Published online by Cambridge University Press: 08 September 2005
In the course of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, “culture” achieved the status of a truly global concept. We find discourses of “culture” emerging to prominence in the German-speaking world during the second half of the eighteenth century (with the closely associated linguistic arenas of the Netherlands and Scandinavia rapidly following suit); in the English-speaking world starting in the first half of the nineteenth century; in Eastern Europe, East Asia, and South Asia starting in the second half of the nineteenth century; and just about everywhere else in the course of the twentieth century. “Culture” began to circulate far beyond the European sites of its modern genesis, sometimes through the direct transfer of lexical items from Western European languages (e.g., Russian kulءtura; the use of kalcar in various South Asian languages); and more often through the construction of new translative equivalencies with preexisting words or concepts most often signifying purification, refinement, or improvement (e.g., Japanese bun-ka; Chinese wen-hua; Bangla and Hindi sanskriti; Urdu tamaddun).
I would like to thank Dipesh Chakrabarty, Manu Goswami, Mark Loeffler, Paul Magee, Moishe Postone, Bill Sewell, and the Social Theory Workshop at the University of Chicago for generous feedback on various incarnations of this paper. All opinions, and any errors, are of course my own.
In the course of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, “culture” achieved the status of a truly global concept. We find discourses of “culture” emerging to prominence in the German-speaking world during the second half of the eighteenth century (with the closely associated linguistic arenas of the Netherlands and Scandinavia rapidly following suit); in the English-speaking world starting in the first half of the nineteenth century; in Eastern Europe, East Asia, and South Asia starting in the second half of the nineteenth century; and just about everywhere else in the course of the twentieth century. “Culture” began to circulate far beyond the European sites of its modern genesis, sometimes through the direct transfer of lexical items from Western European languages (e.g., Russian kulءtura; the use of kalcar in various South Asian languages); and more often through the construction of new translative equivalencies with preexisting words or concepts most often signifying purification, refinement, or improvement (e.g., Japanese bun-ka; Chinese wen-hua; Bangla and Hindi sanskriti; Urdu tamaddun).1
For a discussion of the formation of “translative equivalents” as an object of specifically historical study that goes “beyond the deconstructionist stage of trying to prove that equivalencies do not exist” and instead looks “into their manner of becoming,” see Lydia H. Liu, Translingual Practice: Literature, National Culture, and Translated Modernity. China, 1900–1937 (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1995), 16.
However creatively deployed in however divergent a range of contexts, the power, resonance, and usefulness of any conceptual vocabulary must surely derive from the denotative and connotative baggage accumulated in the course of the history of its prior deployment. Any attempt to understand the global dimensions of the dissemination and circulation of modern cultural discourses must proceed, then, from some initial understanding of what was being disseminated and circulated. Without for a moment thinking that a global concept-history could be reducible to its Western origin, we nevertheless might well wonder what the history that preceded the culture-concept's journey beyond the narrower confines of Western Europe might tell us about the logic of its global dissemination. What was this concept, “culture,” that people in these disparate places were adopting? Proceeding from the recognition that this particular concept was found powerful, resonant, and useful in numerous and diverse historical contexts as the appropriate thought-form for certain kinds of social analysis and critique, this paper sets out first of all to challenge the disaggregative instincts of contemporary intellectual historians by identifying a single, broadly pan-European modern culture-concept that has traversed the boundaries of the specific discourse-formations of pedagogy, aesthetics, anthropology, and so on. This culture-concept, I suggest, has articulated a claim about the fundamental underdetermination of human subjectivity, and has done so fairly consistently since its emergence into philosophical importance in the eighteenth century. From the perspective of this analysis, the global dissemination of the culture-concept consequently becomes susceptible to a more systematic historical analysis than is suggested by fragmentary histories of the transmission of intellectual influences or the reproduction of discursive apparatus. Reading the global history of the culture-concept as the dissemination of a category of autonomous agency does not foreclose the investigation of the specific conditions of its reception in particular times and places; rather, it forms the starting point for an investigation into the ubiquitous centrality of discourses of “culture” to critiques of alien bureaucracy, of colonial domination, and of the anarchic and anomic tendencies of commercial society.
Matthew Arnold's well-known espousal of the term “culture” in the 1860s immediately identified him in the eyes of his contemporaries as a spokesman for what the Victorians termed “Germanism.”2
The prominent English Comtean, Frederic Harrison, for instance, wrote good-humoredly of Arnold's “fiddlestick, or sauerkraut, or culture (call it as you please),” in “Culture: A Dialogue,” Fortnightly Review 2 (July–Dec. 1867), 603–14.
In his essay Über Pädagogik (Langensalza: Hermann Beyer and Sons, 1883), Kant refers in §1 to “Unterweisung nebst der Bildung,” and in §7 to “Kultur (so kann man die Unterweisung nennen).” Mendelssohn's contrastive definitions in his essay, “Über die Frage, was heisst aufklären?” are cited in Rudolph Vierhaus, “Bildung,” in O. Brunner, W. Conze, and R. Koselleck, eds., Geschichtliche Grundbegriffe: Historiches Lexikon zur politisch-sozialen Sprache in Deutschland, (Stuttgart: Ernst Klett, 1972), vol. 1, 508.
