Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-5r2nc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T09:33:43.308Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Change the Meaning, Save More Lives: Why Changing the Meaning of Commercial Compensated Collections of Substances of Human Origin Is Both Feasible and Preferable to Banning the Practice for Fear of Commodification

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 February 2025

Peter M. Jaworski*
Affiliation:
McDonough School of Business, Georgetown University
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Thousands of people will suffer and die this year because we do not donate enough substances of human origin, including blood plasma. To solve this, some recommend that we allow commercial organizations to assist in collecting these and that we permit donor compensation as a tool to encourage donations. Many object to these proposals, including for semiotic or expressive reasons. But insofar as these objections rely on meanings and these meanings are social constructs, we can revise the meaning of these practices to avoid commodification. Revision may work in principle, but in practice some complain that changing meanings may be too difficult or practically infeasible. This essay attempts to show that this is not so in a wide range of cases and uses the case of commercial compensated blood plasma collection as an illustration. Getting people to conceive of this practice not as payment for blood plasma but as compensation for the time, effort, and inconvenience associated with the giving of plasma is practically feasible and preferable to prohibition.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© 2025 Social Philosophy and Policy Foundation. Printed in the USA

Introduction

Many are on waiting lists for kidney, liver, or bone marrow transplants. Others are waiting on therapies made from blood plasma, especially immunoglobulin. For too many, the wait will be futile, the lack of access will be permanent. Thousands of patients die each year because there are too few available organs for transplant and substances of human origin to meet the need. There are too few because too few of us donate these.

Some have suggested that our health systems use tools such as financial incentives to encourage donations and so save more lives. Permitting commercial organizations to secure and allocate these in an efficient manner is another such tool. Both of these are often suggested as ways to increase donations so as to reduce the number of lives lost.

We use these tools without much controversy when it comes to a variety of goods and services, including other basic necessities such as food, clothing, and shelter. We use financial incentives to encourage people to grow our food, make our clothes, and build our homes. We permit commercial organizations to profit from our need to eat, to be protected from the elements, and to be safe from a variety of dangers.

Even within health care, we use financial incentives without much controversy to encourage people to join health-care professions and to stay in those professions. We do not expect nurses, doctors, phlebotomists, and other health-care professionals to volunteer their services. We pay them money. When we have too few nurses or doctors, we often adjust salaries or benefits to encourage young people to enter these professions or to keep people from quitting and doing something else.

However, when it comes to encouraging people to donate organs or substances of human origin, these tools are deeply controversial. Why?

Some think that financial incentives may backfire, resulting in fewer donations, or may reduce donations of related substances of human origin. But there are also objections to the use of compensation and commercialism, even if they do not backfire and do not encroach on other donations, and so have the intended effect of increasing donations. These include worries about possible wrongful exploitation of donors, reducing altruism, undermining community solidarity, and commodification.

This essay is about semiotic or expressive commodification objections to commercial compensated blood plasma collections and donations. These are objections to various practices—like policies, laws, utterances, behaviors, and so on—that rely either on the social meaning or public understanding of the practice or of something associated with the practice. The conclusion of these kinds of arguments is that we ought to prohibit paying donors of organs or substances of human origin or the use of commercial companies in the collection or provision of these because this commodifies something with intrinsic value that ought not be regarded or treated in exclusively instrumental ways. These attitudes may be intrinsically wrongful; for example, it is wrong to regard persons as mere instruments. But they may also lead to downstream harms; for example, regarding a person as possessing merely instrumental value may lead to treating persons in instrumental ways.

One response to these kinds of objections is to ask whether or not it would be, all things considered, better to change the meaning of the practice to make it compatible with the intrinsic value at stake rather than to prohibit it.Footnote 1 This strategy is an option because it looks like these meanings are contingent social constructs. If financial incentives and commercialism will result in fewer lives lost, then a cost-benefit analysis of these rival strategies is likely to recommend changing the meaning over prohibition of the practice. Call this argument “semiotic revision”Footnote 2 or “revision” for short.

Revision may work in principle, but in practice some complain that changing meanings may be infeasible. This essay attempts to show that this is not so in a wide range of cases and uses the case of commercial compensated blood plasma collection as an illustration. Getting people to conceive of this practice not as payment for blood plasma but as compensation for the time, effort, and inconvenience associated with the giving of plasma is practically feasible and preferable to prohibition.

The next section describes the current global situation when it comes to therapies made from blood plasma. The section after that describes semiotic revision. The argument is that insofar as these objections rely on socially constructed meanings, we can change these meanings to avoid commodificatory and other predicted harms, wrongs, or bads. The remaining sections address the most important kind of objection to revision, which is the feasibility objection or what we will call the “FORTRAN objection.” The argument in response to this objection is that when it comes to changing the meaning of compensated blood plasma collections and donations, changing the meaning is practically feasible and is not like trying to get everyone to speak an entirely foreign or alien language.

Will there be blood?

We do not collect enough blood plasma to meet the needs of patients who rely on therapies made from the proteins in that plasma. These therapies include albumin, a variety of clotting factors, and immunoglobulin, among others. Immunoglobulin is used by people with mostly rare diseases like acquired or in-born immune deficiencies, a variety of neurological disorders like multifocal motor neuropathy, autoimmune disorders like chronic inflammatory demyelinating polyneuropathy, and others. Immunoglobulin is a World Health Organization (WHO)-certified “essential medicine.” For about 50 percent of the patients who use it, not having access to it means significant suffering or death.

We have shortages of immunoglobulin, with estimated demand outstripping available supply since about 2009.Footnote 3 We are not in this situation due to plasma donation being arduous or risky. Donating plasma is similar to whole-blood donations, although they are inconvenient and last more than an hour. Unlike whole-blood donation, people are able to donate plasma frequently (up to twice a week in some jurisdictions). Plasma donation comes with some risks, but these are rarer than injuries from fishing for crab, driving a truck, or rock climbing.

