Introduction
The topic of the significance of the figure of the ‘saint’, who over the course of history has often stood as an ideal for human existence, is one that preoccupied Nietzsche throughout his writings. Yet, his account of the saintly ideal has received surprisingly little attention in the scholarly literature.Footnote 1 It will be my task in this essay to examine Nietzsche's understanding of the saintly ideal with an aim to bringing out its philosophical importance, particularly with respect to what I call the problem of ‘cosmodicy’, i.e., the problem of justifying life in the world as worthwhile in light of the prevalent reality of suffering.Footnote 2
For those familiar with Nietzsche's writings it is known that in his early work ‘Schopenhauer as Educator’, the third of his Untimely Meditations, Nietzsche regarded the figure of the saint, along with the philosopher and the artist, as one of the highest human exemplars towards which culture should aspire. Although it is acknowledged – e.g., by Walter Kaufmann – that Nietzsche later removed the figure of the saint from this triumvirate of human exemplars, what has been overlooked is the fact that his understanding of the saint itself underwent change.Footnote 3 In his early account Nietzsche understood the saint as embodying the supreme achievement of a self-transcending ‘feeling of oneness and identity with all living things’, while in his later account he viewed the saint as a representative of an unhealthy, life-denying ‘ascetic ideal’. This shift, I contend, is due in large part to Nietzsche's development of an ‘ethic of power’ as part of his turn against Schopenhauer's ethic of compassion, which needs to be seen in light of his ongoing effort to articulate and defend an adequate cosmodicy. My ultimate aim in this essay is to read the earlier Nietzsche against the later Nietzsche – with the help of Dostoevsky's novelistic depiction of the saintly ideal – and to suggest that when properly articulated the saintly ideal is able to provide a more adequate cosmodicy than that which is offered in Nietzsche's ethic of power. However, we must first begin by considering in more detail Nietzsche's earlier and later accounts of the saintly ideal.
Cosmodicy and the Saintly Ideal
In ‘Schopenhauer as Educator’ Nietzsche is centrally concerned with addressing the problem of cosmodicy, as indeed he is throughout much of his work. In other words, he is concerned with the question of how our life in the world is to be justified as worthwhile in light of the prevalent reality of suffering.Footnote 4 That life should require justification is only the case if life presents itself to us as prima facie problematic with respect to its worthwhileness. By taking extensive suffering as the main problematic feature of life in light of which justification is required, Nietzsche is following Schopenhauer. For Nietzsche and Schopenhauer, this problem becomes especially acute for those ‘good Europeans’, like themselves, who no longer regard as tenable any religious interpretation of the world as purposefully ordered according to ‘the goodness and governance of a god’.Footnote 5 As both realize, even if one no longer regards theodicy as viable, this still leaves the problem of ‘cosmodicy’ (though neither uses this term). Indeed, theodicy is only the most historically dominant form in which the problem of cosmodicy has been addressed. Schopenhauer of course did not think that life could be justified given his view of the all-encompassing reality of suffering due to the insatiable and contradictory nature of the will and thus he advocated the resignation of the ‘will to life’. Nietzsche, for his part, sought to overcome Schopenhauer's pessimism (i.e., ‘nihilism’) through providing a perspective according to which one could affirm all of life, including suffering. ‘Schopenhauer as Educator’ represents one of his most significant early attempts (along with The Birth of Tragedy) to overcome Schopenhauer's pessimism and provide a justification for human existence.