See Anthony La Vopa, Grace, Talent, and Merit: Poor Students, Clerical Careers, and Professional Ideology in Eighteenth-Century Germany (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), esp. ch. 9; Vierhaus, “Bildung.”
Jörg Fisch, “Zivilisation, Kultur,” in O. Brunner, W. Conze, and R. Kosellek, eds., Geschichtliche Grundbegriffe: Historiches Lexikon zur politisch-sozialen Sprache in Deutschland, (Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, 1992), vol. 7, 685, 700–3; Philippe Bénéton, Histoire de mots: Culture et civilisation (Paris: Presses de la Fondation nationale des sciences politiques, 1975), 30. The OED cites Wordsworth's Preludes (1805) as the earliest example of this stand-alone usage in English, but one could certainly find significantly earlier examples.
“Culture” has had a long and intimate relationship with the more expansive concept of civilization, a term that emerged in mid-eighteenth-century French (and English very soon thereafter) with the aspiration to unite the disparate themes of police, politesse, civilité, and doux commerce under the single heading of an overarching social process.6
Lucien Febvre, “Civilisation: Evolution of a Word and a Group of Ideas,” in Peter Burke, ed., A New Kind of History (New York: Harper and Row, 1973), 219–57; and Emile Benveniste, “Civilization: A Contribution to the History of the Word,” Problems in General Linguistics (Coral Gables, Fl.: University of Miami Press, 1971), 289–96.
Cf. Fisch, “Zivilisation, Kultur,” 679.
But the concept has also been slipperier than such an easy translative equation might suggest. “The German word Kultur,” explained W. D. Robson-Scott in a footnote to his 1928 translation of Freud's Future of an Illusion, “has been translated sometimes as ‘culture' and sometimes as ‘civilization,' denoting as it does a concept intermediate between these and at times inclusive of both.”8
Sigmund Freud, The Future of an Illusion, W. D. Robson-Scott, trans. (London: Hogarth Press, 1943), 7 (n. 1).
La Vopa, Grace, Talent, and Merit, 264–78.
Norbert Elias, The Civilizing Process (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), 3–28.
Fisch, “Zivilisation, Kultur,” 681–82, 714–15, 722 (n. 246), 749–52; Bénéton, Histoire de mots, chs. 4–5.
In fact, it is worth noting that Elias himself began his discussion with the more nuanced recognition that “the function of the German concept of Kultur took on a new life in the year 1919,” but that in doing so it was reactivating and re-appropriating an older conceptual antithesis that had its “concrete point of departure” in the “significantly different” historical context of the late eighteenth century. See Elias, Civilizing Process, 7. This was a nuance to which Herbert Marcuse was also drawing attention more or less contemporarily, and without at all reducing the concept to its nationalistic homology: “Although the distinction between civilization and culture may have joined only recently the mental equipment of the social and cultural sciences, the state of affairs that it expresses has long been characteristic of the conduct of life and the weltanschauung of the bourgeois era.” Herbert Marcuse, “The Affirmative Character of Culture,” in Negations: Essays in Critical Theory (Boston: Beacon, 1968), 88–133. On the other hand, T.C.W. Blanning has recently restated the importance of the conceptual opposition between Frenchness and Germanness in his The Culture of Power and the Power of Culture: Old Regime Europe 1660–1789 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), 232–65.
David Blackbourn has briefly but suggestively linked the emergence of “cultural” discourses in late nineteenth-century Germany to the economic instability of the Great Depression of 1873–1896, and thereby helped to locate the specificities of these discourses within an international frame, in “The Discrete Charm of the Bourgeoisie: Reappraising German History in the Nineteenth Century,” in David Blackbourn and Geoff Eley, eds., The Peculiarities of German History: Bourgeois Society and Politics in Nineteenth-Century Germany (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984), 206–21. On the role of Treitschke in leading the shift in German attitudes toward England from the 1870s, see Charles E. McClelland, The German Historians and England: A Study in Nineteenth-Century Views (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1971), part IV. Fritz Ringer has given the best-known account of the German academy's renewed emphasis on the culture/civilization dichotomy in the later nineteenth century, in The Decline of the German Mandarins: The German Academic Community, 1890–1933 (Hanover, N.H.: Wesleyan University Press, 1990).
Conversely, writers in English, drawing directly on these German intellectual influences, would adopt the words “culture” or “cultivation” whenever a distinction from “civilization” was implied.14
Raymond Williams has provided the classic account of the English tradition of cultural criticism in Culture and Society: 1780–1950 (New York: Columbia University Press, 1983).
John Morrow, ed., Coleridge's Writings, Volume 1: On Politics and Society (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1991), 176.
Matthew Arnold, Culture and Anarchy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1963), 48–49.