We have shortages in plasma therapies for two main and related reasons. The first reason is that the preferred models of plasma collection are inefficient and overly expensive, so that governments have been unwilling to spend the sums required to collect sufficient plasma. Every country that uses these models has plasma-collection deficits. The second reason is that the more efficient and less expensive models are so dispreferred that they are banned in most countries. Despite only operating in a handful of countries, these models nevertheless provide nearly 90 percent of the plasma used to manufacture plasma therapies—and specifically, immunoglobulin—for the world. The United States alone provides approximately 60–70 percent of that global total, including more than 80 percent of Canada’s, almost 100 percent of the U.K.’s, nearly 50 percent of Australia’s, over a tenth of New Zealand’s, and more than a third of the European Union’s.Footnote 4

The cost of plasma collections for the preferred models, all of which are noncompensated, has been estimated to be at least two to four times that of compensated collections.Footnote 5 This is mostly a function of volume, although there are higher marketing costs associated with having to remind, nudge, and cajole donors to give. In the U.S., the average compensated plasma donor gives 21.4 times per year,Footnote 6 while the average noncompensated donor in Quebec gives 5.8 times per year.Footnote 7 Noncompensated centers collect somewhere between 10,000–20,000 liters per year, while compensated centers collect two to six times that volume, with similar infrastructure and employee costs. These higher collection costs result in higher costs of therapies. As one example, commercial immunoglobulin therapies cost Australia’s health-care system AUD$45.90 per gram in 2019, while the therapies made from noncompensated collections came in at a cost of AUD$143.72 per gram—or 213 percent more expensive.Footnote 8 That year Australia used about 6.5 million grams of immunoglobulin, meaning that Australia’s health-care system paid a more than AUD$200 million premium to operate a noncompensated collection system.Footnote 9

The costs may help explain why governments are unwilling to dedicate hundreds of millions more to avoid plasma-collection deficits.Footnote 10 This is especially so, given that there are no differences in the safety or efficacy of the therapies whether they are made from the plasma of compensated or noncompensated donors.Footnote 11 What requires explanation is why countries such as Australia, New Zealand, the U.K., Spain, France, Italy, several provinces in Canada, and so on would prohibit domestically what they all rely upon from abroad to make up for their collection shortfalls.Footnote 12

Commercial compensated plasma collections are equally safe, are significantly cheaper, and are effective at meeting patient needs. Noncommercial, noncompensated plasma collections are equally safe, but are significantly more expensive and fail to meet patient needs, thus requiring imports of commercial therapies. But most countries prefer to have only the noncommercial, noncompensated plasma collection models operate within their borders. Why?

Objecting to blood money

Many reasons have been offered for banning commercial compensated plasma collections. Some of these reasons rely on empirical facts. For example, some worry that compensated collections for therapies will negatively affect noncompensated collections for transfusions.Footnote 13 Some worry that compensation will encourage too-frequent donations, and so harm donor health. Others worry that such collections will not benefit domestic patients but will be sold abroad to the highest bidder.Footnote 14 These objections are vulnerable in different ways. One way is that the empirical evidence may turn out the other way. This may be true in the case of the first two worries because the evidence we have so far suggests that they are either overstated or wrong.Footnote 15 Another way all of these kinds of objections are vulnerable is that they do not deal adequately with the significant variation in existing commercial models. A third is that it is difficult to see why these objections point to prohibition rather than changing regulations through policy redesign as the right solution.Footnote 16

This redesign response can also present a challenge to some defenses of bans based on, for example, wrongful exploitation. These objections seem overwrought and implausible given that plasma donation is not a big deal,Footnote 17 but even if they were plausible, they do not show that we should prefer prohibition to redesign. If donors get too little, we can mandate a price floor rather than ban the practice outright.

Semiotic arguments

Arguments that rely, instead, on social meanings or public understandings of these practices or the policies and laws that permit these practices may initially appear to be more resilient against redesign responses. They may seem that way because, as Julian Jonker puts it, they “seem to ground objections that are intrinsic, necessary, and a priori.”Footnote 18 They seem immune to policy redesign responses and, perhaps for that reason, are especially popular. Some exploitation arguments are semiotic, as are some arguments about autonomy.Footnote 19 When people argue that noncompensated donations promote (or compensated donations undermine) altruism or community solidarity, these arguments sometimes rely on the practice being publicly understood as a “gift” exchange.Footnote 20

Commodification objections to commercialism or compensation are often, and maybe always, semiotic. Semiotic versions worry that sales and trades of plasma will communicate a meaning associated with archetypal sales and trades that will lead us to regard donors or other persons as mere commodities.Footnote 21 This commodificatory attitude is a form of disrespectful regard and so wrong, but possessing this attitude can also lead to downstream harms, bads, or wrongs. For example, disrespectful regard may lead to disrespectful treatment; a phlebotomist may take less care in finding a vein or may be indifferent to signs of pain, discomfort, or a possible fainting episode when he is dealing with a donor he regards as being only instrumentally valuable. In taking less care, a donor may be harmed as a downstream effect of disrespectful regard. A very different example might be that sales and trades of plasma may “contaminate” the meaning of noncompensated donations by making us understand all donations, including noncompensated ones, in accordance with archetypal sales and trades.Footnote 22 This can lead to a loss in our ability to publicly express certain values or may undermine our thinking of noncompensated donations as a gift, given on the basis of altruistic fellow-feeling, and so decrease donations in general or only noncompensated donations.Footnote 23

Semiotic arguments are vulnerable in multiple ways as well. For example, we might argue that the purported norms and meanings of commercial practices put forward by critics are closer to stereotypes than archetypes.Footnote 24 A different way is to offer semiotic arguments against prohibition. It is not implausible to argue that legislated prohibitions on commercial practices express attitudes of domination, disrespectful paternalism, inegalitarianism or elitism, and a lack of trust in citizens that may have a corrosive effect on solidarity.Footnote 25 When we have good reason to believe that permitting sales and trades would save more lives or have other beneficial downstream effects, an argument could be advanced that bans express callousness with regard to the value of human life or an inappropriate weighting of the relevant values at stake. If we ban for the sake of altruism or solidarity, this plausibly expresses an instrumentalist attitude toward patients whose medical plight and vulnerability is potentially regarded as a useful tool to promote these values.Footnote 26

Setting aside these and other options, meaning-reliant or semiotic arguments are susceptible to the analogue of redesign in the form of what we might call “semiotic revision” or “revision” for short. As Jason Brennan and I argue,Footnote 27 these meanings look like contingent social constructions that can be revised. If so, then revision and bans would both address whatever harms, bads, or wrongs led us to worry about the practice in the first place. And if that is so, then these arguments are as incomplete as empirical arguments and we need to know why we ought to prefer bans over redesign for empirical arguments or revision for semiotic ones. Here, it looks like the thing to do is to do a cost-benefit analysis comparing ban to revision or ban to redesign.Footnote 28

