In the aftermath of the First World War, international law scholars enjoyed a considerable increase in influence and their ideas had an important impact on public and political debates in the period. Following the creation of the League of Nations in 1919, new multilateral legal techniques and procedures were implemented for the peaceful settlement of international disputes. Jurists seemed to have been ‘able to impose on the political sphere the fact that law could serve as a realistic and efficient science for international governance’.Footnote 1 A great number of professors of international law practised diverse roles successively, and occasionally even simultaneously, including positions as legal advisers to their national governments, members of various international jurist committees, and judges at the Permanent Court of International Justice.Footnote 2
Many of these scholars initially considered any specifically European organisation to be in contradiction to the new global international order and to the spirit of international law. They believed that there was one single international society, subject to the law, which would lose all authority were it not universal. However, following the steady decline in inter-European relations and the failure of the universalist ambitions of the League of Nations, a major change in legal debates occurred during the 1920s leading a number of important scholars, predominantly French, to come out in favour of regional and European alternatives.
This article analyses this crucial turning point in European legal thinking by answering a number of different but related questions: what made international jurists think increasingly in European terms? What solutions and legal mechanisms were proposed in order to create a peaceful Europe? What form of mobilisation could and did they use, considering the variety of institutional positions they held within and beyond the state? Finally, what influence did these legal studies have on the subsequent development of European integration after the Second World War? Did post-1945 conceptions of European law as a distinct and new ‘supranational order’ emerge in direct contrast to the failed inter-war conceptions of regional/European law based on international law?
To answer these questions, this article will analyse primary source materials from the legal scholars involved throughout the 1920s. It synthesises a response across three distinct chronological periods, which reveals the gradual ‘scaling-down’ process that brought scholars to debate the reorganisation of the international system on a regional and European basis from the early goal of a truly global legal order. The first stage includes the debate that occurred in the early 1920s on the universalism of the League of Nations, which was deemed idealistically premature, and the subsequent need to create regional groups under an umbrella League of Nations. The second stage encompasses the mid-1920s, when the question of reorganising the League of Nations on the basis of solid regional foundations was raised in order to improve its capability to secure a sustainable peace (especially in Europe). The third stage focuses on the rise of concrete discussion on a European federation following the proposal made in September 1929 by the French Prime Minister, Aristide Briand, to forge ‘a sort of federal link’ between European peoples.
Universalism versus continentalism
The premature universalism of the League of Nations in the early 1920s
In the aftermath of the First World War, jurists had placed high hopes in the new League of Nations, considering it a crucial step in the evolution towards an organised world community. According to Lassa F. L. Oppenheim, a British professor of German origin, writing in 1919, ‘the League of Nations [sought], through its written constitution, to organise the community of states, which had remained unorganised until then’.Footnote 3 When the members of the famous Institute of International Law (the oldest transnational network of jurists) met for the first time since the end of the war in Rome in October 1921, they adopted a resolution which acknowledged ‘the important progress made in political, legal and moral order by the creation of the League of Nations’ and they showed themselves ‘willing to help . . . the development of an institution the more full of the promise of progress the more it encounters an increasingly enlightened public opinion’.Footnote 4 Furthermore, some legal scholars engaged personally in the struggle for the League, joining the ranks of the Association française pour la Société des Nations (René Cassin, Ferdinand Larnaude, Georges Scelle),Footnote 5 the League of Nations Union in Great Britain (James Leslie Brierly, Alexander Pearce Higgins),Footnote 6 or the Deutsche Liga für Völkerbund (Walther Schücking, Hans Wehberg).Footnote 7
The refusal of the US Senate to ratify the Treaty of Versailles seemed fatally to compromise the prospects of achieving a truly global League of Nations. As a result, the early optimism quickly ran its course. Legal experts, such as the French Professor Georges Scelle,Footnote 8 wondered openly whether the universalist claims of the League were not premature, and whether ‘a scientific error and a breach of common sense’ had been committed by imposing the same rights on all member states without considering the ‘regional or even continental affinities’ that already existed between some states.Footnote 9 In 1922, the Institute of International LawFootnote 10 asked its members to answer whether several leagues of nations organised on a continental or regional basis should exist, or rather one single universal association with continental or regional divisions? The predominant trend among the members was to call for a League of Nations with continental and regional divisions.Footnote 11
Many European scholars, such as Alexandre Merignhac, Paul Fauchille, Charles de Visscher, Nicolas Politis or Joseph de Blociszewski approved of creating continental or regional groups within a universal League of Nations, as foreseen by the Covenant itself, of which Article 21 expressly provided that ‘nothing in this Covenant shall be deemed to affect the validity of international engagements, such as treaties of arbitration and regional understandings like the Monroe Doctrine, for securing the maintenance of peace.’Footnote 12 But the Belgian scholar Charles de VisscherFootnote 13 warned against a double danger posed by the constitution of such groups, namely the risk of compromising the fundamental unity of the League of Nations and pitting hostile groups of states against each other.
