aesthetics of character.

Sages do not need to be identical in their conduct or character nor in the specifics of the religious ways of life that they exemplify. The sages of different traditions often differ from one another in their habits, demeanours, and lifestyles that reflect different ethical and soteriological visions. An enlightened Mahayana Buddhist bodhisattva sitting serenely in meditation is a visually and spiritually different figure from the devout Christian monk kneeling in prayer. The Stoic sage is politically and civically engaged in a way that the quietist daoshi or Hindu yogi is unlikely to be. Descriptions of sages as godly or enlightened or ‘attuned to dao’ denote genuine differences of moral and spiritual orientation, as well as doctrinal conviction and metaphysical vision. Such pluralism is obvious in the hagiography and iconography of the world's religions that depict exemplary figures – Patriarchs, buddhas, saints – in art, statues, and scripture.

The status of sages as religious exemplars can be accepted without a debate about religious pluralism. Sages across religious traditions obviously reflect conceptions of the nature of reality and of the good life that are mutually incompatible. But they all reflect the conviction that one's own way of life can be aligned with or shaped by the way of the world. A Daoist sage's life of virtue (de) is guided by the way (dao) that generates and sustains the world, while the Stoic sage's mind is orderly and rational in emulation of the logos that governs the kosmos at a whole. Such examples indicate that a sage's conduct and character exemplify both the possibility and the fruits that a cultivated religious sense offers. Such religious lives of course require engagement in spiritual practices and disciplined practices of askēsis that demand great effort and sacrifice, of a sort to which many people are naturally averse. The religious life must therefore be made attractive to non-initiates, enough, at the least, to provoke interest.

One way to make a religious life attractive is to show that those who exemplify its mature or advanced forms are themselves attractive. Sages qua exemplars of religious life should evince qualities that make their character and way of life attractive – such as calm, charisma, or tranquillity. In the ‘lives of the saints’, explains Balthasar, one finds ‘faith and understanding . . . bound together’, such that the saintly ‘stand at the heart of the world, enjoying a life of deep confidence and profound peace’.Footnote 6 Buddhist sutras describe the lives of enlightened bodhisattva as marked by joyfulness, wisdom, and ‘radiance’.Footnote 7 Likewise, the tranquillity and spontaneity of Daoist sages stands in stark contrast to the frenetic activity and restlessness of those ‘not on the way’.Footnote 8 One is attracted to a religious life by finding attractive those who exemplify it.

The attractiveness of sages is, however, not simply ethical or psychological. It also has a strong aesthetic aspect. A sage is not only calm or tranquil, but also beautiful. But what does the sage's beauty consist of and how is it related to their moral and spiritual qualities?

Beauty and virtue

Some sages were beautiful in the conventional sense of being physically attractive. Gotama and Krishna, for instance, were reputed to be extremely handsome. But this is a poor characterization of the beauty of sages. First, such erotic or sexual accounts sit badly with moral injunctions in most religious traditions to modesty, chastity, and ‘non-attachment’. Second, not all sages were conventionally beautiful in this sense. A distinguished admirer reports that Mahatma Gandhi had ‘unimpressive features’ and a ‘poor physique’ but also possessed a ‘charm’, ‘magnetism’, and sense of ‘tremendous inner . . . power’ that was beautiful.Footnote 9 So if the sage's beauty is not bodily in an erotic or sexual sense, in what does it consist?

The Buddha answered this question. ‘Beauty for a monk’, he explained, resides in their ‘right conduct, restraint, and perfect . . . behaviour and habits’.Footnote 10 The Prātimokṣa or Monastic Code clarifies the beauty that bhikkhu and bhikkhuni ought to cultivate, express, and appreciate, as do the third-century bce Abdhidharma texts. These set out the forms of ‘beautiful consciousness’ (sobhanā citta) and ‘beautiful mental factors’ (sobhanā cetasika) that characterize the enlightened. These are not abstract mental states, however, but are consistently described in terms of moral qualities and associated forms of bodily comportment. Faith (saddhā) involves a ‘removal of [the] mind's impurities’, manifested in calm and disciplined conduct, free from visible expressions of anxiety. Tranquillity (pasaddhi), which requires a ‘quieting [of] disturbances’, shows itself in a demeanour marked by ‘peacefulness and coolness’.Footnote 11 Such remarks show that inner moral or spiritual qualities are and ought to be expressed in relevant modes of bodily comportment and personal conduct, which it is a purpose of religious training to inculcate.