In response, people have challenged both the possibility and the feasibility of revision.Footnote 29 Some have argued that the meaning of some practices are nonrevisable because they are not contingent social constructs.Footnote 30 Responding to this objection is not the focus of this essay, but it does seem implausible. This objection will probably fail whether you deny its being contingent based on some purportedly necessary association between a practice and its meaning or based on conceptual necessity. You can try to argue that for something to be a practice of this sort is for it to include some feature that embodies or leads to something morally ugly, but then there is “schractice,” which is just like practice without the feature that is or leads to moral ugliness. Claims about conceptual necessity will then also just collapse into cost-benefit analysis between whether we should have practice or “schractice.”Footnote 31

The more plausible rejoinder is that the meaning of some practice is so tightly interwoven into the fabric of our social meaning universe that it is practically closed to revision, even if it could be revised in principle. Most recently, Brookes BrownFootnote 32 and Kenneth SilverFootnote 33 argue that feasibility constraints need to be taken much more seriously as objections to revision. The remainder of this essay attempts to show that revision is practically feasible in the case of commercial compensated plasma collections (and in similar, related cases).

Practical feasibility

In defending an expressive theory of law, Elizabeth Anderson and Richard Pildes acknowledge that the meanings that expressivism relies upon are social constructsFootnote 34 and that they might differ over time.Footnote 35 If so, then we can compare the constructs or conventions and ask which one is better. Unfortunately, Anderson and Pildes do not tell us when we should strive to revise meanings rather than operate within their constraints.Footnote 36

Similarly, Anderson, writing separately, offers expressive (among other) objections to prostitution that are supposed to justify prohibition. With respect to expressive objections, she notes that there is a possible future world where “sex therapists” have sex with patients for money and that in this world payment for sex would not express degrading attitudes associated with the current practice of prostitution.Footnote 37 Unfortunately, Anderson does not tell us why, given that sex therapy would be fine, we should nevertheless prefer the strategy of working toward a ban rather than the strategy of working toward a world with sex therapists.

In a different context, Anderson does give us one bit of guidance. Someone might propose that we change the meaning of concepts such as benevolence and love in such a way that “agent-neutral principles could adequately express them” in order to “minimize the costs of a meaningful life.”Footnote 38 Here, Anderson offers an infeasibility rejoinder: “The proposed reformation of meaning is akin to asking us to speak FORTRAN instead of a natural language. The whole system of meanings in terms of which we understand our lives becomes unhinged.”Footnote 39 Perhaps Anderson believes that a world that allows sex therapy is infeasible or less feasible than banning the practice.

The danger is that if we allow practices similar to sex for money and fail to change its meaning to a sex therapy one, we might have a very bad outcome. As Brown says:

If the semiotic meaning of market exchange proves closed to revision in-practice, and if the damage caused by the existence of market exchanges in light of these norms is sufficiently great, then society has good reason to avoid marketization and individuals should abjure market participation, even as we may also have reason to decry those who make it the case that such downstream harms follow from the relevant expression.Footnote 40

As in prostitution, so too might we say the same when it comes to substances of human origin.

Before responding to this infeasibility objection, it is worth pointing out that the danger is not one-sided. Bans on commercial practices can also be dangerous. For example, banning alcohol sales turned out to be dangerous, while bans on prostitution are plausibly the source of similar danger and moral harm. Bans on commercial compensated collections of substances of human origin are partly if not fully responsible for shortages, and so responsible for unnecessary suffering and many unnecessary deaths. But in principle, it is clear that sometimes a commercial practice may be more dangerous than a ban in anticipation of such danger.

Is it true that commercial practices are practically closed to revision? Below, I argue that at least when it comes to commercial compensated collections of substances of human origin, they are not. To respond to this objection, we will first look at Margaret Jane Radin’s discussion of the legal practice of courts’ compensating people for certain injuries and treat that as a model. Radin defends something that looks very much like semiotic revision in a case that she argues involves multiple, contested understandings. She defends the strategy of attempting to coordinate on one of the inoffensive understandings of the practice, offering several practical ways to do that. She suggests that if that were to fail, then we can think about abolishing the practice. I will try to make the case that the practice of commercial compensated collections is also like this. If so, then the revision strategy will not be like trying to get everyone to speak FORTRAN, and so would not be practically infeasible.

Semiotic shift

Radin says that the legal practice of awarding a sum of money as remedy or compensation for pain and suffering (such as the loss of an arm or other body part) can be understood in at least four different ways. Two are commodified. On these understandings, when someone is awarded money in exchange for loss of an arm, what we are doing is paying people for their arm or trying to make people “whole” by making victims indifferent between the arm and the money. We can ask questions like “How much is your arm worth?” or “How much would you need to be paid to make you indifferent between having and not having an arm?”

However, there are two noncommodified ways of understanding this very same practice. One such understanding is a redress understanding, while the other is a kind of social insurance understanding. When it comes to the former, “compensation is understood not as a commensurable quid pro quo for harm, but rather as a form of redress: affirming public respect for the existence of rights and public recognition of the transgressor’s fault with regard to disrespecting rights.”Footnote 41 We symbolically communicate public respect for these rights through money, but “neither the harm to the victim nor the victim’s right not to be harmed are commensurate with money. They are not conceptually equated with fungible commodities.”Footnote 42 As for the latter, the payment is “supposed to give the victim some needed wherewithal to lead a satisfactory life, thereby making up for—compensating for—the capabilities or advantages the victim lacks.” And this is also noncommodified because “it does not suggest that the money payment is taken in trade for the harm, or equivalent to the harm in exchange value.”Footnote 43

Because there are at least four different ways of understanding this practice, compensation is “contested.” It is true that some might insist that a commodified version is what is “really going on,” but similarly others will insist that the redress or social insurance conception is what is “really going on.” It would be good if we were to have a persuasive theory that could tell us what is “really going on,” a way of adjudicating between the understandings, but Radin does not offer such a theory; indeed, it is difficult to see what such a theory would look like. On its face it looks like it is up to us how we understand it. How we come to understand this practice—what ends up being the dominant conception—matters because the commodified conceptions come with the danger of “degradation of personhood” and an “inferior conception of human flourishing.” This is intrinsically bad, a form of disregard, but it is possible that this may also lead to downstream harms like mistreatment. What to do to avoid this danger? Radin recommends that we do cultural work to demote the commodified understanding by, for example, avoiding use of “market rhetoric” when discussing the practice. We should not say that courts “pay” people for their arms nor talk as though courts put a “price” on arms, and so on. We may also want to redesign some of the details of the practice so as to make it easier for the public to understand it in a noncommodified way. Should these efforts fail, then it would be plausible for someone to argue that we should abolish this practice.