According to Nietzsche in ‘Schopenhauer as Educator’, what is needed in order to justify our existence is to provide suffering with a higher purpose or meaning sufficient to make life worth living. However, doing so requires that human beings transcend their animality, since for animals as mere animals all suffering must remain ‘senseless suffering’ without any higher significance.Footnote 6 What is distinctive about being human is precisely the capacity to transcend our animality and ‘turn the thorn of suffering against itself’ by providing it with a higher sense of significance.Footnote 7 Above all, Nietzsche claims, this higher sense of significance is provided by those true human beings who ‘are no longer animal’: viz., the philosopher, the artist, and the saint.Footnote 8 These three figures stand as the highest human exemplars precisely because of the ways in which they are able to utilize suffering for the sake of great achievements that go far beyond what is possible for non-human animals. In doing so they provide suffering with a ‘higher significance’ as well as a perspective from which life in the world can be justified. Thus Nietzsche contends: ‘It is the fundamental idea of culture, insofar as it sets for each one of us but one task: to promote the production of the philosopher, the artist and the saint within us and without us and thereby to work at the perfecting of nature’.Footnote 9 Likewise, he says: ‘Mankind must work continually at the production of individual great men – that and nothing else is its task. […] How can your life, the individual life, receive the highest value, the deepest significance? […] Certainly only by your living for the good of the rarest and most valuable exemplars’.Footnote 10
It should be noted that there is much in these remarks that prefigures Nietzsche's later philosophy, especially his statements about the ‘overman’ (Übermensch) in the prologue to Thus Spoke Zarathustra. The noticeable difference is the inclusion of the saint, along with the philosopher and the artist, as one of the highest human exemplars. In a remarkable passage from ‘Schopenhauer as Educator’, Nietzsche describes his understanding of the saint in the following terms:
And so nature at last needs the saint, in whom the ego is completely melted away and whose life of suffering is no longer felt as his own life – or is hardly so felt – but as a profound feeling of oneness and identity with all living things: the saint in whom there appears that miracle of transformation which the game of becoming never hits upon, that final and supreme becoming-human after which all nature presses and urges for its redemption from itself. It is incontestable that we are all related and allied to the saint, just as we are related to the philosopher and artist; there are moments and as it were bright sparks of the fire of love in whose light we cease to understand the word ‘I’, there lies something beyond our being which at these moments moves across into it, and we are thus possessed of a heartfelt longing for bridges between here and there.Footnote 11
Although there are no specific ‘religious’ references here, Nietzsche's understanding of the saint in this passage is in fact similar in spirit to the kind of understanding of the saintly ideal that we find in many of the great religious traditions: i.e., the understanding of the saint as embodying the supreme achievement of the religious life in self-transcending communion with all being.Footnote 12 We also find here the apparent influence of Schopenhauer's moral ideal of ‘compassion’. According to Schopenhauer, compassion ‘presupposes that to a certain extent I have identified myself with the other man, and in consequence the barrier between the ego and the non-ego is for the moment abolished’.Footnote 13 Thus, for the compassionate person ‘others are not non-ego for him, but an “I once more”’.Footnote 14 Lastly, it is striking that Nietzsche describes the saintly ideal as the ‘final and supreme becoming-human after which all nature presses and urges for its redemption from itself’, which appears to suggest that the saint transcends even the philosopher and the artist in importance.Footnote 15
This passage becomes all the more remarkable once we consider the contrast with Nietzsche's later understanding of the saint after he had removed this figure from his earlier triumvirate of human exemplars. The following passage from Beyond Good and Evil exemplifies Nietzsche's later understanding of the saint. He remarks:
So far the most powerful human beings have still bowed worshipfully before the saint as the riddle of self-conquest and deliberate final renunciation. Why did they bow? In him – and as it were behind the question mark of his fragile and miserable appearance – they sensed the superior force that sought to test itself in such conquest, the strength of the will in which they recognized and honored their own strength and delight in dominion: they honored something in themselves when they honored the saint. Moreover, the sight of the saint awakened a suspicion in them: such an enormity of denial, of anti-nature will not have been desired for nothing, they said to and asked themselves. There may be a reason for it, some very great danger about which the ascetic, thanks to his secret comforters and visitors, might have inside information. In short, the powerful of the world learned a new fear before him; they sensed a new power, a strange, as yet unconquered enemy – it was the “will to power” that made them stop before the saint.Footnote 16
We can observe here that Nietzsche no longer views the saint as one of the highest human exemplars who justifies life through the achievement of a self-transcending ‘feeling of oneness and identity with all living things’. Instead, the saint, like the figure of the ‘ascetic priest’ in the third essay of On the Genealogy of Morals, is now regarded as an embodiment of an unhealthy, life-denying ‘ascetic ideal’.
In the Genealogy Nietzsche describes this ‘ascetic ideal’ as fundamentally concerned with the task of providing meaning for suffering. But rather than doing so in a way that justifies human existence, it brings ‘fresh suffering with it, deeper, more inward, more poisonous, more life-destructive suffering’.Footnote 17 This is because the ascetic ideal interprets all suffering as just punishment for sin, which gives rise to feelings of guilt and the desire to deny our instinctual drives to life, such as sensuality, pride, lust to rule, avarice, and vengefulness – all of which are expressed in the fundamental instinct of the ‘will to power’.Footnote 18 Thus, the ascetic ideal looks for redemption from suffering either in the annihilation of the ego (as in Buddhism) or in another life (as in Christianity). For Nietzsche, these two modes of ‘redemption’ from suffering in fact amount to the same thing: ‘the desire for unio mystica with God is the desire of the Buddhist for nothingness, Nirvana – and no more!’Footnote 19 Indeed, in the case of the saint, the ascetic ideal is simply ‘a pretext for hibernation, […] their repose in nothingness (“God”), their form of madness’.Footnote 20 He concludes then that the meaning of the ascetic ideal is that ‘man would rather will nothingness than not will’.Footnote 21 In other words, the ascetic ideal is essentially a desire for power over the conditions of life itself, which is the direction the will to power takes in those individuals who are not healthy or powerful enough to affirm all of life, including suffering as a precondition for growth in the will to power.Footnote 22
With this stark contrast in place between Nietzsche's earlier and later understandings of the saint, we must now turn to examine the reasons for this shift.