Bénéton, Histoire de mots, 56–59, 73–76.
Jean Starobinski, Blessings in Disguise; or, The Morality of Evil (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1993), ch. 1.
See Jan Goldstein, “Mutations of the Self in Old Regime and Postrevolutionary France,” in Lorraine Daston, ed., Biographies of Scientific Objects (Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 2000), 86–116. Cousin, Bénéton notes (Histoire de mots, 56–57), was also instrumental in introducing the French public to the philosophies of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel.
For a liberal like François Guizot, the distinction between the moral and material dimensions of human progress, while clearly conceived, was nonetheless contained within the larger process of civilisation, which was the higher synthesis of its two equally necessary subordinate elements.20
See Francois Guizot, General History of Civilization in Europe from the Fall of the Roman Empire to the French Revolution (New York: D. Appleton, 1928).
A. L. Kroeber and Clyde Kluckhohn, Culture: A Critical Review of Concepts and Definitions (New York: Vintage, 1963), 29–30.
John Stuart Mill, On Liberty, in The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, Volume XXI: Essays on Equality, Law and Education (Toronto, Buffalo, and London: University of Toronto Press and Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1984); and see also Wilhelm von Humboldt, The Limits of State Action (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969).
Yet one can see how easily this kind of liberal culturalism could slip into a culture/civilization opposition: while Mill would on the one hand posit liberty and culture as mutually reinforcing and complementary principles, he could also call for the cultivation of higher virtues on the part of university elites to counter the dangerous leveling effects of the democratized mass-society that “civilization” had called forth.23
John Stuart Mill, “Civilization,” in The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, Volume XVIII: Essays on Politics and Society (Toronto, Buffalo, and London: University of Toronto Press and Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1977), 117–47.
Fraser Neimann, ed., Essays, Letters, and Reviews by Matthew Arnold (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1960), 105; Arnold, Culture and Anarchy, 75, 82, 95–97.
See David Lloyd and Paul Thomas, Culture and the State (New York and London: Routledge, 1998).
Stefan Collini has written persuasively concerning the ubiquity of anxieties about the social consequences of the generalized pursuit of self-interest in Britain in the second half of the nineteenth century, noting Victorian social critics' “obsessive antipathy to selfishness” and their “constant anxiety about the possibility of sinking into a state of psychological malaise or anomie, a kind of emotional entropy assumed to be the consequence of absorption in purely selfish aims,” in Public Moralists: Political Thought and Intellectual Life in Britain, 1850–1930 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991), 65.
Seen from this wider perspective, we might suggest that the culture-concept enjoyed a precarious universality within the European cosmopolis constituted by the heritage of Latin cosmopolitanism and the subsequent history of modern vernacular interpenetration. Yes, this universality was shot through with different emphases, degrees of prominence, discursive functions, homological transformations, and ideological implications within particular national and linguistic arenas. And of course, the instabilities of two centuries of usage render any single and exhaustive definitional generalization outrageous at a strictly lexical level. Yet in the end it seems undeniable that the concept's major fault-lines have followed less the contours of different languages than certain internal semantic differentiations.
The well-known “review” of the history of the culture-concept undertaken by Alfred Kroeber and Clyde Kluckhohn identified two of the most prominent of these semantic fault-lines. To begin with, the distinction between culture and civilization in Germany seemed, they not unreasonably noted, to correlate with “the spirit-nature dichotomy—Geist und Natur—that so deeply penetrated German thought from the eighteenth to the twentieth century.”27
Kroeber and Kluckhohn, Culture, 26.
“Civilization,” explained Wilhelm von Humboldt, Kroeber and Kluckhohn's most important exemplar of this alternative tradition, “is the humanization of peoples in their outward institutions and customs, and the inner attitudes pertaining thereto. Culture adds science and art to this refinement of the social order.”28
Wilhelm von Humboldt, On Language: On the Diversity of Human Language Construction and Its Influence on the Mental Development of the Human Species (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 34; Kroeber and Kluckhohn, Culture, 26.
Humboldt, On Language, 34–35.
Ibid., 35.
Even in his earlier circumstance, man transcends the present moment, and does not remain sunk in mere sensual enjoyment. Among the roughest tribes we find a love of adornment, dancing, music and song, and beyond that forebodings of a world to come, the hopes and anxieties founded on this, and traditions and tales which commonly go back to the origin of man and of his abode. The more strongly and brightly does the spiritual power, working independently by its own laws and forms of intuition, pour out its light into this world of the past and future, with which man surrounds his existence of the moment, the more purely and variously does the mass [of his creative energy], simultaneously, take shape. Thus do science and art arise, and the goal, therefore, of mankind's developing progress is always the fusion of what is produced independently from within with what is given from without, each grasped in its purity and completeness, and bound into the subjection which the current endeavour by its nature demands.31
Ibid., 30.
For Humboldt, “contact with the world” and “communication of outer exertion and inner perceptions” turn out to be irreducibly necessary for the actual “formation of character” that Bildung names.32
Ibid., 23, 30–31.