American lawyers, by contrast, were less drawn to the existing League of Nations and instead, following in particular the example set by the Chilean scholar Alejandro Alvarez,Footnote 14 advocated the creation of a flexible world association, which would encompass the League of Nations – as a de facto European organisation – and the Pan-American Union. Alejandro Alvarez thought that the League of Nations should have taken into account the sentiments of continental solidarity. Despite the fact that Europe and America were of the same civilisation, he argued that there were many differences in their legal doctrines and preferred systems of international organisation, and these had been further accentuated by the First World War. Therefore the Covenant of the League of Nations should be reformed along continental lines. According to Alvarez, there were in fact only two possible continental ‘leagues of nations’ (as Asia and Africa were politically dependant on Europe): the ‘European’ League of Nations based in Geneva and the Pan-American Union based in Washington. He argued for a ‘world association of states’, which would secure co-operation between Europe and America, while also taking into account their specific interests.Footnote 15
As a result of these contributions, the 27th Commission of the Institute of International Law in August 1922 adopted a draft convention on the creation of a world association of states. This argued that it was necessary to create a link between the League of Nations, the Pan-American Union, and states which were not part of either of these organisations but were willing to engage with the rest of the world on the basis of co-operation, peace and justice.Footnote 16 However, a few weeks later, in its session in Grenoble, and after long deliberations, the commission overturned its previous decision so as not to harm the prestige of the League of Nations. Even if the putative world association of states was not designed to replace the existing League of Nations, the jurists did not want to fuel further the existing public distrust in the League of Nations. Consequently, all members of the commission, including Alvarez, agreed to remove the project from the agenda of the Institute.Footnote 17 This proposal had probably come too early and certainly seemed quite radical to many European jurists. Nevertheless the pressure coming from American side (especially from Alejandro Alvarez) to take regional solidarity seriously prompted reflection by the European jurists throughout the early 1920s on what constituted the best way to achieve a universal League of Nations despite the reluctance of the United States of America to take part.
Regionalism to the rescue of the League of Nations – the mid-1920s
From the mid-1920s the difficulties facing the League of Nations and its repeated failures to implement an ill-conceived universalist approach to international politics forced a growing number of legal scholars to accept the necessity of regionally focused solutions. For instance the Corfu Crisis in 1923 between Italy and Greece clearly demonstrated that the League could not exercise its authority effectively when a great power was involved in a dispute. Yet all attempts to strengthen its legal machinery led to failure, as British governments, in particular, were anxious to minimise the security commitments of the Covenant. The withdrawal of the United States from the League had led British governments to ‘believe that only a flexible and consultative League could now have any hope of operating effectively’.Footnote 18 For instance Britain rejected a Protocol for the Pacific Settlement of International Disputes that had been unanimously adopted by the Fifth Assembly of the League of Nations in 1924 and which would go beyond the Covenant with regard to the compulsory arbitration of disputes and mutual assistance. The hopes of reforming the League of Nations on a universal model were thus increasingly compromised, and the failure of the Protocol of 1924 seemed to compromise the vision of European peace guaranteed by a universal pact.