Nietzsche contra Schopenhauer
The shift in Nietzsche's understanding of the saint can be observed starting from Human, All Too Human, which was published four years after ‘Schopenhauer as Educator’.Footnote 23 It is significant that it was starting with this work that Nietzsche also began his campaign against Schopenhauer's morality of compassion (or ‘pity’, as the German word Mitleid is often translated in Nietzsche's works). This is significant precisely because of the apparent influence of Schopenhauer's ideal of compassion on Nietzsche's earlier account of the saint. In the preface to the Genealogy Nietzsche describes his campaign against Schopenhauer's morality of compassion starting from Human, All Too Human and onwards as follows:
What was at stake was the value of morality – and over this I had to come to terms almost exclusively with my great teacher Schopenhauer […]. What was especially at stake was the value of the “unegoistic,” the instincts of pity, self-abnegation, self-sacrifice, which Schopenhauer had gilded, deified, and projected into a beyond for so long that at last they became for him “value-in-itself,” on the basis of which he said No to life and to himself.Footnote 24
The reference here to Schopenhauer projecting the value of the ‘unegoistic’ (i.e., ‘selflessness’) into a ‘beyond’ such that it had ‘value-in-itself’ alludes to his attempt to account for the reality and value of ‘selfless’ compassion for others in a world otherwise driven by egoistic desires. Schopenhauer did so by positing a metaphysical monism with the help of the resources of Kantian epistemology: i.e., he claimed that individuality is only an appearance in the ‘phenomenal’ realm of space and time, whereas in the ‘noumenal’ realm of the ‘thing-in-itself’ all beings are a manifestation of a single ‘blindly striving will’.Footnote 25 Compassion is possible for a person then on the basis of ‘recognizing in another his own self, his own true inner nature’.Footnote 26 Moreover, it is precisely because in compassion we realize our true numerical identity with others in the noumenal realm of the ‘thing-in-itself’ that compassion can be considered to have ‘value-in-itself’.
For Nietzsche, Schopenhauer's devaluation of the individual self and the natural world in favor of a realm ‘beyond’ the natural world where the ego is annihilated in the ‘metaphysical identity’ of all being essentially amounts to saying ‘no’ to life. In other words, Schopenhauer's morality of compassion is simply a form of nihilism, i.e., a ‘new Buddhism’.Footnote 27 Therefore, in his campaign against the morality of compassion, starting in Human, All Too Human, Nietzsche sought to show how so-called ‘selfless’ motives of compassion could be accounted for without appealing to any metaphysical realm beyond the natural world. In doing so he also hoped to show how these so-called ‘selfless’ motives are actually driven by ‘ulterior motives’ that are egoistic, or ‘human, all too human’.Footnote 28 Ultimately, Nietzsche would account for these ‘all too human’ or egoistic motives in terms of his doctrine of the will to power, which seeks to explain ‘our entire instinctive life as the development and ramification of one basic form of will – namely of the will to power’.Footnote 29 In short, the fundamental, all-encompassing instinctual drive of each individual human life is the continual striving for greater power or ‘empowerment’ through overcoming limitations or resistances.Footnote 30 The resistances to be overcome here can be something internal to the agent, such as a psychological or motivational inhibition (e.g., fear), or something external to the agent, such as factors in one's physical and social environments.Footnote 31 Overcoming internal resistances can take the form of self-mastery (hence the role of the will to power in Nietzsche's account of the ascetic ideal), whereas overcoming external resistances can take the form of domination, control, exploitation, or appropriation. Nietzsche writes: ‘life itself is essentially appropriation, injury, overpowering of what is alien and weaker; suppression, hardness, imposition of one's own forms, incorporation and at least, at its mildest, exploitation […]. “Exploitation” does not belong to a corrupt or imperfect and primitive society: it belongs to the essence of what lives, as a basic organic function; it is a consequence of the will to power, which is after all the will of life’.Footnote 32
On the basis of his doctrine of the will to power Nietzsche seeks to articulate an ‘ethic of power’, which he thinks is able to affirm life in the world as worthwhile, unlike Schopenhauer's morality of compassion. He writes: ‘What is good? – Everything that heightens the feeling of power in man, the will to power, power itself. What is bad? – Everything that is born of weakness. What is happiness? – The feeling that power is growing, that resistance is overcome’.Footnote 33 Such an ethic of power affirms suffering as part of a worthwhile life because it regards suffering as integral to the process of overcoming resistance and achieving greatness in the expression of the will to power (e.g., in artistic, athletic, or intellectual achievement).Footnote 34 Moreover, for Nietzsche, the greatest expression of the will to power is found in the ability to say ‘yes’ to all of life, including the prevalent reality of suffering.Footnote 35 In his account of the ‘overman’ in Thus Spoke Zarathustra – the individual who transcends the all-too-human or mediocre level of human achievement by achieving something truly great – we find an idealization of this ethic of power, which offers a rival ideal of self-transcendence to that of the saint.Footnote 36 Instead of self-transcendence in love or concern for others, we have here self-transcendence – or ‘self-overcoming’, as Nietzsche would put it – through continual growth in power, whereby one moves towards ever more enhanced forms of achievement in overcoming limitations or resistances.Footnote 37 For Nietzsche, this represents the ideal of a healthy, life-affirming expression of the will to power. As aforementioned, he believes that the will to power is operative in all of human life, including in the so-called ‘selfless’ motives of the morality of compassion. But in this latter case, he thinks that the will to power takes an unhealthy, life-denying form and thus represents a bad or inadequate expression of the will to power.