It looks like Radin is recommending semiotic revision. It might seem to differ if you understand revision to only be about cases where we create a whole new meaning or change the meaning from what it is now to something entirely different. If so, then think of this strategy as “semiotic shift,” a subset of revision. Semiotic shift is, for cases like Radin’s, where a practice has semiotic-independent net benefits and where there are multiple different social meanings or public understandings of this practice, at least one of which is morally acceptable. In cases of contested understandings, we are not doing anything like trying to get everyone to speak FORTRAN when we adopt a shift strategy. We are trying to get the public to coordinate on one or another of the available noncommodified understandings of a practice. This is not infeasible, although it may be difficult.

Donor compensation is contested

Much like compensation for injuries at law, the social meaning or public understanding of the practices of commercialism with respect to substances of human origin and donor compensation are also contested. There are transactions that involve both money and these substances, but are understood by some as an exchange of money for services and money for time, effort, and inconvenience rather than for the substance itself. In either case, if the public understanding is that people are not paying for the substance of human origin itself but for something else, then this would not amount to the commodification of that substance. Provided this preserves the benefits of the practice and avoids the bads, harms, or wrongs associated with commodification of the substance, then this ought to be the preferred strategy over prohibition.

For example, when someone receives a blood transfusion, they receive blood but also get the skills, time, and effort of the phlebotomist and the use of hospital infrastructure. In those cases where someone is billed for this, we can ask whether the payment is for the blood; the skill, time, and effort of the phlebotomist; or use of hospital infrastructure. Put differently, we can ask whether the blood is a good, a product, or property that was sold or whether what was sold was a service that incidentally involved blood. Whatever may be the dominant public understanding of this practice, it is in fact contested because at least some understand it in a different way.

We can also apply this shift to donor compensation. A commercial organization may receive a substance of human origin, but they will also receive time and effort from the donor who was inconvenienced. It is possible for the organization to pay for the plasma itself, but it is also possible that they are compensating donors for these other things. Even if we now think that the object of exchange is the substance, with time, effort, inconvenience, opportunity costs, and so on being incidental, we could shift our understanding.Footnote 44 This would be compatible with thinking that the substance is given as a gift, is “priceless” or “sacred,” and so could conceivably play whatever role “gifting” is said to play in encouraging community solidarity.

Below, I deal with the objection that this is mere euphemism, but let us first notice a few things. These understandings are neither foreign to our system of meanings nor do they require any sort of sophistication. It is perfectly ordinary and common to talk about the sale of time and effort, to distinguish sales of products from provision of services, and so on. Second, notice that while the sale of time and effort and being paid for services may in some cases raise commodificatory concerns, they do not plausibly arise in these cases.Footnote 45 Third, for all these reasons, this strategy looks to be practically feasible and, at any rate, is a good deal more feasible than the strategy of promoting a ban on, specifically, commercial compensated plasma collection—or compensated phlebotomists, payment for transfusion, for-profit medical services, and so on—in the United States.

Another thing to notice is that every plasma collection company in the European Union says that they compensate for time and effort rather than the plasma itself. The same is true in Canada and the vast majority of plasma collection companies in the United States.

Of course, you might think that this is mere euphemism, that what is “really going on” is patients paying for the blood itself and companies paying people for their plasma. What theory allows us to adjudicate this? While there may be other theories, my best guess is that people adjudicate this on the basis of what is desired or wanted. Call this view the object of desire is the object of exchange view. On this view, what the plasma company wants is the plasma, and so that is what is being paid for and, if the patient wants the blood, then that is what they are paying for. Our desires determine the object in any exchange. But this view confronts two difficulties. The first difficulty is that the “euphemistic” view appears to be the one adopted by courts and other official bodies. These rulings can form the basis of a public appeal that is likely to be influential on the public conception or understanding of what the object of exchange is. The second difficulty is that the object of desire, the thing people want, will sometimes differ as between buyer and seller. Let us take each difficulty, in turn, in the next section.

Perlmutter, Garber, and Germany

In the early 1950s, Martha Perlmutter had received a tainted blood transfusion at Beth David Hospital in New York and was suffering from the ill effects of “serum hepatitis.” She took the hospital to court and argued that blood used in transfusions was a product like any other and that the hospital is therefore strictly liable under products liability law. Perlmutter had bought the blood for $60, it was itemized on her bill, and so the blood carried an implied warranty of being free of the kind of defects that, had she known about them, would have made her not want to buy it.

However, the court in Perlmutter v. Beth David Hospital (1954) did not think that the hospital sold Perlmutter a product. In a 4–3 decision, the court ruled that the blood she received and the money she gave for it was not a “sale” but a “service.”Footnote 46 Even if the itemized bill said that the charge was for blood, what was “really going on” was the sale of a service; the substance of the exchange was service, even if it came in the form of a sale, and services do not carry an implied warranty. The court reasoned:

The supplying of blood by the hospital was entirely subordinate to its paramount function of furnishing trained personnel and specialized facilities in an endeavor to restore plaintiff’s health. It was not for blood—or iodine or bandages—for which plaintiff bargained, but the wherewithal of the hospital staff and the availability of hospital facilities to provide whatever medical treatment was considered advisable. The conclusion is evident that the furnishing of blood was only an incidental and very secondary adjunct to the services performed by the hospital and, therefore, was not within the provisions of the Sales Act.Footnote 47

Despite the good news for blood bankers and hospitals, many were unnerved by how close the ruling was, so they pushed for states to pass statutes that would protect them from products liability law in general. Several states passed what would become known as “blood shield laws,” exempting blood as well as blood products, including plasma and plasma protein therapies, from products liability law.Footnote 48 Simultaneously, the American Medical Association urged hospitals to stop the practice of charging for “blood.” They told them to charge the same amount, but to itemize it as being payment not for blood but for the services of the phlebotomists and other medical personnel as well as for use of hospital infrastructure.Footnote 49 They urged a redescription of the practice that is more consonant with a service conception of transfusion rather than a sales or product conception as had been the custom.Footnote 50 They also urged hospitals to have patients sign a waiver of warranty.

When it comes to transfusions at a hospital, being able to point to a court case is likely to carry some influence over the public understanding. The public understands the sales-service distinction and, if court decisions are influential on the public conception of the practice, as I think they are, then the public is likely to accept that hospitals are paid for the services of their staff rather than for the blood itself.