The difficulties experienced by the League appeared to prove that it was necessary to reorganise the international system on the basis of solid regional foundations in order to avoid a slide towards a new catastrophe. From this point of view, the Locarno agreements of October 1925 seemed to demonstrate the importance of regional reconciliation. René Cassin of France even thought that this type of regional agreement was ‘apt to lead to the general acceptance of a higher universal protocol, on the basis of the satisfactory experience of obligations that were more geographically limited’.Footnote 19 This was why these accords needed to be concluded within the framework of the League of Nations, respecting as far as possible the principles of the now defunct Geneva protocol. However, some other lawyers were more concerned about the consequences of the Locarno settlement on the League of Nations: for instance José Ramon Orúe y Arregui, professor of international law at the University of Valencia, believed that in Locarno ‘the healthy international mind [had been] defeated by the most decentralising particularism’. As an ardent supporter of the Geneva organisation, he preferred a ‘courageous work of rejuvenation rather than a risky dislocation the consequences of which [were] clearly problematic’.Footnote 20
Nevertheless the League of Nations looked increasingly like a European project: for the Greek legal scholar and diplomat Nicolas PolitisFootnote 21 the European character of the League was ‘the main reason for Russia's hostility and especially [explained] the attitude of the United States’.Footnote 22 Furthermore, the League of Nations faced a real crisis in 1926 arising out of Germany's decision to apply for membership. Legal scholars were worried about the campaigns by Spain, Brazil and Poland, who each wanted a permanent seat on the Council and opposed Germany's application. According to Georges Scelle, this crisis was due to the ‘initial misconception’ of the League of Nations, that is to say ‘the error of centralising uniformity’.Footnote 23 The remedy consisted in the ‘decentralisation’ of the Geneva system, or in institutionalising ‘the distinction between the universal League of Nations and the particular continental or other societies that it harbours’.Footnote 24 For the French professor, the League of Nations had to ‘develop in the direction of a complicated federation of federations, superimposed and interconnected’.Footnote 25
Along with the influence of Alejandro Alvarez, the idea of reorganising the League of Nations along continental lines led to further, quite intense debate within the legal community during 1926 and 1927. In June 1926, the Union juridique internationale, another transnational network of specialists in international law set up by Ferdinand Larnaude and Léon Bourgeois, took up the question of reforming the League of Nations Covenant along continental or regional lines. Alejandro Alvarez again proposed to ‘establish a link between the two great international organisations presently in existence: the League of Nations and the Pan-American Union, leaving to each its proper shape’.Footnote 26 He emphasised the fact that ‘states of the New World do not want to get involved in European affairs and those of other continents, and they refuse to allow the states of these continents to become involved in theirs. However they are disposed to co-operate in world affairs with these continents and especially with Europe’.Footnote 27 His colleagues, notably LarnaudeFootnote 28 and LapradelleFootnote 29, insisted that the Covenant already authorised regional accords for peace in its Article 21, and that there was no need to revise or amend it. Larnaude called for prudence and for ‘infringing on the great Covenant of the League of Nations as little as possible’.Footnote 30 These legal scholars were unwilling to compromise the possibility of a truly universal legal framework through the League. Nevertheless, the Union juridique internationale agreed on the idea that ‘to achieve its universal vocation, the League of Nations could delegate the accomplishment of some task or other to a given region or continent, to the organs set up within them’.Footnote 31
At the same time, some scholars were keen to commit themselves to one (or several) of the pro-European movements that were starting to flourish. They sometimes played an important role in these militant organisations, not only as legal experts but also as involved intellectuals worried about Europe's future. George Scelle, already an indefatigable activist for peace and for the League of Nations, became vice-chairman of the French Committee for a European Customs Union. Walther Schücking became vice-chairman of the Federal Committee for European Co-operation, whose national sub-committees brought together some of the most renowned lawyers of that time: Hans Kelsen and Alfred VerdrossFootnote 32 in Austria, Joseph Barthélemy, Jules Basdevant and Louis Le Fur in France, Nicolas Politis in Greece, and others. Politis also played an important role in the Pan-European Union chaired by the cosmopolitan aristocrat Richard Coudenhove-Kalergi.Footnote 33 During its first International Congress in Vienna (October 1926), Politis gave an important speech declaring that ‘the Pan-Europa has the same goal, the same ideal as the League of Nations: serving the cause of peace and international co-operation. It is in perfect harmony with the spirit of the Covenant’.Footnote 34
In the mid-1920s, due to the continued failure of the League, a certain consensus seemed to have emerged among jurists, especially French ones, about the desirability of European regionalism within the framework of the League of Nations. But it was the Briand Plan for a European Federal Union that launched a widespread debate on European questions among international law professors during the late 1920s.
The Briand Plan and the debate on a European federation
This movement in favour of a united Europe reached its climax at the end of the decade, when Aristide Briand, French Prime Minister and Minister for Foreign Affairs, proposed in September 1929 the creation of ‘some sort of [European] federal link’, further clarifying his ideas in his later ‘Memorandum on the Organisation of a Regime of European Federal Union’ (May 1930).Footnote 35 Although legal experts had already anticipated the question of a European union, the French proposals now gave them the opportunity to examine the European question more deeply and concretely. A number of specialised reviews and learned societies took note of this great debate, contributing to theoretical reflections that had until then been somewhat distant from reality.