We can take the following passage from the Genealogy as an example of Nietzsche's method of interpreting so-called ‘selfless’ motives of concern for others as mere expressions of an individual's will to power:
[By] prescribing “love of neighbor,” the ascetic priest prescribes fundamentally an excitement of the strongest, most life-affirming drive, even if in the most cautious doses – namely, of the will to power. The happiness of “slight superiority,” involved in all doing good, being useful, helping, and rewarding, is the most effective means of consolation for the physiologically inhibited.Footnote 38
In other words, such compassion or love of neighbor is essentially an expression of the will to power over others in those who are too weak to express such power in a more honest and direct manner. This is why the morality of compassion (Mitleid) is better rendered as the morality of ‘pity’ in translations of Nietzsche's writings since it involves a kind of looking down on another person, rather than a ‘feeling-with’ another person (as the word compassion suggests).
Nietzsche argues that to regard such pity or ‘love of neighbor’ as a moral ideal is in fact inimical to life understood as will to power. First of all, he thinks it is bad for the person pitied because it transgresses against his or her pride or self-esteem.Footnote 39 Secondly, he thinks it is bad for the pitier because it makes suffering contagious and has a ‘depressing effect’ on the fundamental instinct of life – viz., the will to power – such that we are deprived of our strength and vitality.Footnote 40 Moreover, he thinks that the morality of pity is an expression of a ‘slave morality’ in those who are too weak to honestly and directly express the will to power – unlike those who hold to the ‘master morality’ – and hence they do so indirectly through condescending pity and the ascetic ideal.Footnote 41 However, the problem is that these indirect expressions of the will to power are actually counter-productive to realizing the fullest and most life-affirming expressions of the will to power. We have already seen how Nietzsche claims that the ascetic ideal seeks to deny our instinctual drives to life. In regard to the morality of pity, he sees it as putting forward an ideal of ‘selflessness’ in concern for others that stands opposed to the honest and direct expression of individual will to power. The ideal of selflessness enjoins a concern for the weak that distracts us from pursuing our own self-enhancement and from encouraging the development of strong and creative individuals who are capable of fully affirming life, including suffering, and who through their greatness in power can justify existence.Footnote 42
Ultimately, Nietzsche regards the morality of pity as the ‘practice of nihilism’ as it expresses ‘hostility to life’.Footnote 43 It seeks to do away with suffering, but since life is necessarily bound up with suffering, Nietzsche sees this as an attempt to do away with life itself. Suffering must be affirmed as a necessary part of growth in the will to power; only in this way can we achieve an adequate cosmodicy.Footnote 44 In one of his most chilling passages, Nietzsche goes so far as to say: ‘Quite in general, pity crosses the law of development, which is the law of selection. It preserves what is ripe for destruction; it defends those who have been disinherited and condemned by life; and by the abundance of the failures of all kinds which it keeps alive, it gives life itself a gloomy and questionable aspect’.Footnote 45 We are here miles away from his earlier idealization of the saint. However, it is important to note that elsewhere in his later writings Nietzsche says that he is not opposed to all forms of pity and beneficence towards others, but to have value they must result from healthy expressions of the will to power or from an ‘overflow’ of strength.Footnote 46 Of course, this hardly can be considered to represent an ideal of ‘selflessness’ since it is an expression of one's own power, which we have seen can also result in cruelty, domination, and exploitation of others.Footnote 47
Now, given this critique of the value of ‘selflessness’ as life-denying, I believe we can see here an important reason why Nietzsche abandoned his earlier account of the saintly ideal as the achievement of a self-transcending ‘feeling of oneness and identity with all living things’: viz., even without accepting Schopenhauer's metaphysical monism, the saintly ideal appears too similar to Schopenhauer's ideal of ‘selflessness’, which is opposed to the will to power as the fundamental instinct of life. We might further assume that Nietzsche's growing opposition to religion also played a role in his reinterpretation and rejection of the saintly ideal, since clearly the ‘saint’ is a figure most commonly associated with religious worldviews, even though Nietzsche's earlier understanding of the saint contained no specific ‘religious’ references.