If so, the beauty of sages – at least in the Buddhist tradition – is not a beauty of the body itself, but rather of the bodily expression of moral and spiritual virtues. But this claim is not confined to ancient Indian religion, since one finds it in other traditions. David E. Cooper dubs it the ‘virtue-centric’ theory of beauty.Footnote 12 The beautiful soul that Plato and his followers, especially Plotinus, sought and celebrated is apprehended in the forms of ‘noble conduct’ that express ethical and intellectual virtues.Footnote 13 Nor was virtue-centrism confined to antiquity, for it is present at the birth of aesthetics in its modern form during the eighteenth century. In the Critique of Aesthetic Judgement, Kant argued that the ‘ideal of beauty’ should be ‘sought in the human figure’, where, ‘visible in bodily manifestation’, are the ‘moral ideas’ that ‘govern men inwardly’. Such ideas are, in effect, virtues, like purity and benevolence. Schiller, too, argued that a person is beautiful in so far as his or her conduct manifests the primary virtue of ‘self-determination’.Footnote 14

The virtue-centric account also recurs throughout the world's religious traditions. Later Buddhists followed their founder in locating the beauty of people in an ‘inner beauty’, ‘beauty of the mind’, or ‘beauty of the inner reality’.Footnote 15 Rūmī – the great Sufi poet – found the best ‘image’ of ‘beauty in the world’ not in art or nature, but rather in the ‘hearts of perfect men’ – that is, the character of religious exemplars. A modern Sufi agrees that the ‘sense of beauty’ is found in an ‘art of personality’, understood as the cultivation and exercise of virtues, like sincerity and tactfulness. It is in personal conduct shaped by this ‘art’ that a Sufi beholds the ‘very nature of spiritual beauty’.Footnote 16 The erōs of Christian spiritual life is, says Balthasar, ‘fundamentally ordered to the divine self-manifestation in the specific and beautiful form of Jesus Christ’.Footnote 17

I need not pile up testimonies to establish further that the beauty of sages has both bodily and moral or spiritual aspects. It is a beauty of body and of virtue, where this latter term is shorthand for what those cited called ‘moral ideas’ or ‘mental factors’. The beauty of a sage, it is emerging, consists in their bodily expression of virtues. But that claim, as it stands, poses two questions, which I address in the next two sections.

Inner beauty, virtue, and expression

The claim that the beauty of the sage is an ‘inner’ or moral beauty poses the question of how this inner beauty relates to outer beauties – of objects perceived through the senses, like sunrises and sonatas. If talk of inner beauty is to be legitimate, then it must be related in a substantive way to aesthetic experiences of the sensory world. It is through such experiences that aesthetic terms ‘first get their sense and power’.Footnote 18

There are bad accounts of the relation of inner and outer beauty. One is to appeal to an analogy between them – to say, for instance, that an orderly mind, like an orderly garden, is pleasingly calm and peaceful. But that is clearly too weak. Another may be to assert some causal relation between inner and outer beauty. Some Buddhists think that physical beauty is karmic reward for good moral conduct. But aside from the fact that such replies are only available to those who accept doctrines of rebirth, there are familiar concerns about motivating moral actions by appeal to sensual reward. A love of physical beauty is typically recognized as a vice that impairs moral growth.

Cooper develops a better account of the relation of inner and outer beauty. One can speak legitimately of inner beauty if and when inner qualities – virtue, de, holiness – find expression in forms of bodily comportment that are found beautiful. Smiles that express kindness, or gestures that manifest compassion, are beautiful for that reason (at least for those who recognize those qualities as admirable qualities). A cruel sneer reflects or expresses a vice – cruelty – which is why we do not find it to be beautiful. Cooper notes that this explains why beauty matters so much to people: who and what we find beautiful reflects not only the idiosyncrasies of subjective taste, but also our deeper sense of the nature of the good. Our sense of beauty is therefore informed by the ‘economy of our most central concerns’.Footnote 19

The claim that actions and characters that express virtues are beautiful is supported by the testimonies of religious persons. Susanna Mrozick offers many examples from Buddhism in her book, Virtuous Bodies.Footnote 20 The Prātimokṣa and other Buddhist training texts – like Shantideva's Compendium of Training (Shikshasamucchaya) – dissolve a ‘distinction between body and morality’. Actions and practices such as bowing, meditating, and walking should express virtues and are beautiful in so far as they do. Mother Teresa described her pastoral work as emotionally exhausting, but also as ‘very beautiful’, since it consisted of visible, tangible acts of love, courage, and hope. Such pastoral acts express virtues taught by Jesus and loved by God, and which are therefore beautiful as well as good.Footnote 21