The community of international legal scholars did not react in unanimous fashion to the French scheme. In their comments, they were partly influenced by their national origins and the interests of their individual countries. Their positions often reflected those of their respective governments, all the more so as they were frequently employed as legal advisers and consultants for their respective ministries for foreign affairs.Footnote 36 For instance, Francis Deák, assistant professor at Columbia University Law School, who served as legal expert to the Hungarian delegation to the League of Nations, published an article in 1931 in the Political Science Quarterly that criticised Briand's proposal. For him, Europe could not unite unless there were no longer post-war winners and losers, but equal states acting together:
The framers of the European federation scheme should have realised, in the atmosphere of Geneva, separated from the hysteria of 1919 by more than a decade, that certain fundamental errors and substantial injustices still exist, and are not conducive to the development of a community of interest and of a sentiment of solidarity.Footnote 37
French international legal scholars, on the other hand, argued that this European solidarity did exist and generally took a positive view of Briand's proposal. Between European states there was, in the words of Louis Le Fur,Footnote 38 ‘the same common ground, a deep unity, due to a single civilisation, not only moral . . . but also intellectual and technical’,Footnote 39 and this old civilisation now had to be formalised through common institutions. As a consequence French legal scholars played a prominent role in this intellectual debate on a united Europe, which contrasts with the little interest in this question shown by other European legal circles at this time, notably British ones. Although this point deserves further investigation, this seems to corroborate the frequently-noted British reluctance towards the European idea in the 1920s, Great Britain experiencing its Europeanist ‘golden age’ only in the late 1930s.Footnote 40 The role played by French legal experts was not a question of loyalty or allegiance to their government, for they were not invited to participate in the elaboration of the Memorandum of May 1930, which was instead drafted by Alexis Leger, political director of the Foreign Ministry, with the help of a handful of French diplomats.Footnote 41
Now that the French proposal had been made public, international legal scholars were certainly among the most qualified to address the question of the appropriate European institutional architecture. While the community of international legal scholars was not naturally inclined to think in a focused European perspective, the previous reflections on international life and regional solidarities could nevertheless help the most innovative professors rethink the official French proposal in legal terms. Yet, how did they conceive of a specific ‘European’ law? How did they anticipate the legal nature of a united Europe and its institutional form?
The outlines of a European union
International law and ‘European’ law
In the 1920s, the community of international legal scholars shared the same beliefs about the universal and non-national nature of international law.Footnote 42 For them there was one single international society, which was subject to the law, and the law was law only if it was universal. ‘If you repeal the idea that law is “one”, not only international law, but law as a whole, you remove most of its power’, warned Fernand Larnaude;Footnote 43 ‘Law is universal by nature . . . Do not give up the idea of the universality of law’.Footnote 44 Nonetheless, as they considered that law emerged from given social facts, many scholars maintained that international law had to take account of and reflect the ‘realities’ of international life. Though the gradually increasing economic and cultural interdependence of humankind was noticeable, Scelle and Mirkine-Guetzevitch identified ‘areas of more intense solidarity’ between some ‘families of peoples or nations, that is to say smaller international societies within the global or world international society’.Footnote 45
In his ‘Treaty of International Law’ Paul Fauchille wrote that ‘one must not become obsessed, as has been the case up to now, by the idea that all rules must be universal: for this could only be the case if all continents were in the same condition, which is not the present reality’.Footnote 46 In fact, European legal scholars were strongly influenced by the development of a truly American international law, fashioned by Alejandro Alvarez and the American Institute of International Law. This breakthrough on the other side of the Atlantic had a great impact on the idea of the regionalisation of international law. However the rise of international law would not be compromised by the development of regional or continental laws, according to Politis, as ‘they are in constant touch so that one could not separate them without harming them.’Footnote 47 The unity of international law was therefore ‘the general framework within which . . . legal rules of smaller societies are drawn up.’Footnote 48
Even if a specific European law did not necessarily contradict the spirit of international law, many legal scholars, such as the Greek lawyer Stélio Séfériadès, were dubious of an overly strong focus on European regionalism: ‘every effort should be made to avoid splitting world-wide interests if there is damage to the solidarity that should exist between states’.Footnote 49 Moreover, the German Walther SchückingFootnote 50 wondered whether ‘bringing together states by continents’ could lead to the danger that these groups ‘break the unity of the League of Nations and that they become hostile towards each other’.Footnote 51 Nevertheless, he and the majority of his colleagues did not want to oppose this regionalist legal trend on principle, as long as it was compatible with the Covenant and its Article 21. But there was a need, as the Spanish lawyer De Orrué y Arregui wrote, to put these ‘regional understandings under the auspices and the control of Geneva, investing [the League of Nations] with clear authority over them’.Footnote 52
The legal nature of a European union
Legal scholars faced further difficulties in anticipating the legal form of a future European union and showed a high degree of caution in their reflections on European constitutionalism. Scelle and Mirkine-Guetzevitch explained that ‘any specific plan for European organisation is all the more fanciful or unreal when it is more detailed’.Footnote 53 They did not want to develop any specific institutional scheme. This would better be left to natural evolution: ‘most of the time these schemes first develop in political reality, in facts, and only then do jurists construct their doctrines’.Footnote 54