In response, you might say that hospitals hire professionals and you might think that a transfusion requiring some sort of skill will be relevantly different from amateur donors giving blood or plasma. But a year prior to the Perlmutter ruling, Revenue Ruling 162 (1953) rejected the view that donors give property when they donate blood. A taxpayer wondered whether she was eligible for a charitable tax deduction for the fair market value of the blood she donated. The U.S. Internal Revenue Service (IRS) said she was not, because what she donated was a service, not property, and the donation of services is not subject to a charitable tax deduction.

The same is true of the treatment of donor compensation for plasma donation in American courts and by U.S. taxing authorities. When donors are compensated for plasma, they are required to declare this on their taxes. In the 1970s, Dorothy Garber failed to do this. She had a very rare type of plasma and plasma companies competed to persuade her to donate it to them on a regular basis. She earned $70,000 to $90,000 per year donating plasma semi-weekly and received other benefits such as use of a car. In failing to declare this on her taxes, the IRS charged her with criminal tax evasion. One of the experts called by Garber had argued that her plasma was property that she sold, and so subject to capital gains tax rather than income tax. He argued that her “basis” in the plasma was equal to the sum of money she received, and so there was no capital gain and so no tax liability. She also tried to argue that the financial value of plasma, as a bodily product, was not only immeasurable but also incommensurate with money, and so there was no way to attach a price tag to her contribution or to tax her appropriately on this. The court found this unpersuasive and sentenced her to twelve months in prison. She appealed.Footnote 51

While the appellate court did eliminate Garber’s prison sentence, they did not accept any of Garber’s arguments. They said that it was not the sale of property but, instead, ordinary income that she earned. In ruling this way, the court effectively said that plasma donors do not transfer property to plasma companies and are not paid for the plasma itself but, rather, for time, effort, inconvenience, or other things associated with the donation of plasma that amounts to ordinary income.

Perlmutter, Revenue Ruling 162, and United States v. Garber (1979) each rejected commodified understandings or conceptions of blood and plasma in favor of the view that what people do is basically provide or sell a service that consists at least of time and effort. According to these cases, people do not sell blood or plasma itself; instead, they sell services.Footnote 52

Apart from court cases, consider that the object of desire is the object of exchange view needs to decide whether the buyer’s or seller’s perspective is privileged in picking out the object. What the company desires may be the plasma, but what the donor cares about in the exchange—what she regards as the thing of value that she gives up—is very plausibly her time, effort, inconvenience, and opportunity costs. She does not think about the value of the plasma to her; she thinks about the value of her time and effort and possibly the discomfort associated with donations. If so, then plasma is the object of exchange only if we privilege the perspective of the organizations, but time and effort is the object of exchange if instead we privilege the donor’s perspective.

Conclusion

While the euphemism objection may have a good foothold in the U.S. and in Canada, the same may not be true in at least Germany. Germany allows commercial compensated plasma collections and has a long history with the practice. My understanding is that they believe that compensation for time and effort is what is “really going on.” This would require a survey, but in discussing the case of Germany, Stephan Dressler writes: “In general, there is no payment to whole-blood donors, but plasma donors may receive remuneration … as compensation for their time. Many in Germany do not consider this ‘payment’.”Footnote 53 If Germans can see compensation as being for time and effort rather than for a product or property, then so can Canadians and Americans. We would be asking of them something not utterly alien but merely somewhat foreign: not like learning FORTRAN so much as like learning a few words of German.

Of course, these efforts may nevertheless turn out to fail. U.S. culture may resist this noncommodified (as to the substances) understanding of commercial practices with respect to substances of human origin and donor compensation. But given the benefits of these practices and given the costs of the noncommercial alternatives—measured in thousands of lives each year—it appears to be a significant moral mistake to prefer banning the practice over attempting to shift to a (relevantly) noncommodified understanding of it.

Competing interests

The author declares none.

References

1 I offer such a response in previous work. See, e.g., Brennan, Jason and Jaworski, Peter Martin, “Markets without Symbolic Limits,” Ethics 145, no. 2 (2015): 1053–77CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 “Semiotic revision” is the equivalent of “semantic revision” in the case of the meaning of words. But “semiotic” is intended to capture semantic as well as other meanings that include verbal and nonverbal methods of communicating or expressing meaning.

3 See Goodsall, Andrew, “A Plasma Problem: Dwindling Supply in the Face of a Growing Demand,” GE BioProcessing Asia Conference: In Review (2019), Figure 3, https://www.qgdigitalpublishing.com/publication/?m=61643&i=625153&view=articleBrowser&article_id=3499465&ver=html5.Google Scholar

5 Health Canada, Protecting Access to Immune Globulins for Canadians: Final Report of the Expert Panel on Immune Globulin Product Supply and Related Impacts in Canada (Ottawa: Canadian Minister of Health, 2018), https://donationethics.com/static/IGReport.pdf.Google Scholar

6 Schreiber, George Brooks and Kimber, Mary Clare, “Source Plasma Donors: A Snapshot,” Transfusion 57 (2017), https://www.researchgate.net/publication/321807978_Source_Plasma_Donors_A_Snapshot.Google Scholar

7 Hema-Quebec, Every Gesture Counts: 2019–2020 Annual Report (Montreal, 2020), 19, https://www.hemaquebec.ca/sites/default/files/public/document/en/annual-report-2019-2020.pdf.Google Scholar

8 The COVID-19 pandemic has resulted in significantly higher costs of commercial immunoglobulin. In 2022, commercial immunoglobulin cost the National Blood Authority A$75.59 per gram, while domestic immunoglobulin from noncompensated collections was A$118.99 per gram, or 57.4 percent more expensive. National Blood Authority Australia, Annual Report 2021–2022 (Canberra, 2022), https://www.transparency.gov.au/publications/health/national-blood-authority/national-blood-authority-annual-report-2021-22.Google Scholar

9 Slonim, Robert, “How Australia Can Fix the Market for Plasma and Save Millions,” The Conversation, September 2, 2018, https://theconversation.com/how-australia-can-fix-the-market-for-plasma-and-save-millions-101609.Google Scholar

10 Canadian Blood Services (CBS) requested $855 million from provincial governments over seven years in order to open and operate forty plasma collection centers in 2016. Those governments did not grant the request, but eventually increased budget allocations to CBS to permit only eleven new centers. See Grant, Kelly, “Blood Agency Seeking $855-Million in Funding to Boost Plasma Supply, Document Reveals,” The Globe and Mail, August 14, 2017, https://www.theglobeandmail.com/news/national/blood-agency-seeking-855-million-in-funding-to-boost-plasma-supply-document-reveals/article35980339/.Google Scholar