La Vopa, Grace, Talent, and Merit, 272.
Humboldt, On Language, 34.
Humboldt's emphasis on Kultur as the practical expression of subjective freedom was fundamentally inspired by Kantian idealism. Kant himself had defined Kultur as the process of “[p]roducing in a rational being an aptitude for purposes generally (hence [in a way that leaves] that being free),” where such “aptitude for purposes generally” included both “man's aptitude in general for setting himself purposes,” and his aptitude “for using nature (independently of [the element of] nature in man's determination of purposes) as a means [for achieving them] in conformity with the maxims of his free purposes generally.”35
Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgment, Werner S. Pluhar, trans. (Indianapolis: Hacket, 1987), §83, 319, translator's interpolations.
In the first critique, Kant had juxtaposed discipline and culture as negative to positive: the restraint and extirpation of our natural inclination to contravene the dictates of reason, versus the acquisition of skills that can be used to any given end, which may or may not be in accordance with reason. Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, Norman Kemp Smith, trans. (Houndmills, New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2003), 575 (A 709–10, B 737–38). The formulation just cited from the third critique, however, recognizes that an aptitude is only “culture” (i.e., a properly human aptitude) if it is grounded in the “culture of discipline,” that is, in the free subjectivity of a rational will.
Immanuel Kant, “Idea for a Universal History from a Cosmopolitan Point of View,” in Lewis White Beck, ed., On History: Immanuel Kant (New York: Macmillan, 1963), 21.
“Culture” in this usage might seem, as Raymond Geuss has argued, a profoundly individualized, and even utterly asocial, category.38
Raymond Geuss makes this claim in “Kultur, Bildung, Geist,” in his Morality, Culture and History: Essays on German Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 33–34.
Immanuel Kant, Über Pädagogik, §3–4, my emphasis.
Cf. Robert B. Pippin, Idealism as Modernism: Hegelian Variations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), chs. 3 and 4; Allen W. Wood, Kant's Ethical Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999); and Yirmiahu Yovel, Kant and the Philosophy of History (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1980).
Kant, “Conjectural Beginning of Human History,” in Beck, ed., On History, 60–63.
Seen from this perspective, the relationship between what Kroeber and Kluckhohn identified as “contrary” currents of usage appears much less opaque: both Kant and Humboldt agreed that technical prowess could be the logical extension of the critical constitution of the self as a self-determining (autonomous) subject. Even when it seemed to name an instrumental relationship to res extensa, “culture” ultimately and crucially retained its affiliation with the “spirit” side of the classic antinomy. But more importantly, we can already identify in these most proto-Hegelian (but still ultimately subject-centered) moments of Kant's philosophy the key problematic that has consistently defined the culture-concept: the practical realization of free subjectivity.
Kroeber and Kluckhohn, however, viewed this first genealogical puzzle as an anachronism that could be largely consigned (as, in their opinion, “mainly an episode in German thought”) to the pre-history of the “scientific” culture-concept that was at the heart of their concerns.42
Kroeber and Kluckhohn, Culture, 29.
Ibid., 284. Proceeding from this anthropological universalization of “culture,” the older part-whole relationship of “culture” and “civilization” could be reversed, so that “civilization” could specify that subset of “cultures” that had achieved certain levels of technical advancement. See for example Robert Redfield, “Civilizations as Things Thought About,” in Margaret Park Redfield, ed., Human Nature and the Study of Society: The Papers of Robert Redfield, Volume I (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962), 367–71.
Analytically, then, it would be quite straightforward to assume, as so many have, that the humanistic and anthropological conceptions are in a straightforward sense definitionally distinct. “Culture,” in other words, was simply a homonym. But a historical investigation cannot afford to leap directly to this analytical premise, without first lingering over some important questions: Why have these two analytically distinct dimensions of the culture-concept been so ubiquitously conflated in actual usage (hence provoking the need for recurrent analytical clarifications, of which Kroeber and Kluckhohn's own review merely stands as the best known)? And if the humanistic meanings of the word, “culture,” long predate its ethnological meanings, what was it about that earlier usage that made the word available for its new role as the foundational concept of an emergent discipline of “cultural anthropology”?
Genealogies of anthropological culture most commonly begin with German Romanticism, and more particularly with Herder's pluralistic organicism as the antithesis of Kant's abstract universalism. They all too rarely take stock of the fact, however, that Herder's pluralism revolved around the concept of Volk, not Kultur.44
Raymond Williams appears to be partly responsible for the ubiquity of this misrepresentation. See Keywords: A Vocabulary of Culture and Society (New York: Oxford University Press, 1983), 89.
Johann Gottfried von Herder, Reflections on the Philosophy of the History of Mankind (Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 1968, abr. ed.), 100–1; and cf. Fisch, “Zivilisation, Kultur,” 708–12.
Herder, Philosophy of the History of Mankind, 110–11.