The idea that the comportment of religious initiates ought to express virtues is also evident in systems of religious training and practice. The disciplines of bodily, moral, and spiritual training undergone by monks, nuns, and others are intended not only to cultivate their virtues, but also to train them to express them – how to sit at prayer, how to eat a meal, how to sit before an icon, and so on. Such disciplined expression is itself facilitated and amplified by the material culture of religious life, such as ritual, art, music, and the use of sacred spaces and places, like temples. But it is not only in religious communities that people express their character in bodily comportment. An obvious way we learn about the virtues and vices of others is by attending to how they speak and act and move – kind smiles, earnest tones of voice, warm demeanour. Indeed, it is otherwise difficult to see how we could form impressions of people.

The claim that one's ‘inner’ character expresses itself in ‘outer’ comportment raises two worries: first, a skilled dissimulator could successfully express virtues they in fact lacks; second, a person may fail to express their virtues properly – if, say, they are naturally shy or retiring. Both challenge the relation between inner and outer beauties: one could express a false character, or fail to express one's real character.

Starting with dissimulation, the claim that a certain bodily action is expressive of a virtue is perfectly compatible with the occurrence, on certain occasions, of that action being faked. If a certain type of smile is recognized in a culture to be expressive of kindness, it does not, and need not, follow that kindness motivates every such smile. That is no more puzzling than the fact that a word retains its typical meaning even if on certain occasions it is used to signify something different. The word ‘good’ keeps its meaning even if I sardonically describe a morning of calamities and an afternoon of disasters as ‘a good day’. So forms of action or behaviour express virtues even if, on some occasions, those acting lack those virtues (although an interesting question remains about whether one's perception of, say, a smile as kind remains once one discovers that the smiler was, at that moment, thinking cruel thoughts).Footnote 22

Moving on to inexpression, it is true that some people are less animated than others. Some people are lively and expansive, others reserved and demure, although certain personal qualities are expressed in each case, even if they are reserve not bubbliness. But the inexpression worries primarily apply to laymen, meaning those who have not undergone religious training, therefore not to sages qua religious exemplars. For religious instruction, as noted earlier, involves training novices how to cultivate and to express their virtues through disciplined conduct. Novices typically live in a small community with other aspirants led by a religious exemplar – an abbot or guru, say – whose conduct and comportment they scrutinize and emulate. Such sages provide both practical demonstration and theoretical instruction in the conduct of a religious life in different situations and among different people – monks in the temple, say, or laymen in the marketplace. Such communities include the small informal groups that gathered around Jesus and Epicurus, or larger institutional bodies like the Buddhist saṅgha or Sikh gurduārā.Footnote 23

A religious initiate is trained both how to express their own character and to perceive better that of others. This includes appreciation of the subtleties and significance of symbols, words, colours, vestments, and timing, refining the initiate's powers of moral and spiritual resolution and discernment (a theme of much recent work in the phenomenology of the spiritual life).Footnote 24 The religiously exemplary are therefore adept both at expressing their own ‘inner moral reality’ and at identifying that of others; as with art scholars, their trained powers of discrimination enable them to spot not only nuances and subtleties, but also fakes. Moreover, an ability to discern the expression of virtues by religious persons will be present, at least to some degree, among many of the members of societies with a religious heritage – young Britons can still perceive in the figure of the Buddha his virtues of tranquillity and equanimity.

The claim that the beauty of sages consists in their bodily expression of virtues can therefore be secured against concerns about dissimulation and inexpression. It might even be the case that such worries could only obtain if the ‘expression’ account – as Cooper calls it – is true. For we would only worry that people could deceive us about their moral character by dissimulative actions if we trusted that one's conduct does reflect one's character. Compare this with lying, which is only possible where it is an established practice that what we say accurately reflects what we sincerely believe.Footnote 25 Similarly, we could only worry that some people might fail to express their character through their conduct if we suppose that most people generally do so successfully – a point reflected in our disdain for liars, fakers, and ‘bullshitters’.Footnote 26