11 Albert Farrugia writes:

The convergence of appropriate donor selection driven by knowledge of viral epidemiology, the development of blood screening now based on molecular diagnostics, and the incorporation of viral inactivation techniques in the manufacturing process are now recognised as constituting a “safety tripod” of measures contributing to safety from pathogen transmission. Of these three components, viral inactivation during manufacture is the major contributor and has proven to be the bulwark securing the safety of plasma derivatives over the past thirty years. Concurrently, the safety of banked blood and components continues to depend on donor selection and screening, in the absence of universally adopted pathogen reduction technology. This has resulted in an inversion in the relative safety of the products of blood banking compared to plasma products. Overall, the experience gained in the past decades has resulted in an absence of pathogen transmission from the current generation of plasma derivatives.

Farrugia, Albert, “The Evolution of the Safety of Plasma Products from Pathogen Transmission: A Continuing Narrative,” Pathogens 12, no. 2 (2023): 1CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

12 The last country to be fully self-sufficient without compensation was New Zealand back in 2014.

13 This worry has its origins in the work of Titmuss, Richard, The Gift Relationship: From Human Blood to Social Policy (UK: George Allen and Unwin Ltd., 1970)Google Scholar.

14 This objection was raised by some supporters of prohibition of commercial compensated plasma collection in Canada.

15 For more on “crowding” or “encroachment,” see Jaworski, Peter M. and English, William, “The Introduction of Paid Plasma in Canada and the U.S. Has Not Decreased Unpaid Blood Donations” (Working Paper 3653432, July 15, 2020), Social Science Research Network, https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=3653432 Google Scholar. For donor health concerns, the most recent overview finds little evidence of significant donor health concerns, although notes that long-term studies are currently underway. See Purohit, Mitali et al., “Review and Assessment of Donor Safety among Plasma Donors,” Transfusion 63, no. 6 (2023): 1230–40CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

16 There are several different models of commercial compensated plasma collection, not just one. For example, the U.S. permits twice-weekly donations up to 104 times per year, while Germany and Austria permit sixty-five and fifty such donations, respectively, and the Czech Republic allows thirty-three. Each of these models is more efficient than any of the noncompensated alternatives are. Total protein levels are checked once every four months in the U.S., while Germany requires them more often. Egypt and parts of Canada have a partnership between the public blood collector and a private company that permits only that company to collect plasma (in both cases, the company is the Spanish company Grifols). Grifols collects exclusively for the public blood collector. The objection that plasma will be sold abroad to the highest bidder does not apply to these partnerships. This variation shows that the commercial model is flexible and can be changed. We can create catchment areas to address worries about the negative effect of one kind of collection on another. We can require more frequent checks on the protein levels of donors.

17 For an argument about why it is unlikely that donor compensation is exploitative in practice and why this would not, in any case, justify prohibition in Canada, see Wells, Mark and Jaworski, Peter, “Exploitation Does Not Justify Prohibiting Canadian Paid Plasma,” in Exploitation: Perspectives from Philosophy, Politics, and Economics, ed. Ferguson, Benjamin and Zwolinski, Matt (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2024), 253–74CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For an argument about why informed consent may require plasma donor compensation, see Taylor, James Stacey, “Why Prohibiting Donor Compensation Can Prevent Plasma Donors from Giving Their Informed Consent to Donate,” The Journal of Medicine & Philosophy 44, no. 1 (2019): 1032 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

18 Jonker, Julian, “A Dilemma for Expressive Arguments about Markets” (unpublished manuscript, 2019), 2Google Scholar.

19 For example, Lucie White presents us with a version of an autonomy-based argument that partly depends on the stigma associated with commercial compensated plasma donations. The stigma is based on the presumed motives of these donors and the reasons they have to do it. They engage in this practice out of desperation and it is the sort of thing that only poor and desperate people do for the sake of the money alone. White, Lucie, “Does Remuneration for Plasma Compromise Autonomy?HEC Forum 27, no. 4 (2015): 387400 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

20 Simon Cotton writes: “I maintain that gifting serves an expressive function. In communicating other-regard, gifting both affirms self-worth and possesses the potential to dissolve barriers to collective action by dispelling mutual suspicions and fostering solidarity.” Cotton, Simon, “Sacrifice, Solidarity, and the Scope of the Market: Why Might Permitting Trade Crowd Out Gifting, and Why Would It Matter?” Polity 49, no. 3 (2017): 355 CrossRefGoogle Scholar. He further writes: “Specifically, I argue that gifting has expressive value over and above its value in satisfying needs. As gifting is difficult to explicate without attributing a degree of other-regard (or altruism) to the giver, it serves not merely to benefit the recipient but to convey the giver’s concern. In doing so, it not only offers the recipient affirmation, but promises to dispel mutual suspicions and cement solidarity, the bond that sees those who share it be disposed to act as if part of a team.” Cotton, “Sacrifice, Solidarity, and the Scope of the Market,” 361.

21 For example, Adrian Walsh describes this objection when it comes to plasma: “One prominent justificatory ground for prohibiting such exchanges is the ‘Commodification Objection’ in which concerns are raised about the shift in attitudes brought about by commercializing human organs. The key idea is that commercializing leads us to regard the commercialized objects as mere commodities and, accordingly when applied to the case of blood products, financially compensating donors for blood plasma would lead us to regard the humans from whom the organs are obtained as mere commodities.” Walsh, Adrian, “Compensation for Blood Plasma Donation as a Distinctive Ethical Hazard: Reformulating the Commodification Objection,” HEC Forum 27, no. 4 (2015): 402 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

22 Archard, David, “Selling Yourself: Titmuss’s Argument against a Market in Blood,” The Journal of Ethics 6, no. 1 (2002): 87102 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

23 For an overview and evaluation of these kinds of arguments, see Gold, Natalie, “The Limits of Commodification Arguments: Framing, Motivation Crowding, and Shared Valuations,” Politics, Philosophy & Economics 18, no. 2 (2019): 165–92CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

24 As a recent example, Virgil Henry Storr and Ginny Seung Choi argue, among other things, that “rather than necessarily destroying social bonds, markets can and often do encourage their development … . Furthermore, the evidence also suggests that, rather than making us selfish and corrupt, markets both work better when peopled by virtuous people and encourage virtuous behavior.” Storr, Virgil Henry and Choi, Ginny Seung, Do Markets Corrupt Our Morals? (London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2019), 8CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

25 This raises an interesting question regarding the level at which semiotic arguments are made. We can ask what a policy expresses as distinct from what the practice that is permitted or disallowed by the policy expresses. Because that is so, it leaves open the possibility that what is expressed by a legislature is offensive or wrongful, while what is expressed by the practice is positive and prosocial, or vice versa. How we should prioritize in cases of conflicting messages remains, I think, an unanswered question for expressivists.