Herder, Philosophy of the History of Mankind, 84, my emphasis.
Kroeber and Kluckhohn, Culture, 35–38.
Whether used in the singular as a horizontal conceptual distinction within social process or as a vertical distinction between different social groups, anthropological “culture” has always taken plurality and diversity as its defining object. One can in fact trace through the course of the nineteenth century the gradual “reification” of the culture-concept, along with the word's consequent pluralization.49
Fisch, “Zivilisation, Kultur,” 746–48.
George W. Stocking, Jr., Race, Culture and Evolution: Essays in the History of Anthropology (New York: Free Press, 1968), 72–73.
Whether we are talking about “culture” as such, or the various “cultures” that differ from one another, the category has emerged as a term of social analysis in constitutive contradistinction to objective determinations. Freud, for instance, would define both functions of Kultur—“to protect men against nature and to adjust their mutual relations”—in terms of the imposition of the restriction and sublimation of the primordial instinctual drives of the individual.51
Sigmund Freud, Civilization and Its Discontents (New York, London: W. W. Norton, 1961), 36–50.
Alternatively, “culture” has been analytically juxtaposed to other dimensions of the social that are organized by what are understood to be objectively necessary abstract laws, such as the “economy” or “society.” Adam Kuper has persuasively argued that Talcott Parsons' tripartite anatomy of the structure of social action was not only central to laying the foundations for anthropology's claims to disciplinary autonomy, but that in so doing it further underwrote the autonomy of “culture” itself as a distinct determination of social action.52
Adam Kuper, Culture: The Anthropologists' Account (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999), ch. 2. In the developmentalist discourse of the 1950s and 1960s, the construction of “culture” as the residual determinant after social and ideological factors were subtracted often led to a negative characterization of cultural subjectivity as an obstacle to the “natural” process of economic growth. Cf. Carl Pletsch, “The Three Worlds Concept and the Division of Social Scientific Labor, Circa 1950–1975,” Comparative Studies in Society and History 23 (1981), 565–90.
Claude Lévi-Strauss, The Savage Mind (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1966), 66–70, 130–31.
Following from such substantive contrasts between collectively constituted subjectivity and objective structures of social organization, anthropological “culture” can also by extension be opposed as a theoretical or methodological category of analysis to the “brute and disinterested objectivism” of sociological abstractions, providing a richer subjectivistic emphasis on the “rich description” of “human thought, achievement, consciousness, pain, stupidity and evil” that, precisely because of its irreducibility to objective structures of determination, “cannot be anticipated on the basis of some theoretical premise.”54
Roy Boyne, “Culture and the World System,” Theory, Culture & Society 7, 2&3 (1990), 57–62.
Cf. Elman R. Service, A Century of Controversy: Ethnological Issues from 1860 to 1960 (Orlando: Academic Press, 1985), ch. 16.
Geuss, “Kultur, Bildung, Geist,” 36–37; Kroeber and Kluckhohn, Culture, 47; Ringer, Decline of the German Mandarins.
Heinrich Rickert, Science and History: A Critique of Positivist Epistemology (Princeton, N.J.: D. Van Nostrand, 1962). See also Andrew Arato, “The Neo-Idealist Defense of Subjectivity,” Telos 21 (1974), 108–61.
The issue is not then, as Stocking sometimes seems to imply, one of shifting the moment of the transition from humanistic to anthropological conceptions of “culture” from Tylor in the later nineteenth century to Boas in the early twentieth. For Kroeber and Kluckhohn, the key issue on which the difference between anthropological and humanistic “cultures” turned was value-neutrality. But while the shift from viewing “culture” as a condition achieved through a history of human improvement to viewing it as a universal condition of human social existence is certainly of great significance for the history of the social sciences, the two “cultures” are still defined by a single problematic. Anthropological “culture” still indexes the relative autonomy of human subjectivity from “natural” or “objective” determinations. This is not to deny, of course, that there can be a theory of “culture” that attempts to identify forms of social or biological determination. On the contrary, Malinowski's analysis of “basic needs” is just one eminent attempt within the modern anthropological tradition to identify such forms of determination. But for the object of such an analysis to be initially identifiable as “culture” is what first requires historical explanation. While culturalism—that is, a discourse that assumes the standpoint of culture as a category of human underdetermination—was required for the identification of certain kinds of objects or practices (e.g., custom, symbolic representation) as “culture,” once the identification of such objects as forms of “culture” was disciplinarily conventionalized, “culture” itself became immediately susceptible to analysis in terms of external determinations, whether in terms of needs, interests, or practices. Yet the deeper history of the constitution of the “cultural” object of knowledge remains evident symptomatically even in the writings of an ethnologist with such distinctly reductionist leanings as Malinowski. In Argonauts of the Western Pacific, for instance, he used “culture” as a standpoint from which to attack the stereotype of the “Primitive Economic Man,” the fabricated projection of classical political economy who was “prompted in all his actions by a rationalistic conception of self-interest.” Even “man on a low level of culture,” Malinowski sought to demonstrate, was driven to “work and effort”—far beyond the merely necessary, and, indeed, even as “an end in themselves”—“by motives of a highly complex, social and traditional nature, and towards aims which are certainly not directed towards the satisfaction of present wants, or to the direct achievement of utilitarian purposes.”58
Bronislaw Malinowski, Argonauts of the Western Pacific: An Account of Native Enterprise and Adventure in the Archipelagoes of Melanesian New Guinea (London: Routledge, 1922), 60–62.