Beauty and sages

The beauty of sages, I have suggested, consists in their bodily expression of virtues in perceptible modes of bodily comportment. But a second question is this: why speak, here, of beauty, rather than the sage's goodness or holiness? Use of an aesthetic term requires some justification; otherwise its use may seem, to a critic, to be merely figurative. The worry expressed here is apt to be amplified by the fact that the concept of beauty fell into neglect in the last century, when many obituarists reported the ‘death of beauty’. If ‘beauty belongs nominally to aesthetics’, judged one commentator, then it seems that it has been ‘disowned’ by that discipline.Footnote 27

Happily, cultural and intellectual tastes change and such obituaries were revised. A new kalliphilic mood, more sympathetic to talk of beauty, has emerged.Footnote 28 But the task still remains to show that what sages evince or manifest is a genuinely beauty.

My strategy for doing so will be to show that the comportment of sages fulfils all of the features that characterize an experience of the beautiful. I rely on Mary Mothersill's book, Beauty Restored, in which she identifies a consistent concept of beauty in the western philosophical tradition that has four features.Footnote 29 An experience, she argues, is one of beauty if it (i) is a kind of good, (ii) linked with pleasure, delight, or joy, which (iii) inspires love or longing, and (iv) depends on perception.

First, what a sage expresses in their conduct and comportment is a good. Indeed, in the relevant religious traditions, it is typically the highest or primary good, whether that is godliness, enlightenment, or ‘profond de’. The daoshi's life and demeanour evince the virtues (de) that mark out a person attuned to the Way (dao), harmony with which is the ultimate Daoist imperative: a point evident in the title of one of their main texts, the Daodejing, or ‘The Classic of the Way and its Virtue (or Power)’. The Christian saints manifest virtues like piety and humility that are both necessary for and constitutive of the relationship with God on which one's salvation depends. The goods that the sage manifests naturally differ by tradition, but they are all the fundamental good to which human beings can aspire – so different goods generate different beauties.Footnote 30

Second, a sage's conduct, to be beautiful, must inspire joy and delight. That it does so is attested to by a huge body of testimonies from those who encounter them. Aquinas defined beauty as ‘that which pleases through being seen’, while Augustine added that it was the quality which ‘attracts’ us to ‘things we love’.Footnote 31 For both men, what ultimately ‘pleases’ and ‘attracts’ are the ethical and spiritual qualities that are loved by God and present in spiritually exemplary persons. The sages described in Daoist texts – like the titular figure of the Zhuangzi – are lively and spontaneous and inspire pleasure and delight in those who read them. Buddhists monks and nuns are, as noted earlier, trained to comport themselves in ways that will attract people to the Eightfold Path to enlightenment. And think, too, of popular western enthusiasm for the delight occasioned by the cheerful glee of the Dalai Lama.Footnote 32

Third, an experience of beauty must inspire longing and love. The objects of this longing vary across religious traditions. The beautiful ‘noble conduct’ of a Plotinian sage inspires a powerful ‘yearning’ for the One, the mystical source of all things. The gentle spontaneity of a rustic daoshi instils a desire for a life free from the pressure and artifice of everyday life – and so on. Sages aim to inspire in others a longing for or love of the religious modes of life that are, variously, wise, godly, or enlightened – for these are lives purified of or liberated from fear, sin, or suffering. Indeed, a sage's life can inspire joy and delight precisely because it is free of such things.

And finally, an experience of beauty must depend on perception. That the sage's beauty does so was established earlier when it was explained that it is perceived in modes of bodily comportment – posture, gestures, smiles, and tone of voice. One sees the sage's humble posture, hears the sincerity as they intone prayers – and so on – both during ritual activities, like singing, and everyday activities, like eating. Indeed it is truer to say that a sage's life is one in which the distinction between the religious and the everyday is elided. The beauty of a sage is therefore not an abstract property that is apprehended through some special spiritual sense, but a perceptually available aspect of their bodily comportment.