But we must now ask: is Nietzsche right to abandon the saintly ideal? I think he is not, at least when this ideal is properly understood. Indeed, I will argue that the saintly ideal can offer a better path of cosmodicy than that which is offered in Nietzsche's later work.
The Nature of Love
In the foregoing we have seen that Nietzsche's rejection of the saintly ideal is predicated on his critique of Schopenhauer's morality of compassion. However, apart from Nietzsche's critique, I think we have reason to question Schopenhauer's account of compassion, which also provides reason for questioning Nietzsche's own understanding of compassion or ‘love of neighbor’ as well as the shift in his account of the saint. As we have observed, Schopenhauer attempts to account for the feeling of unity with others in compassion by positing a monistic metaphysic that denies both the value and reality of the individual self. In doing so he was motivated by his acceptance of a Kantian-esque view of the conflict between an individual's desire for his or her own happiness and the requirements of morality, which for Schopenhauer takes the form of an opposition between egoism and compassion, or between self-regarding and other-regarding concern, or finally, between selfishness and selflessness. Nietzsche, as we have seen, questions these dichotomies by arguing that all forms of so-called ‘selfless’ concern for others should be interpreted as in fact egoistic expressions of the will to power. However, I think that we can also question these dichotomies in a different way on the basis of what I believe is a more accurate understanding of the nature of ‘self-transcendence’ in love for others when this love is understood as a kind of interpersonal communion.
To achieve ‘self-transcendence’ in love for others, I contend, is not in fact a form of ‘selflessness’; rather, it involves transcending a normatively ‘lower’, more enclosed mode of selfhood for the sake of a normatively ‘higher’, more extended mode of selfhood in communion with others. By the latter I mean the self that is attained by extending our sense of self through affective identification such that we intersubjectively include the being of others as a part of our own sense of ‘self’.Footnote 48 This constitutes what might be called a ‘we-self’ or ‘communal-self’ in which we experience both the happiness and unhappiness of others as our own and thus we wish and pursue good for them as though for our own self. In this way the dichotomy between self-regarding and other-regarding concern is overcome, since there exists a shared form of happiness such that wishing and pursuing good for others can be considered as both self-regarding and other-regarding.Footnote 49
Now, in saying that this communal-self attained through love of others is a normatively ‘higher’ mode of selfhood I mean to suggest that it also involves transcending a ‘lower good’ for the sake of a ‘higher good’. In other words, we experience a greater sense of fulfillment or fullness of life in communion with others – who are seen as worthy of our love because of their human dignity and perhaps also because of other particular lovable qualities – than we would apart from it since such communion involves affectively including the being and happiness of others as part of our own sense of self and happiness. Thus, love for others is not based merely on commiseration and the desire for the alleviation of others’ suffering, but more positively, it is above all based on the desire for fullness of life in communion with others.Footnote 50
For both Schopenhauer and Nietzsche this understanding of the ‘self’ as intersubjectively extended in communion with others is not adequately recognized because each in his own way tends to presuppose an atomistic conception of the ‘self’, which makes ‘self’-love something inherently narrow and therefore problematic in regard to understanding the motivation for other-regarding concern. Thus, Schopenhauer must presuppose a metaphysical monism in which there is numerical identity between persons in order to make sense of the motive for compassion. But this is unnecessary if we understand love for others as a kind of communion, which preserves the reality and value of the individual within the intersubjective union of love and the shared happiness it makes possible.Footnote 51 As we have seen, Nietzsche, for his part, attempts to account for the motive of other-regarding concern by interpreting such concern in terms of individual expressions of will to power or as the overflow of strength.Footnote 52 However, a key significance of Nietzsche's early understanding of the saint as embodying a self-transcending ‘feeling of oneness and identity with all living things’, I contend, lies in the fact that it shows that he felt moved by something like what I have described as a communion-perspective on the self and human fulfillment – even if he was not able to adequately articulate the experience – which cannot be interpreted as merely an expression of an individual's will to power. If Nietzsche's early account of the saint is understood in this way then I believe that we have reason to question his later rejection of the saintly ideal.