As they could not completely escape the debate on the nature of a future European union, legal experts warned of the dangers of simplified formulas such as the ‘United States of Europe’, as this suggested ‘a misinterpretation that would give a misleading idea’.Footnote 55 Thus Yves de La Brière wanted to ‘banish [it] mercilessly’Footnote 56 because the situation was clearly different on each side of the Atlantic: unlike the United States of America, ‘the various European states are inhabited by true nations with a very old history, whose political and moral features are clearly characterised, and almost always with a distinctive language’.Footnote 57 Nevertheless, some American lawyers, such as James Brown Scott, reminded their European colleagues of the American experiment:
It will perhaps not be considered impertinent to venture to suggest that America should not be overlooked in contemplating a rapprochement, however loose, of the nations of Europe. . .. what one group of states has done, another may do, even though it be to a lesser and different degree.Footnote 58
However few European lawyers echoed this vision. Most believed that the US could not be used as a model for a European union. One exception was a young scholar from the Lyon Law School, Jacques Lambert, who published an article in 1929 entitled ‘The United States of Europe and the American Example’. He recalled the fact that the unification of the US had been a long and difficult process and that according to him, American federalism ‘contain[ed] some elements that may contribute to the solution of the problems Europe faces’.Footnote 59 But most of his colleagues considered that only the Pan-American Union could provide a relevant pattern for a European union, as such a union should also operate through regular inter-state meetings. In fact, legal experts were not really willing to learn from foreign experiments and considered that a European union would find its own way within international society.
Nevertheless, taking recourse to legal doctrine, international jurists did not believe that a European understanding could lead to a real federation, not even Georges ScelleFootnote 60 who ‘held law a translation of sociological and ultimately biological processes that led inexorably to federalism’.Footnote 61 For the moment, he did not believe that a European union could be a ‘merging of European peoples in one super-state with common governmental institutions’.Footnote 62 Thus ‘speaking of a European federation means nothing’, as ‘we can hardly speak yet, nor even in the future might we speak of an outline of a “confederation”.’Footnote 63
In the context of the release of the French ‘Memorandum on the Organisation of a Regime of European Federal Union’, Joseph Barthélemy,Footnote 64 one of France's leading constitutional lawyers, made a substantial and in some ways highly prescient contribution to the question of the legal nature of a future united Europe in June 1930. In a report for the International Federation of Committees for European Co-operation, he developed the idea that the European union would be ‘a mere union of free nations, independent, sovereign within and outside of its borders, each nation preserving its personality, its characteristics and traditions’.Footnote 65 He thus preferred to speak in terms of ‘union’ than in terms of ‘unity’. The European union would act as an organ of international law and not of constitutional law: ‘Decisions will be made unanimously. Each state, for each decision, will have no obligations other than its own consent’.Footnote 66 Barthélemy wanted this European union to respect the national sovereignty of its member states, which was different in his mind from keeping absolute sovereignty. He believed that ‘sovereignty as an absolute liberty to act its own way [was] but a historical ghost’.Footnote 67 State sovereignty was henceforth ‘the power of acting freely within the limits set by international law’.Footnote 68 As a consequence ‘there [could not be] any European union without limitation of sovereignty’.Footnote 69
Since the end of the First World War, many lawyers had indeed vigorously denounced classical international law and called into question the absolute sovereignty of states, in particular the fact that they had sovereign rights to go to war with another state.Footnote 70 Traumatised by the horrors of the First World War,Footnote 71 Scelle called for the deliberate and definitive rejection of the notion of sovereignty ‘because it is false and harmful’.Footnote 72 Influenced by the theories of Léon Duguit, who considered the state to be pure fiction, he contested the notion of the state's personality: for him, the only subjects of law were individuals, and this was why he came back to the old expression ius gentium,Footnote 73 ‘law of the peoples’, ‘people’ being understood in the everyday sense of ‘individuals’. Louis Le Fur, professor at the Paris law faculty and defender of a return to natural law, also hoped to see an end to references to ‘the absolute sovereignty of the state, its arbitrary will in domestic policy and its unlimited independence in foreign policy, a double error which has overthrown and corrupted all of public law’.Footnote 74 This is why many legal experts showed great reserve towards the French government's proposal published in the famous Memorandum of May 1930 and the legal imprecision of its language. Scelle pointed to the fact that ‘the conciliation between the idea of absolute sovereignty and the idea of federation or confederation is a logical and juridical impossibility’.Footnote 75
In fact, legal scholars felt much more comfortable criticising the legal imprecision, loopholes and contradictions in the Memorandum than in proposing alternatives. Joseph Barthélemy considered it ‘remarkable by the richness of its uncertain formulae, by the care with which these formulae have been robbed of their juridical content and also by the loose usage of these terms’.Footnote 76 George Scelle also deplored the great number of ‘ambiguous phrases’, ‘inaccurate passages’, ‘dangerous assertions’ and ‘counter-truths’, all of which reflected essentially diplomatic preoccupations.Footnote 77 As a result, many jurists felt the need to place their legal expertise at the disposal of European governments, and they thus attempted to clarify the legal contours of a European union.