These four aspects of the experience of beauty are illustrated by Balthasar's account of the Christian saint. These men and women express in their conduct various ‘marks of spiritual credit’ that reflect an ‘interior rightness’ – a purity of the spirit – understood in terms of virtues like piety, faith, and humility. Such saints therefore manifest an ‘attractive charm’ that can enthuse others into a ‘state of rapture’ through which one is ‘captivated and transformed’ by a powerful sense of being in the ‘presence of . . . spiritual beauty’.Footnote 33 Already one sees the first three features – the good, delight, and longing – and the fourth appears when Balthasar emphasizes that a saint's beauty is necessarily embodied. ‘Only though [bodily] form . . . can the lightning-bolt of eternal beauty flash.’Footnote 34

One might ask whether Mothersill's concept of beauty is confined to the western religions, such as Christianity, which after all were shaped by the very concept of beauty she traces. The answer is that the four-part concept of beauty she describes applies perfectly well to describe and explain reports of the beauty of the sages of other traditions, including those discussed earlier in the article. Bodhisattvas, daoshis, gurus, and yogis all perceptibly conduct themselves in ways that exemplify a vision of the good life in ways that can inspire delight and longing. The art and literature of religious traditions carefully describe the character and the conduct of sages, many now familiar to our cultural imagination. There is anyway no reason why a concept of beauty that emerged within one tradition cannot be applied to explain experiences of beauty in another. That the beauty of exemplary religious figures is explained by this concept is a testament to that.

Conclusions

I suggest that the beauty of religious exemplars – of sages – can be understood using the virtue-centric account. Beauty expresses or manifests virtues, and those exemplary people who have cultivated their virtues to a high degree are therefore beautiful. The aesthetics of religion should recognize religious exemplars as interesting and unique objects and sources of beauty – and so, too, should exemplarist virtue theory.Footnote 35

Footnotes

2. Scruton (Reference Scruton2009), 189.

3. Cooper (Reference Cooper2014).

4. See, for instance, Novitz (Reference Novitz1991); Harcourt (Reference Harcourt and May2001); Sherman (Reference Sherman2005).

5. Zagzebski (Reference Zagzebski2010). Exemplarist virtue theory was also the theme of her October 2015 Gifford Lectures at the University of St Andrews.

6. Quoted in Moss (Reference Moss, Oakes and Moss2004), 80.

7. The latter terms (joyfulness etc.) are some of the ten (sometimes fourteen) bhūmis or ‘grounds’ through which an aspiring bodhisattva must proceed, as described in the Avataṃsaka Sūtra and Laṇkāvatāra Sūtra.

8. The ‘way of dao’ is described in Daodejing, ch. 25, and the lives of people who ‘lost the Way’ are criticized in Zhuangzi, chs 2 and 4.

9. The admirer is Jawaharlal Nehru (Reference Nehru1962), 129–130.

10. The Buddha (Reference Buddha and Walshe1995), 405.

11. See Nārada (Reference Nārada2007), 85–87 passim.

13. Ennead, §I.6.1.

14. Quotations are from Kant, The Critique of Aesthetic Judgement, §17, and Schiller, Kallias Letters, referenced and discussed in Cooper (Reference Cooper2008), 248–249ff.

15. These and other examples are referenced and discussed in Cooper (Reference Cooper, Sikka, Maira and Higginsforthcoming).

16. Rūmī (Reference Rūmī2012), poem XV, ‘The truth within us’, 11; Inayat Khan (Reference Inayat Khan2013), ch. 11 passim.

17. Quoted in Davies (Reference Davies, Oakes and Moss2004), 134–135.

19. See, e.g., Cooper (Reference Cooper2008), §3, and (Reference Cooper and Keping2010), §3.

20. Mrozick (Reference Mrozick2007).

21. Quoted in Chawla (Reference Chawla2003), 285–286.

22. I am very grateful to David E. Cooper for guiding my response to this objection.

23. A detailed study of Buddhist monastic life is Wijayaratna (Reference Wijayaratna, Grangier and Collins1990).

24. See, for instance, Cottingham (Reference Cottingham2005), 99f., and Wynn (Reference Wynn2013), 94f.

25. This point about dishonesty and practices of truth-telling is developed by Williams (Reference Williams2002).

26. A cheerful discussion of this point is Frankfurt (Reference Frankfurt2005).

27. Kirwan (Reference Kirwan1999), ix.

28. Two good examples of this new kalliphilic mood are Sartwell (Reference Sartwell2004) and Scruton (Reference Scruton2014).

29. Mothersill (Reference Mothersill1984).

30. On the idea that different conceptions of the good can give rise to a plurality of conceptions of beauty, see Cooper (Reference Cooper and Keping2010), §§1–2, and Sartwell (Reference Sartwell2004).