First of all, his early account of the saint presents the possibility of another mode of human fulfillment besides the individual mode of fulfillment achieved through the feeling of power growing in continually overcoming internal and external resistances: viz., human fulfillment through self-transcending communion with others whereby we achieve a normatively higher mode of selfhood through affectively identifying with the being and happiness of others such that they are included within our own extended sense of ‘self’.Footnote 53 In fact, these two modes of human fulfillment need not be regarded as mutually exclusive. The most fulfilling human life can include both fulfillment through self-transcending communion and fulfillment through continually overcoming internal and external resistances in the development of our various human capacities. It should also be noted that of course love itself involves ‘overcoming resistances’ as we grow deeper in communion with another person. But the fulfillment experienced in such communion is not merely the experience of ‘overcoming resistance’. Above all, it is the experience of the communion itself in which we achieve a higher, more extended mode of selfhood through affectively identifying with the being and happiness of others. However, granted that the two ideals of human fulfillment through self-transcendence can both be viewed as part of a holistic account of human fulfillment, there remains the issue of which mode of fulfillment should have priority if a conflict arises.Footnote 54 One important question to ask here is: which mode of fulfillment is more integral to our humanity? I maintain that it is our need for communion with others since it seems that human beings can more easily live without great achievements than without love.Footnote 55 But we can also ask: which provides a more adequate path for justifying life in the world as worthwhile in the face of suffering? I contend that it is the path of love as charted out in a proper understanding of the saintly ideal.
Dostoevsky versus Nietzsche on the Saintly Ideal
In order to make my case here we need a better depiction of the saintly ideal, and for this I turn to the work of Dostoevsky. One of Dostoevsky's central concerns in his fictional work is to provide a realistic portrayal of the ‘saintly ideal’, which will show the significance of Christianity for the modern age.Footnote 56 Indeed, throughout his major works we find a number of ‘saintly types’,Footnote 57 though in what follows I will focus on the depiction of Father Zosima in The Brothers Karamazov, who is based on real exemplars and is arguably Dostoevsky's most successful portrayal of the saintly ideal. Most importantly for my purposes, Zosima's life and teachings offer an especially powerful expression of Dostoevsky's religious views and provide a rival to Nietzsche's solution to the cosmodicy problem.Footnote 58
Zosima is an Elder in the local Orthodox monastery and the spiritual mentor to the youngest Karamazov brother, Alyosha. He is portrayed as a man of deep humility, great compassion, and profound insight into human life.Footnote 59 His two fundamental teachings are that ‘life is paradise’ and that ‘we are responsible to all and for all’. These are in fact related teachings and Zosima takes them over from his brother Markel, who underwent a spiritual transformation as the result of a terminal illness. Zosima reports his brother as saying that ‘life is paradise, and we are all in paradise, but we won't see it, if we would, we should have heaven on earth the next day’.Footnote 60 Then later he reports Markel as saying that ‘we are each responsible to all for all, it's only that men don't know this. If they knew it, the world would be a paradise at once’.Footnote 61 Zosima himself remarks: ‘we don't understand that life is a paradise, for we have only to understand that and it will at once be fulfilled in all its beauty, we shall embrace each other and weep’.Footnote 62
To see life as paradise is clearly an affirmative stance towards the world – i.e., it is to see life as fundamentally good and a source of joy and fulfillment – and Dostoevsky intends this as a response to Ivan Karamazov's rejection of life in the world as worthwhile due to the problem of evil and suffering. The claim then is that life already is paradise, even in the face of evil and suffering, but this paradise can be more fully realized by acknowledging our responsibility to all and for all and by engaging in turn in active love for others and thereby helping to ‘heal the world’.Footnote 63 Moreover, the recognition that life is paradise and that this can be fully realized through active love can inspire such love, though love for others and for the world can also help to more fully appreciate how life is paradise, i.e., it can bring about a transfiguration in the way we see the world.Footnote 64 Zosima teaches:
Love all God's creation, the whole and every grain of sand in it. Love every leaf, every ray of God's light. Love the animals, love the plants, love everything. If you love everything, you will perceive the divine mystery in things. Once you perceive it, you will begin to comprehend it better every day. And you will come at last to love the whole world with an all-embracing love.Footnote 65