A cautious construction process
As a whole, international jurists were extremely cautious regarding the institutional form that European co-operation might assume. Barthélemy stated that ‘everything has to start small . . . An effort to rush things would be likely to compromise the whole endeavour’.Footnote 78 Louis Le Fur declared that it was necessary ‘not to jump the gun and to observe the rule of steady growth which is very natural’.Footnote 79 In Scelle's view, the European union could at first resemble ‘a diplomatic congress, analogous to the “assembly of representatives” envisaged in Wilson's initial scheme as the unique organ of the League of Nations – indeed the only organ, with a secretariat or technical commissions as necessary’.Footnote 80 Barthélemy referred to ‘a pre-organised organism, set up ahead of the time when it will have particular needs to address’.Footnote 81
In the summer of 1930, the Union juridique internationale took up the problem. In the light of the reservations they had expressed concerning the French Memorandum, eminent lawyers such as Alvarez, Lapradelle, La Brière, Politis, Le Fur and Truchy tried to clarify the legal contours of the European institutions highlighted by the Briand Memorandum: a general conference, an executive council and a permanent secretariat. Therefore they developed a Plan for an International European Union consisting of twenty-one articles, mostly inspired by the Pan-American Union and the Covenant of the League of Nations. The European Council would be made up of five permanent members (Germany, Britain, Spain, France and Italy), three members elected for three years, and members representing regional unions within Europe. Decisions would be taken by unanimous vote of the council and assembly, except in matters of internal regulation, where a qualified majority of four-fifths of those present would suffice.Footnote 82 However, the text was disappointing from an institutional point of view as it was, like the French Memorandum, an imitation of the workings of the League, although it claimed that the European union, based in Geneva, would not duplicate the work of the League. The document was released on 30 August 1930, on the eve of the General Assembly of the League of Nations. The proposal was notably published on the front page of the influential Parisian daily newspaper Le Temps Footnote 83 and was widely commented on during the following days, not least by some civil servants of the International Labour Office, who disapproved of the creation of continental unions within the framework of the League of Nations.Footnote 84
The legacy of this first legal debate on a united Europe
The official responses to the French Memorandum were muted, if not hostile, because of the deteriorating economic and political context in Europe. In September 1930, delegates to the League of Nations agreed to sidetrack the Briand proposal to a new committee within the framework of the League of Nations, the Commission of Inquiry for European Union. In the context of the Great Depression, it held a series of meetings in 1931/2 devoted to economic problems, and worked out plans for agricultural surpluses, unemployment, public works, and an International Agricultural Mortgage Credit Company. But the economic crisis made any attempt to implement these simply futile.
The Depression of the 1930s had already altered the European landscape and caused the decline of a certain international mindset as Feliks Frankowski, a Polish lawyer, wrote in 1934: ‘the failure of pan-European ideas, the repeated failures of the so-called policy of the League of Nations, and finally the rise of nationalist and authoritarian governments in most countries of the world mark the low tide of internationalism.’Footnote 85 However some legal scholars still advocated a united Europe in the 1930s. In 1935 José Ramon Orúe y Arregui declared himself to be a ‘resolute supporter of regionalism’ within the framework of the League of Nations,Footnote 86 whereas in 1937 Louis Le Fur admitted the possibility of two separate leagues of nations, an American one and a European one, as he deplored the American unwillingness to build a truly global organisation.Footnote 87 In the light of the rise of authoritarian regimes, these legal scholars considered it essential for Europe to be able to benefit from a strengthened League of Nations. Regionalisation could help the League reinforce its global capability and bolster it against authoritarian states likely to threaten peace. But the outbreak of the Second World War led some jurists to advance ever more radical reforms of the international system and for a more demanding type of federalism, criticising the institutional reticence of the 1920s. For instance, in 1940 Scelle attempted to outline the perspective of establishing a true European federation after the war, taking the Franco-British relationship as an initial central bond to which other states would adhere.Footnote 88
After the Second World War, some legal scholars were involved in movements supporting a federal Europe, such as the Union of European Federalists (UEF) set up in late 1946, and the European Parliamentary Union (EPU) founded in July 1947 on the initiative of Coudenhove-Kalergi. These legal experts helped to establish European institutional schemes, such as two professors from the University of Strasbourg, Michel Mouskhély and Gaston Stefani, who drew up in March 1948 a ‘draft federal European constitution’ for the UEF of which they were members. Michel Mouskhély, a Russian émigré who had fled communism, was a former doctoral student of Louis Le Fur, and then became a follower of Georges Scelle.Footnote 89 After the Second World War, he specialised in European federalism and published numerous studies on the subject. He and Gaston Stefani indicated in broad terms in their draft certain fundamental constitutional provisions: legislative power would reside in a federal chamber intended to represent the people of the federation and elected directly by universal suffrage, and in a Chamber of