26 This interpretation is especially plausible in cases where there are many different ways to express altruism or promote solidarity apart from plasma donation, but only one way to get the material to create the medicine necessary for patients to survive or thrive. For arguments about why altruism and solidarity fail against practices such as commercial compensated plasma collections, see Faraci, David and Jaworski, Peter M., “On Leaving Space for Altruism,” Public Affairs Quarterly 35, no. 2 (2021): 8393 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

27 For the original versions of these arguments, see Brennan and Jaworski, “Markets without Symbolic Limits,” and Brennan, Jason and Jaworski, Peter M., Markets without Limits: Moral Virtues and Commercial Interests (New York: Routledge, 2015)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For a restatement and responses to some objections, see the second edition of Brennan, Jason and Jaworski, Peter M., Markets without Limits (New York: Routledge, 2022)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

28 Brookes Brown describes this argument as consisting in three steps. The first is “contingent,” the second is the “productivity thesis,” and the third is “cost-benefit analysis.” Brown, Brookes, “The Meaning of Markets,” in The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy, Politics, and Economics, ed. Melenovsky, C. M. (New York: Routledge, 2022), 229 Google Scholar. Julian Jonker calls this argument that turns a purportedly nonconsequentialist argument into one that can be addressed by cost-benefit analysis the “collapsing move.” Jonker, Julian, “The Meaning of a Market and the Meaning of ‘Meaning,’Journal of Ethics & Social Philosophy 15, no. 2 (2019): 187 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

29 Some have also given responses based on a narrow and technical interpretation of the original argument. These include Daniel Layman, Julian J. Koplin, David Dick, and James Stacey Taylor, who say that the semiotic argument amounts to the claim that because the wrong is merely symbolic, it is easily outweighed by other, nonsymbolic considerations (or are not genuine wrongs at all). Instead, they say that commodification objections to practices are about “embodiment” of nonsymbolic wrongs, are about “human interests,” or are mostly “impure” cases where symbolic and nonsymbolic wrongs are both implicated. But notice that here I am offering a broader conception of the semiotic argument, which is responsive to any kind of harm, wrong, or bad that relies upon (and so need not be constituted by) social meanings or public understandings, including downstream harms, wrongs, or bads. See Daniel Layman, “Expressive Objections to Markets: Normative, Not Symbolic: A Commentary on Brennan, Jason and Jaworski, Peter (2015), ‘Markets without Symbolic Limits,’Business Ethics Journal Review 4, no. 1 (2016): 16 Google Scholar; Koplin, Julian J., “Commodification and Human Interests,” Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 15, no. 3 (2018): 429–40CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Dick, David G., “Impure Semiotic Objections to Markets,” Public Affairs Quarterly 32, no. 3 (2018): 227–46CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Taylor, James Stacey, “The Myth of Semiotic Arguments in Democratic Theory and How This Exposes Problems with Peer Review,” International Journal of Applied Philosophy 35, no. 1 (2021): 1329 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

30 For an interesting attempt, see Sparks, Jacob, “Can’t Buy Me Love: A Reply to Brennan and Jaworski,” Journal of Philosophical Research 42 (2017): 341–52CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

31 Avihay Dorfman and Alon Harel have put forward perhaps the most ambitious effort to try to make a constitutive case like this for punishment. They argue that we could not privatize punishment or have commercial punishment practices, because only public, noncommercial punishment expresses the disapproval of the community. This disapproval is conceptually necessary for something to count as punishment rather than be mere vigilantism and only arms of the state can metaphysically express this meaning. Harel, Alon and Dorfman, Avihay, “The Case against Privatization,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 41, no. 1 (2013): 67102 Google Scholar. I tried to show how, in principle, we could privatize punishment by constructing an alternative metaphysics, in Jaworski, Peter, “Privatization and the Ought/State Gap,” in Nomos LX: Privatization, ed. Knight, Jack and Schwartzberg, Melissa (New York: New York University Press, 2018), 79112 Google Scholar. Brennan has responded by granting the claim that only state punishment could express this, which would mean private punishment is “schpunishment,” and then showing that we should probably prefer schpunishment to punishment, given certain assumptions about the effects of each. Brennan, Jason, “Consequences Matter More: In Defense of Instrumentalism on Private versus Public Prisons,” Criminal Law and Philosophy 11 (2017): 801–15CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

32 Brown, “The Meaning of Markets.”

33 Silver, Kenneth, “Markets Within the Limit of Feasibility,” Journal of Business Ethics 182, no. 4 (2023): 1087–101CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

34 Elizabeth Anderson and Richard Pildes write:

The expressive meaning of a particular act or practice, then, need not be in the agent’s head, the recipient’s head, or even in the heads of the general public. Expressive meanings are socially constructed. These meanings are a result of the ways in which actions fit with (or fail to fit with) other meaningful norms and practices in the community. Although these meanings do not actually have to be recognized by the community, they have to be recognizable by it, if people were to exercise enough interpretive self-scrutiny. This is the sense in which expressive meanings are public constructions. It is not that the public interpretation is infallible or definitive of what a practice means, but that a proposed interpretation must make sense in light of the community’s other practices, its history, and shared meanings. Thus, to grasp the expressive meaning of an act, we try to make sense of it by fitting it into an interpretive context. Contrary to some views, this does not mean that expressive theories require that “a norm display[s] its justification on its face.” The expressive meaning of a norm does not inhere in that norm in isolation, but is a product of interpreting the norm in the full context in which it is adopted and implemented.

Anderson, Elizabeth S. and Pildes, Richard H., “Expressive Theories of Law: A General Restatement,” University of Pennsylvania Law Review 148, no. 5 (2000): 1525 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

35 For example, when discussing punishment, Anderson and Pildes write: “To condemn meaningfully requires not a mere utterance, even in the form of a stern lecture from the bench, but a practice of punishment socially understood to express condemnation effectively, such as incarceration. Of course, the forms of punishment that properly express the requisite condemnation can change as cultural understandings change.” Anderson and Pildes, “Expressive Theories of Law,” 1567–68.