The anthropological conception of “culture,” stripped of its implication of evolutionary improvement so as to accord underdetermined subjectivity to all social collectivities, replicates the Kantian understanding of human subjectivity at a collective level—and in all the more Kantian a spirit for its radically universal attribution of “culture” to all human societies. In other words, “culture” still names the emancipation of human reason (now grasped as variable systems of meaning-making, but still constituted subjectivistically in keeping with Kant's “Copernican revolution”) from the natural determinations of utility maximization or biological necessity (“the despotism of desires”). The community thus comes to stand in as the arena for the realization of human worldly agency (“skill”) that this fundamental freedom is supposed to ground.59
Of course, this transformation of the subjectivistic standpoint from the individual to the collective level may not be admissible in the strictly philosophical terms of Kant's argument, but this should not blind us to the deeper homology in the structure of argumentation.
None of this is to say that these different forms of cultural discourse, anthropological and humanistic, are simply “the same.” After all, the specific modalities in which subjective autonomy has been conceived—as a characteristic of the individual or the social, the community or the state—must surely be significant when we turn our attention to particular historical contexts. My point is rather to suggest that, from a historical standpoint, the proliferation of meanings should be considered within a single, internally differentiated conceptual history structured by a single, more-or-less internally consistent, modern understanding of human subjectivity as underdetermined and thus self-positing. “Culture,” humanistic and anthropological, has with remarkable regularity operated within a repertoire of homologous antinomies: inside-outside, authenticity-appearance, content-form, organism-mechanism, mind-body, meaning-thing, subject-object, freedom-necessity, autonomy-heteronomy, and spirit-nature. As a method of investigation, it will be indisputably important to specify the historical transformations the concept has undergone at particular points in time and space. It is in fact only because this concept has been assimilated into diverse discursive fields to diverse ends that the recognition of an underlying regularity becomes historically and theoretically meaningful. Such contextualization is, in the end, the only way to proceed to an understanding of this conceptual regularity as in any sense historically determinate. This in turn is what might make it possible to analyze in a historically determinate manner the changing ways in which free subjectivity has been construed in different temporal and spatial locations. Yet it will simply not do to dissolve this remarkable regularity into the pluralized discursive formations connected to particular institutional practices—to deny that “culture” is a concept that has exceeded its articulation as a specific form of discourse within particular institutional contexts. Such a strategy will get us no closer to understanding the central antinomic logic—the “deep structure,” if you will—that has with such remarkable consistency marked the concept across its different major forms of usage. The Foucauldian emphasis on the embeddedness of discourse within regimes of practice should instead serve to impel us to recognize that “intellectual history,” narrowly conceived either in terms of a chain of influence or in terms of the intertextual context of intellectual production, is far too narrow a framework within which to make sense of these deeper regularities across time and space.
A concept that is historically modern cannot be derived from metaphysical Truth; not, at least, without explicitly addressing the question of why an eternal verity had to wait so long for a systematic elaboration. Recognizing this has driven many intellectual historians to critique the more traditional “history of ideas” from the standpoint of a “genealogical” approach to the history of discourse formations. Yet it remains unclear whether the explanatory power and compelling plausibility of any concept to which can be ascribed the kind of universality that “culture” has enjoyed within the modern European tradition (in the dual sense of the regularity of its reproduction across centuries and its disregard for geographical and linguistic boundaries) can be plausibly derived from the specific institutional contingencies of discursive practice. The Foucauldian argument has certainly been made. Ian Hunter has argued that British cultural discourse in the second half of the nineteenth century took its significance from the pedagogical arrangement of the classroom: the presentation of the teacher as a model for ethical emulation shifted cultural discourse from its earlier valence of reflexive self-formation to a form of power-knowledge whose normalizing function was strategically directed to the production of a manageable population. For Hunter, then, the history of cultural discourse is not a “tradition” of thought, but rather a discourse-formation generated “piecemeal” out of an “ensemble of historical surfaces and forces” that was a “purely contingent and provisional configuration or ‘programme,' whose emergence is not governed by any overarching historical purpose or theoretical goal” such as might be figured by the concept of “man.”60
Ian Hunter, Culture and Government: The Emergence of Literary Education (London: Macmillan, 1988), 262.
David Lloyd and Paul Thomas share Hunter's suspicion of the figure of “man” at the heart of cultural discourse, but they balk at this crypto-positivist reduction of discourse to institutional contingency.61
David Lloyd and Paul Thomas, Culture and the State (New York and London: Routledge, 1998), 16–20.