States representing member states. The executive organ would be a federal council of ten members at most, elected by the federal assembly. Finally, to settle any disputes arising from the application, interpretation or execution of the constitutional or federal laws, there would be a federal supreme court consisting of eleven to fifteen judges. A few months later, the authors developed their ideas in book form: L'Europe face au fédéralisme,Footnote 90 and their draft for the UEF was used in June 1948 by François de Menthon for the purpose of his ‘Constitution for the United States of Europe’. At the time de Menthon was a French deputy and leader of the Mouvement Républicain Populaire (MRP) parliamentary group (and formerly law professor at the University of Nancy in the 1930s), and he chaired the legal committee set up in 1947 within the European Parliamentary Union (EPU) that was responsible for preparing a European constitution. But his plan was turned down in September 1948 by the Interlaken Congress of the EPU, and in 1952–4, as president of the Assembly of the Council of Europe, he became firmly opposed to his own previous federal views advocating a confederative model for Europe.Footnote 91
Ultimately, the federalist movement did not succeed in winning support for its ideas, either among the general public or from national governments. Moreover it was competing with the unionists who were satisfied with a simple union of states and whose main champion was the former British Prime Minister, Winston Churchill, chairman of the United Europe Movement. The first European institutions born in the late 1940s were strictly intergovernmental bodies and their scope of action was limited by the unanimity rule, as was the case for the Organisation for European Economic Co-operation (1948) and the Council of Europe (1949), which did not become a real European political authority despite the efforts of pro-European activists.
In 1950, the Schuman Plan inaugurated a new method of European construction, which attempted to overcome the divisions between federalists and unionists. The European Coal and Steel Community (ECSC) was the first European organisation based on supranational integration whose aim was to create ‘de facto solidarity’ as a first step in the ‘federation of Europe’. In these first steps of European unification, the inter-war lawyers did not play any direct role, with the exception of a young professor of international law, Paul Reuter, who worked with Jean Monnet on the development of the High Authority of the ECSC, as described in Anne Boerger's article in this special issue. While he was professor of International Law at the University of Aix-en-Provence and Legal Adviser to the Ministry of Foreign Affairs, he drew up a draft proposal with Jean Monnet for the pooling of the coal and steel resources of France and the Federal Republic of Germany, and he worked to transform it into legal rules: ‘Paul Reuter was the origin of the High Authority, of the word as of the thing’, wrote Jean Monnet in his Mémoires.Footnote 92 But Reuter's involvement was purely accidentalFootnote 93 and the young legal expert had been less influenced by the doctrine of inter-war international law than by the spirit of the 1930s and the Third Way ideology between capitalism and communism, individualism and collectivism, USA and USSR, advocating anti-materialism, State planning and corporatism.Footnote 94 He had been also inspired by the New Deal model of independent regulatory authorities, and by inter-war ideas about functional evolution of governance structures.Footnote 95 Paul Reuter had mainly developed his thinking on the need for European federalism during the Second World War, when he was one of the lecturers at the Ecole Nationale des Cadres at Uriage. At that time, in the context of a general critique of the pre-war liberal regime, he urged the need for the ‘beginning of a political federalism’ between the European states, the better to resist the capitalist ‘trusts’, as unified political forces would be stronger than ‘economic forces of concentration’.Footnote 96
But, as Martti Koskeniemi has pointed out, to elaborate on his European proposal ‘Jean Monnet had not consulted Georges Scelle or the other inter-war lawyers’.Footnote 97 In fact, it would be the debate on the creation of a European Political Community (EPC) at the time of the negotiations on a European Defence Community (EDC) in 1952/3 that would once again offer scholars of international law an important role in discussions about a European institutional order. Georges Scelle, who had participated in the famous ‘Congress of Europe’ at The Hague in May 1948 under the auspices of the International Committee for the Co-ordination of the Movements for a United Europe, played a key role in these debates of the early 1950s. For instance, he sat on the International Juridical Committee created on 17 December 1950 by the UEF. This committee was chaired by Fernand Dehousse, a Belgian socialist senator and professor of international law at the University of Liège. It also comprised three other law professors from the inter-war period, Hans Nawiasky (University of Munich) Piero Calamendrei (University of Florence) and Léon Julliot de la Morandière (University of Paris).Footnote 98 The committee eventually formulated a proposal for a Statute for the European Constituent and a memorandum containing the outline of a federal constitution, which were finalised and adopted at the Lugano conference in April 1951.Footnote 99 Subsequently, Dehousse, Calamandrei and Nawiasky took part in the Committee for the European Constitution, established by Paul-Henri Spaak and with Dehousse as functioning secretary in 1952 within the framework of the European Movement. This new committee had to prepare the ground for the planned Ad Hoc Assembly that, according to article 38 of the EDC treaty, would be given the task of writing a constitution for the EPC.Footnote 100 But again all these efforts were in vain, as the EDC failed to be ratified by the French National Assembly in 1954.