36 Anderson tells us that we can call “expressive norms into question, when previously unrecognized costs of obeying them are brought to light. The revelation of such costs is evidence that obeying the norms in question may not express appropriate regard for the people who suffer as a result.” Anderson, Elizabeth, Value in Ethics and Economics (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1995), 77 Google Scholar.

37 Anderson, Value in Ethics and Economics, 156.

38 Anderson, Value in Ethics and Economics, 77.

39 Anderson, Value in Ethics and Economics, 77.

40 Brown, “The Meaning of Markets,” 230.

41 Radin, Margaret Jane, “Compensation and Commensurability,” Duke Law Journal 43 (1993): 57 CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Anderson and Pildes similarly interpret nominal compensation as redress: “Compensation, even if not commensurate with loss, expresses recognition that the State is inflicting serious harm on individuals in the service of justifiable ends. Nominal damages for violations of constitutional rights play a similar role. These and other ‘expressive legal remedies’ matter because they express recognition of injury and reaffirmation of the underlying normative principles for how the relevant relationships are to be constituted.” Anderson and Pildes, “Expressive Theories of Law,” 1529. They do not raise the possibility that this compensation expresses a commodificatory attitude toward constitutional rights and treats them as “cheap” in being incommensurate with loss, where “incommensurate” means less than the suffered loss.

42 Radin, “Compensation and Commensurability,” 61.

43 Radin, “Compensation and Commensurability,” 62.

44 Incidentally, you might have noticed that I have been using “commercial compensated collections” and “donor compensation” throughout rather than “payment,” “paid collections,” “for-profit collections,” or “plasma selling” or describing donors as “paid vendors” as some philosophers have done. It is at least surprising that philosophers who express concern about commodification would use market rhetoric in this context when different rhetoric is available.

45 For example, the sale of sex would be no better if we thought of it as the sale of sexual services. It may not be better if we thought of it as the sale of time and effort associated with sex. Not all time and effort are the same. Time and effort involved in sex will likely be subject to the very same commodificatory concerns as the sex itself.

46 Perlmutter v. Beth David Hospital, 308 N.Y. 100, 123 N.E.2d 792 (1954). This treatment differs from the way France, for example, treated tainted blood transfusions in the 1980s and 1990s. Courts in France did find hospitals liable under torts similar to products liability law, which carried an implied warranty.

47 Perlmutter v. Beth David Hosp., 106.

48 It is worth noting that this decision plausibly played a role in the AIDS and tainted blood scandal in the 1980s and 1990s as well as in problems with the pre-1980s spread of hepatitis. When the scandal hit, most of the organizations responsible for collecting and distributing blood and blood products were exempt from any form of liability. Efforts to get compensation from the scandal are still on-going in the U.K. and Australia, for example. These exemptions from liability also plausibly contributed to the scandal. As Clark C. Havighurst puts it: “[I]ndependent action by individual firms motivated by fear of strict liability (or perhaps by greater exposure to antitrust penalties for coordinating their response to a public-health catastrophe) would have improved the survival chances of patients receiving blood or blood products. Contrary to Titmuss’s impulse, the wiser policy would have been to treat blood as an ordinary commodity and its purveyors as ordinary competitors.” Havighurst, Clark C., “Trafficking in Human Blood: Titmuss (1970) and Products Liability,” Law & Contemporary Problems 72, no. 1 (2009): 14 Google Scholar.

49 Kara Swanson writes:

California was the first state to pass a responsive law, declaring in 1955 that the provision of banked blood for transfusion was a service and not a sale. For those involved with banked blood in other states, the AMA advised changing billing practices: “Instead of making a charge for blood, the hospital should make an equivalent and specific charge for the use of its facilities and services of its technician.” Hospitals should still collect the money, but call it something else. Further, the AMA recommended getting signed consent forms from patients that the blood supplied for transfusions was “incidental to the provision of services” and no “warranty of fitness or quality” applied.

Swanson, Kara W., Banking on the Body: The Market in Blood, Milk, and Sperm in Modern America (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2014), 129 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

50 Incidentally, tax law in general has significant difficulty with categorizing substances of human origin as being either sales of products or services because, as Lawrence Zelenak explains,

(1) the distinction between labor income and property income is crucial under the income tax rules; and (2) there is no intuitive answer to the question of whether the transfer of one’s own blood, for example, should be thought of as the performance of a service or as a property transaction. The degree of personal participation—in both the self-creation and the extraction of one’s blood—suggests the performance of a service; however, the undeniable thingness of the resulting pint of blood, and its ready alienability and transferability, point in the direction of property.

Zelenak, Lawrence, “The Body in Question: The Income Tax and Human Body Materials,” Law & Contemporary Problems 80, no. 1 (2017): 52 Google Scholar.

51 United States v. Garber, 607 F.2d 92 (5th Cir. 1979), 94n1.

52 That we do not have a very clear idea of how courts conceive of this matter remains true. Despite the cases I have cited, there are conflicting cases about, for example, payment for the provision of milk to milk banks, the question of gift tax treatment, and so on. Most recently, for example, U.S. Customs and Border Patrol decided that Mexicans who cross the border to donate plasma for compensation count as employees of the plasma organization, and so could not engage in this practice using a simple visitor’s visa. CSL Plasma and Grifols sued and won a stay on the decision. CSL Plasma Inc. v. United States Customs and Border Protection, No. 21-5282 (D.C. Cir. 2022). Despite the stay, the court did not rule on whether or not payment for plasma counted as employment income for purposes of customs enforcement. Lisa Milot writes: “Under current law, the answers to these questions are unclear. There are no statutory provisions on point, and the available guidance from the Internal Revenue Service (the I.R.S. or Service) is conflicting and outdated. There are only a small number of judicial decisions in this area, and each is narrowly written to resolve only the tax liability of the particular taxpayer before the court.” Milot, Lisa, “What Are We: Laborers, Factories, or Spare Parts? The Tax Treatment of Transfers of Human Body Materials,” Washington & Lee Law Review 67 (2010): 1057 Google Scholar.

53 Dressler, Stephan, “Blood ‘Scandal’ and AIDS in Germany,” in Blood Feuds, ed. Feldman, Eric and Bayer, Ronald (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), 192 Google Scholar.