31. Aquinas, Summa Theologiae I-II, 27, 1; Augustine, Confessions, book 4, ch. 13, sect. 20.

32. A rich source for the delight etc. inspired by contemporary Buddhists is Samuels (Reference Samuels2010).

33. Balthasar (Reference Balthasar1982), 188, 200, 32, 34, 33.

34. Footnote Ibid ., 32.

35. I am very grateful to David E. Cooper for inspiring and informing my interest in this topic. Thanks also to Rachel Muers, Victor Durà-Vilà, Sara Uckelman, Mark Wynn, Linda Zagzebski, an audience at Leeds, and an anonymous referee.

References

Balthasar, H. U. von (1982) The Glory of the Lord: A Theological Aesthetics, I: Seeing the Form (Edinburgh: T&T Clark.)Google Scholar
Buddha, The (1995) The Long Discourses of the Buddha, Walshe, M. (tr.) (Boston, MA: Wisdom, 1995).Google Scholar
Chawla, N. (2003) Mother Teresa: The Centenary Edition (New Delhi: Penguin), 285286.Google Scholar
Cooper, D. E. (2008) ‘Beautiful people, beautiful things’, British Journal of Aesthetics, 48.3, 247260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cooper, D. E. (2010) ‘Edification and the experience of beauty’, in Keping, W. (ed.) Diversity and Universality in Aesthetics (Beijing: Institute for Transcultural Studies), 6280.Google Scholar
Cooper, D. E. (2014) ‘Religion without faith?’, paper read at the workshop Faith, Trust, and Religious Belief, Durham University, 16 July 2014.Google Scholar
Cooper, D. E. (forthcoming) ‘Buddhism, beauty, and virtue’, in Sikka, S., Maira, S., & Higgins, K. (eds), The End of Art and the Promise of Beauty (Dordrecht: Springer).Google Scholar
Cottingham, J. (2005) The Spiritual Dimension: Philosophy, Religion, and Human Values (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davies, O. (2004) ‘The theological aesthetics’, in Oakes, E. T. & Moss, D. (eds) The Cambridge Companion to Hans Urs von Balthasar (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 131142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, H. (2005) On Bullshit (Princeton: Princeton University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harcourt, E. (2001) ‘Nietzsche and the “aesthetics of character”’, in May, S. (ed.) On the Genealogy of Morality: A Critical Guide (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), 265284.Google Scholar
Inayat Khan, H. (2013) The Heart of Sufism: Essential Writings of Hazrat Inayat Khan (Boston: Shambhala Press).Google Scholar
Kirwan, J. (1999) Beauty (Manchester: Manchester University Press).Google Scholar
Moss, D. (2004) ‘The saints’, in Oakes, E. T. & Moss, D. (eds) The Cambridge Companion to Hans Urs von Balthasar (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 7992.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mothersill, M. (1984) Beauty Restored (Oxford: Clarendon).Google Scholar
Mrozick, S. (2007) Virtuous Bodies: The Physical Dimensions of Morality in Buddhist Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nārada, M. (ed. and tr.) (2007) A Comprehensive Manual of Abhidhamma: The Abhidhammattha Sangha of Ācariya Anuruddha (Kandy: Buddhist Publication Society).Google Scholar
Nehru, J. (1962) An Autobiography (Bombay: Allied Publishers).Google Scholar
Novitz, D. (1991) ‘Love, friendship, and the aesthetics of character’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 28.3, 207216.Google Scholar
Rūmī, J-D. (2012) Selected Poems of Rūmī (New York: Dover).Google Scholar
Samuels, J. (2010) Attracting the Heart: Social Relations and the Aesthetics of Emotion in Sri Lankan Monastic Culture (Honolulu: University of Hawai'i Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sartwell, C. (2004) Six Names of Beauty (London: Routledge).Google Scholar
Scruton, R. (2009), Beauty (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009).Google Scholar
Scruton, R. (2014) The Soul of the World (Princeton: Princeton University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sherman, N. (2005) ‘Of manners and morals’, British Journal of Educational Studies, 53.3, 272289.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wijayaratna, M. (1990) Buddhist Monastic Life: According to the Texts of the Theravada Tradition, Grangier, C. & Collins, S. (trs) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, B. (2002) Truth and Truthfulness: An Essay in Genealogy (Princeton: Princeton University Press).Google Scholar
Wynn, M. (2013) Renewing the Senses: A Study in the Philosophy and Theology of the Spiritual Life (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zagzebski, L. (2010) ‘Exemplarist virtue theory’, Metaphilosophy, 41, 4157.CrossRefGoogle Scholar