After the rejection of the EDC, the supranational dimension of the European construction process seemed to be under question. The Italian Centre for Legal Studies decided to organise an international conference on the ECSC in Stresa in 1957 to rethink approaches to European integration. Giuseppa Pella, the Chairman of the Common Assembly of the ECSC, chaired the organisation committee of the Conference.Footnote 101 The main objective of this conference would be to legitimise the ECSC from an academic perspective and the Communication and Legal Departments of the High Authority were of great help in its organisation. However, the committee of international law scholars, who were invited to write a report on the legal nature of the ECSC, concluded that the latter was merely an international organisation, albeit of a peculiar kind, and refused to accept the concept of supranationality as a new legal category. Their argument thus stuck with the classical and well-established theory of international law from the inter-war period and refused to admit that this nascent ‘European law’ could constitute a new legal order. They were above all attached to the universality of international law. This contrasted with a miscellaneous group of young professors (mainly specialised in comparative law) and some of ‘the organic jurists of the Community’Footnote 102 who had strong links with the European institutions (Michel Gaudet, member of the Legal Service of the High Authority, Pierre Wigny, of the Common Assembly, and Louis Delvaux, of the European Court of Justice), supported the opposite point of view, and conceived supranationality as an autonomous legal category.Footnote 103 In Stresa, despite the conclusions of the committee, it was clear that the doctrines of international law were deemed insufficient not only by the new European institutions responsible for developing European integration, but also by a new generation of law scholars from comparative law. Thus, the debate expressed a trend towards the development of an independent legal doctrine in European law – a doctrine that the European Court of Justice (ECJ) finally developed with Van Gend en Loos and Costa v. E.N.E.L. in 1963–4.
As has been asserted in this study, the inter-war period was a key (but rather forgotten) moment in the debate among legal scholars on a European institutional order. Although the European Communities established in the 1950s did not derive directly from the institutional schemes of the 1920s, the 1920s can be seen as having played an important role in the building of a European legal doctrine. After the failure of the universal ambitions of the League of Nations and the pressure coming from the American side (especially from the Latin American jurist Alejandro Alvarez) to take regional solidarity seriously (such as the Pan-American Union), an increasing number of legal scholars, especially French ones, came out in support of regional and European solutions. The need to create a peaceful Europe through the rule of law, the increase in salience of regional solidarity due to of the failures of universalist solutions, and the criticisms of the absolute sovereignty of the state were all promising concepts used by international scholars from the aftermath of the First World War to the aftermath of the Second.
However, inherent in international law were also certain obstacles to thinking about European unification and what kind of legal shape it would take. In the 1920s, legal scholars generally showed a high degree of caution regarding the institutional architecture and the feasibility of any form of European construction. They were unwilling to consider any institutional reality of possible European unification in legal terms before the politicians had taken the first steps. In this respect the Briand Memorandum of 1930 boosted their reflection on European legal construction. But in contrast with the shallowness of the 1920s debates, the Second World War pushed a certain number of international legal scholars to uphold more extreme positions on the abandonment of sovereignty and some of them were even keen to commit themselves to federalist organisations.
The conclusion we can draw from this study on professors of international law is that the two worldwide cataclysms did lead many to question existing legal doctrine and the legal organisation of Europe was seen each time as a possible way of adapting international law to meet the needs of the present time, according to the functionalist – and inter-war – idea that institutions and law should evolve as a function of the problems they addressed. But in the 1950s, when European integration really began to develop according to a functionalist method, international legal doctrine revealed itself to be inefficient in dealing with the new challenge of supranationality. International law was no longer the crucible for European law. This was now set to become a category all of its own.