We find here in this ‘all-embracing love’ a significant overlap with Nietzsche's early view of the saintly ideal as the achievement of a self-transcending ‘feeling of oneness and identity with all living things’, but there is the additional claim that this love makes possible an awareness of the ‘divine mystery in things’.Footnote 66
Another way to put this, which could appeal to the theist and non-theist alike, is that the saintly ideal – i.e., the ideal of an all-embracing love – seeks to give proper recognition to the sacred character of the world, where the sacred is understood as that which is worthy of reverence. The transfigured vision of the saintly ideal is thus one that takes us from our profane or mundane experience of the world to an experience of the world as imbued with the sacred. Indeed, the claim that life is paradise is often expressed in many of the great religious traditions as the claim that life is sacred, or a sacred gift (a more theistic rendering), which is worthy of being loved, cherished, and revered.Footnote 67 We should see then a crucial element that was missing in the preceding characterizations of the saintly ideal by Nietzsche: viz., the saint is motivated not only by compassion for the suffering of others, but also and more fundamentally by a sense of the sacred, including with regard to these others.Footnote 68 In short, on my view it is the sacred that is most definitive of the saintly ideal as the would-be saint is one who seeks to become holy or sanctified through a proper relationship in feeling and action to what is seen as sacred or holy. Above all, the proper relationship is one of an all-embracing love for the world. But it is important to be clear that this is not mere abstract love. Zosima warns of the danger of ‘love in dreams’ where we abstractly love humanity in general but fail to love human beings in particular. It is important then that an all-embracing love for humanity always find its terminus in ‘active love’ for particular human beings.Footnote 69 One cannot of course actively love everyone, but the feeling of love for everyone – where there is an imaginative affective identification, since we cannot know every individual human being that exists – is still important since it makes us disposed to actively love those particular people who are a part of our lives as well as those who happen to come across our path, as in the Gospel story of the ‘Good Samaritan’.
I believe this picture of the saintly ideal as centered on an all-embracing love ethic provides a much better path for justifying life in the world as worthwhile in the face of suffering than does Nietzsche's rival ideal, which is centered on an ethic of power that finds it fullest expression in those who are able to say ‘yes’ to all of life, including suffering. The fundamental problem with Nietzsche's account is that it does not say why one should say ‘yes’ to life beyond claiming that doing so enhances one's own self-empowerment. In other words, it does not explain what it is about the world that makes it worthy of such affirmation.Footnote 70 The same problem remains if we seek an ‘aesthetic’ justification through artistic creation.Footnote 71 By contrast, the saintly ideal, as I have described it, regards the world as worthy of our affirmation because of its fundamentally sacred character. It is of course true that the saintly ideal does not affirm suffering as such and indeed it often seeks to reduce suffering, and for Nietzsche this means that it fails to affirm all of life, since suffering is a necessary part of life. However, the point of cosmodicy is not to affirm all aspects of life as good – e.g., the prevalence of cruelty, oppression, suffering, and so forth – but to affirm that life is fundamentally good and worthwhile. Nietzsche himself does not affirm all of life since he does not want to affirm the weak and the failures, as they are thought to give life ‘a gloomy and questionable aspect’. In this way the saintly ideal is more ‘life-affirming’ with its all-embracing love ethic.
Now, the foregoing account of the saintly ideal and the claim that it provides a more adequate cosmodicy depend upon being able to affirm that life is sacred and worthy of our love, affirmation, and reverence, which in turn depends upon our overall worldview. In fact, it may depend upon seeing the world as ‘a moral order’ that expresses ‘ultimate moral purposes’, which for Nietzsche is no longer tenable.Footnote 72 However, even if one is not able to believe in such an idea of a moral teleology at work in the universe – and I think this is an open debateFootnote 73 – it is still worth exploring what is at stake in whether or not we do believe in it. What may be at stake in fact is the possibility of a viable cosmodicy. According to William James, the belief or at least hope that the world is a moral order and expresses ultimate moral purposes ‘not only incites our more strenuous moments, but it also takes our joyous, careless, trustful moments, and it justifies them’.Footnote 74 In other words, it can inspire the strenuous activity of making ourselves ‘responsible to all and for all’ in order to heal the world and it also can justify the affirmation that ‘life is paradise’ – i.e., life is fundamentally good and a source of joy and fulfillment – in spite of the evil and suffering that exists.