Ibid., Culture and the State, 3–5.
Ibid., Culture and the State, 15.
Ibid., Culture and the State, 118.
Yet surely the devastating critique that Lloyd and Thomas direct at Hunter could just as easily be laid at their own feet. Does the fact that the ideological project of Victorian state-consolidation appropriated a discourse of “culture” (as they convincingly demonstrate it did) necessarily mean that the concept itself can be derived from or reduced to such functionality? In this sense, Hunter as well as Lloyd and Thomas fundamentally fail to come to terms with one of the core insights of the classic text against which they have commonly positioned their own arguments. In Culture and Society, Raymond Williams had sought to show, in a thoroughly non-functionalistic manner, how the concept of “culture” had emerged in modern British thought “as an abstraction and an absolute.” The delineative axis of the concept's significance was grounded in “the recognition of the practical separation of certain moral and intellectual activities [and ultimately, these conceived in turn as “a whole way of life”] from the driven impetus of a new kind of society”—which is as much as to say, the positing of a peculiarly modern subject-object dichotomy, and its subsequent alignment with a culture-society dichotomy. The second, evaluative axis then involved “the emphasis of these activities, as a court of human appeal, to be set over the processes of practical judgment and yet to offer itself as a mitigating and rallying alternative”—which is as much as to say, the assumption of cultural subjectivism (individual or collective) as the standpoint for a critique of the abstract, coercive, and destructive forces of modern industrial society.65
Williams, Culture and Society, xviii.
Yet Williams was, of course, writing about modern Britain, which leaves wide open the larger question of what such a non-functionalistic historical account would look like when considered at the level of the global dissemination and circulation of the culture-concept as a category variously of colonial cosmopolitanism, anti-colonial nationalism, pan-Asianism, and anti-Western anti-capitalism. Whatever else may be said, if we wish to follow the travels of the culture-concept beyond the borders of industrial Britain—even so far as to the eighteenth-century German-speaking world where the concept first rose to prominence—we will necessarily have to begin by displacing the problematic of “industrial society” from the conceptual primacy accorded to it in Williams' own account. There are, I would suggest, good reasons for doing this even on the basis of the British materials that Williams himself analyzed. Carlyle's critique of “‘Laissez-faire,' ‘Supply-and-demand,' and ‘Cash-payment as the sole nexus'” aspired not to the dissolution of industrial society, but to the liberation of the “rational soul” of labor from its subjection to the “Brute-god Mammon.”66
Thomas Carlyle, Past and Present (Cambridge: Riverside Press, 1965), 38, 191, 207; Thomas Carlyle, “Signs of the Times,” in Critical and Miscellaneous Essays (London: Chapman and Hall, 1899), vol. 2, 56–82.
Arnold, Culture and Anarchy, 80–81; and cf. Stefan Collini, Arnold (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988), 78–81.
The emergence of an assertive culturalist politics in colonial Bengal followed the broad contours of the British juxtaposition of subjective agency to the heteronomy implicit in objective structures. While direct critiques of Western industrial production were in circulation in the late nineteenth century, Bengali critics like Bankimchandra Chatterjee more generally focused on the deleterious characterological, ethical, and political consequences of the absorption of Indian bureaucratic and clerical functionaries into the structures of civil society: the reduction of society to a “giant marketplace” where effeminate, hypocritical, verbose, and ineffective “babus,” reciting “mantras from Adam Smith's puranas and Mill's tantras,” lived a travesty of “independence” in the practical reality of a mere “habit of heartless isolation.”68
Andrew Sartori, “Emancipation as Heteronomy: The Crisis of Liberalism in Later Nineteenth-Century Bengal, Journal of Historical Sociology 17, 1 (Mar. 2004), 56–86.
Bankim first broached this argument in an 1877 essay, “Manushyatva ki?” (What is humanity?), in Dr. Vishnu Basu, ed., Bankim racanabali: Sahitya samagra (in Bangla, Calcutta: Tuli-Kalam, Bengali year 1393 [c. 1986]), 374–76. His most detailed statement followed in his 1880s dialogical treatise, Dharmmatattva: Anushilan (The essence of religion: Culture)—see the new translation by Apratim Ray: Bankimchandra Chattopadhyay's Dharmatattva (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003).
See Andrew Sartori, “The Categorial Logic of a Colonial Nationalism: Swadeshi Bengal, 1904–1908,” Comparative Studies of South Asia, Africa and the Middle East 23, 1&2 (2003), 271–85; Joya Chatterji, Bengal Divided: Hindu Communalism and Partition, 1932–1947 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994), ch. 4; and Niharranjan Ray, Krishti, kalcara, samskriti (in Bangla, Calcutta: Jijnasa, 1979). I am currently working on a book manuscript that will present a more detailed substantive and theoretical consideration of the culture concept's history in Bengal.
This pattern was not confined to Britain's colonial territories. Starting in the later nineteenth century, the concept of culture was widely adopted to challenge Western civilizational domination through an identification of authentic indigenous tradition as the practical and intellectual foundation for the recuperation of an autonomous subjectivity from slavish imitation. In the 1850s, Ivan Kireevsky was clearly in search of a concept with which to articulate a distinction between Europe's alleged propensity for rationalist formalism and Russia's Christian commitment to the “higher and living unity” of “inner wholeness.” His contrast turned on the difference between Western and Russian prosveshchenie (enlightenment), a term that evokes quite powerfully the notion of a subjectivity liberated from heteronomous constraint, but whose usage in this context to express the notion of discrete value-orientations stretched its conventional meaning to the limits of intelligibility.71
Boris Jakim and Robert Bird, trans. and eds., On Spiritual Unity: A Slavophile Reader: Aleksei Khomiakov and Ivan Kireevsky (Hudson, N.Y.: Lindisfarne Books, 1998), 187–88, 213.
Kroeber and Kluckhohn, Culture, 53–54; Frank Fadner, Seventy Years of Pan-Slavism in Russia: Karazin to Danilevskii, 1800–1870 (Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 1961), 314–38; Andrzej Walicki, The Slavophile Controversy: History of a Conservative Utopia in Nineteenth-Century Russian Thought (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1989), chs. 12 and 13.
In Walicki, Slavophile Controversy, 529, where the author himself cites Williams to draw a direct parallel between Slavophilism and the British tradition of cultural criticism.
Bunka was widely understood in the Meiji period to be an abbreviation of bunmeikaika. By the 1920s, however, it had been clearly established as the translative equivalent of Kultur, and (on the model of Kultur/Zivilisation) it could be opposed to bunmei, or the material civilization with which the Meiji era was associated. In China, the character (kanji) used in Japan for bunka was then “translated back” into its classical Chinese equivalent, wen-hua, to allow the classical term to do the new work of translating the concept of “culture.” See Douglas Howland, Borders of Chinese Civilization: Geography and History at Empire's End (Durham and London: Duke University Press, 1996), 294 (n. 37); Liu, Translingual Practice, 32–34, 239.
Tessa Morris-Suzuki, “The Invention and Reinvention of ‘Japanese Culture,'” Journal of Asian Studies 54, 3 (1995), 762–63.
Howland, Borders of Chinese Civilization, 65.
Prasenjit Duara, “The Discourse of Civilization and Pan-Asianism,” Journal of World History 12, 1 (2001), 99–130; Stephen N. Hay, Asian Ideas of East and West: Tagore and His Critics in Japan, China and India (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1970); Liu, Translingual Practice; Morris-Suzuki, “Invention and Reinvention of ‘Japanese Culture.'”
Cf. Duara, “Discourse of Civilization”; Morris-Suzuki, “Invention and Reinvention of ‘Japanese Culture,'” 762.
I am not of course trying to conflate the mere identification of such formal regularities across cultural discourses with an explanation for the global dissemination of the culture-concept. This paper undertakes a more modest task: to emphasize the unity of “culture” as a global conceptual field in order to frame a starting-point from which a more substantial historical investigation of the significance of this modern thought-form might proceed. The distinction I have been trying to draw between the conceptual content of the culture-concept and its specific discursive and ideological deployments challenges any straightforward reduction of the globalizing movement of the concept to the heterogeneous contingencies of the concrete institutional or intellectual vehicles of its dissemination. After all, the remarkably consistent tendency of the concept to global dissemination over the past two and one-half centuries in itself seems to militate against an account that depends solely on the specificity of contingent historical conjunctures. An emphasis on structural continuity over contingency and heterogeneity, and conceptual content over discursive effectivity, flies in the face of the conventional disaggregative wisdom of contemporary intellectual history, whether of the Foucauldian or Skinnerian varieties. Yet the approach I am suggesting here does not necessarily have to abandon the considerable insights of this literature in the dubious cause of flattening the historical process of the globalization of the concept into a homogeneous monocausality; for it allows for the possibility that “culture” arrived in specific locations embedded in specific discursive frameworks, serving potentially quite different concrete functions in the hands of quite different historical agents intervening in quite different historical contexts and conceptualizing the appropriate agent of subjective autonomy in quite different ways. Nonetheless, I submit that there seems to be a deep coherence to the history of the culture-concept, and recognizing this could form the working hypothesis from which further historical investigation into its global dissemination and circulation might begin. Such an investigation could do worse than to broadly follow Williams in proceeding from a question quite different from the kind normally asked in the history of ideas: Under what circumstances has the problematic of subjective autonomy come to assume such global resonance in the modern age? If the culture-concept has indeed consistently articulated a claim about the underdetermination of human subjectivity, its movement might well track the dissemination of a more fundamental problematic: the definitively “modern” problematic of subjective autonomy itself. It is the historical conditions for the global emergence of this problematic, rather than the history of ideas or of the transfer of discursive-institutional apparatus from metropole to periphery, which should form the basic material for a truly global history of the culture-concept.