Consider again Zosima. He claims that we would be altogether lost without the ‘precious image of Christ before us’ and our ‘mysterious sense of our living bond with the other world’. Moreover, if this sense is weakened or destroyed he says that we can then become ‘indifferent to life, and even come to hate it’.Footnote 75 The ‘image of Christ’, for Dostoevsky, represents the perfection of the saintly ideal of an all-embracing love and in a notebook he describes the image of Christ as an ‘eternal ideal toward which man aspires and is bound to aspire according to nature's law’.Footnote 76 Here we see a moral and spiritual teleology at work and Dostoevsky claims that it is in aspiring after and achieving this ideal – or at least approximating it – that our happiness or fulfillment it to be found: ‘the greatest use a man can make of his personality, of the fullest development of his I, is in one way or another to destroy this I, to give himself up wholly to all and everyone, selflessly and wholeheartedly. And that is the greatest happiness’.Footnote 77 While this might at first suggest a total renunciation of the self, I think it is best interpreted in terms of my account of self-transcendence in love: viz., as the transcending of a lower, more enclosed mode of selfhood for the sake of a higher, more extended, more fulfilling mode of selfhood. Hence he speaks of achieving ‘the greatest happiness’. Likewise, Zosima says: ‘people are created for happiness, and he who is completely happy can at once be deemed worthy of saying to himself: “I have fulfilled God's commandment on this earth.” All the righteous, all the saints, all the holy martyrs were happy’.Footnote 78
It is particularly noteworthy that Zosima says that our ‘mysterious sense of our living bond with the other world’ is important for affirming our this-worldly existence due to its connection with a transcendent purpose for human life. This stands in strong contrast to Nietzsche's tendency to see anyone who affirms the ‘transcendent’ or the ‘other-worldly’ as being life-denying. It must be acknowledged that Nietzsche's later understanding and critique of the saintly ideal as embodying an unhealthy, life-denying ‘ascetic ideal’ certainly provides an insightful account of at least the worst representatives of various religious perspectives. However, as we have seen, there are better religious representatives who are affirmative of our this-worldly existence for religious reasons.Footnote 79 Dostoevsky is in fact well aware of the sort of critique that Nietzsche leveled against asceticism. Earlier in The Brothers Karamazov the narrator remarks that ascetic practices are ‘a double-edged weapon, which may lead a person not to humility and ultimate self-control but, on the contrary, to the most satanic pride – that is, to fetters and not to freedom’.Footnote 80 Moreover, in the character Father Ferapont, the great faster and keeper of silence, Dostoevsky provides an artistic portrayal of the kind of unhealthy, life-denying ‘ascetic ideal’ that Nietzsche critiques. For Dostoevsky, however, certain ascetic practices, properly directed, remain important for the moral and spiritual transformation that is needed for growth in self-transcending love for all.
That human life requires such transformation is due to what Dostoevsky describes as the ‘broadness’ of human nature in allowing for fundamentally opposed tendencies.Footnote 81 On the one hand, we find ourselves naturally inclined towards the ideal of self-transcending love wherein our true happiness resides. On the other hand, however, we may also find in ourselves certain opposing motives, including tendencies towards self-enclosure, diabolical pride, and even violence. For Dostoevsky these are directions the ‘thirst for life’ can take when not properly trained and ordered towards the ideal of self-transcending love.Footnote 82 Key to this training (i.e., askesis) is the practice of active love itself. ‘Brothers, love is a teacher’, says Zosima, ‘but one must know how to acquire it, for it is difficult to acquire, it is dearly bought, by long work over a long time, for one ought to love not for a chance moment but for all time’.Footnote 83 Important also are other spiritual practices such as obedience, fasting, and prayer: ‘Obedience, fasting, and prayer are laughed at, yet they alone constitute the way to real and true freedom: I cut away my superfluous and unnecessary [desires], through obedience I humble and chasten my vain and proud will, and thereby, with God's help, attain freedom of spirit, and with that, spiritual rejoicing!’Footnote 84 Ultimately, these spiritual practices seek to enable an all-embracing active love, which is the most truly powerful force in life. Zosima remarks: ‘One may stand perplexed before some thought, especially seeing men's sin, asking oneself: “Shall I take it by force, or by humble love?” Always resolve to take it by humble love. If you so resolve once and for all, you will be able to overcome the whole world. A loving humility is a terrible power, the most powerful of all, nothing compares to it’.Footnote 85 Here we have an important insight – whatever we make of the theological perspective that Dostoevsky couches it in – that is missed in Nietzsche's later account of the saintly ideal.
Conclusion
In the foregoing I have tried to read the earlier Nietzsche against the later Nietzsche and to argue that when properly articulated – with the help of Dostoevsky – the saintly ideal is able to provide a more adequate cosmodicy than that which is found in Nietzsche's later work. Nietzsche was not wrong to move away from Schopenhauer's morality of compassion, but I have argued that he moved in the wrong direction. The right direction involves a move towards a better account of the nature of the saintly ideal of self-transcending love for other persons and for the world.Footnote 86