Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-g4j75 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-05T05:24:19.919Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Beyond the binary: Inferential challenges and solutions in cognitive archaeology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 January 2025

Cheng Liu*
Affiliation:
Department of Anthropology, Emory University, Atlanta, GA, USA cheng.liu@emory.edu https://raylc.github.io/
Dietrich Stout
Affiliation:
Department of Anthropology, Emory University, Atlanta, GA, USA cheng.liu@emory.edu https://raylc.github.io/ Center for Mind, Brain & Culture, Emory University, Atlanta, GA, USA dwstout@emory.edu https://anthropology.emory.edu/people/bios/stout-dietrich.html
*
*Corresponding author.

Abstract

We welcome Stibbard-Hawkes's empirical contributions and discussion of interpretive challenges for archaeology, but question some of his characterizations and conclusions. Moving beyond critique, it is time to develop new research methods that eschew simplistic modern/premodern binaries. We advocate an inductive, probabilistic approach using multiple lines of evidence to infer the causes and consequences of behavioral variability across time and space.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press

‘Modern’ is thus doubly asymmetrical: it designates a break in the regular passage of time, and it designates a combat in which there are victors and vanquished. If so many of our contemporaries are reluctant to use this adjective today, if we qualify it with prepositions, it is because we feel less confident in our ability to maintain that double asymmetry: we can no longer point to time's irreversible arrow, nor can we award a prize to the winners (Latour, Reference Latour1993, p. 10)

We applaud Stibbard-Hawkes's cutting-edge analysis of data from three African foraging communities and his consideration of its implications for archaeology. Nonetheless, we are concerned that his broader critique employs straw-man arguments that misrepresent the state of the field. In particular, Stibbard-Hawkes's analysis of logical errors in cognitive archaeology (target article, sect. 4) and subsequent discussion downplays widespread critiques of the “behavioral modernity” construct over the past two decades, including McBrearty and Brooks (Reference McBrearty and Brooks2000) and many others (Kissel & Fuentes, Reference Kissel and Fuentes2021; Kuhn, Reference Kuhn2021; Meneganzin & Currie, Reference Meneganzin and Currie2022; Shea, Reference Shea2011), some of which he cites in section 3. This amplifies unilinear and teleological views of cognitive evolution and erroneously portrays them as consensus. We suggest it is time to move from critique to the development of new approaches not organized around sterile simple/complex or modern/pre-modern binaries.

We advocate (e.g., Stout & Hecht, Reference Stout, Hecht, Wynn, Overmann and Coolidge2023) a more particularist approach to studying the cognitive processes behind the production, reproduction, perception, and variation of specific material cultural evidence (e.g., geometric engravings, cave painting, pigment, compound tools, etc.) by integrating experimental, ethnographic, comparative, and archaeological evidence. We agree with Stibbard-Hawkes that such investigations should not be framed around an assumed “null hypothesis” of cognitive primitiveness. We instead suggest (e.g., Stout, Rogers, Jaeggi, & Semaw, Reference Stout, Rogers, Jaeggi and Semaw2019) an inductive and probabilistic approach (c.f. consilience, Inference to Best Explanation [Killin & Pain, Reference Killin and Pain2021; Stock, Will, & Wells, Reference Stock, Will and Wells2023]). Our own work focuses on stone toolmaking, but Tylén et al. (Reference Tylén, Fusaroli, Rojo, Heimann, Fay, Johannsen and Lombard2020) provide a relevant example. Using Blombos and Diepkloof engravings as stimuli, they found that design changes over 30,000 years made these signs more salient, memorable, and easier to reproduce. This provides positive evidence for the use of these signs in an evolving communicative system but does not warrant conclusions about the presence/absence of symbolic cognition. Ethnographic studies can help us understand possible social contexts for such sign systems, as briefly considered in section 10 of the target article.

Stibbard-Hawkes argues that cognitive archaeologists routinely treat absence of evidence as evidence of absence. We agree this can be a problem, but not that archaeologists are generally so simplistic. As recently reviewed by Wallach (Reference Wallach2019), archaeologists often use the absence of evidence in a probabilistic way. This is logically valid and consistent with the move away from a “null hypothesis” approach. Kelly, Mackie, and Kandel (Reference Kelly, Mackie and Kandel2023) demonstrate the utility of such argumentum ad ignorantiam to identify behavioral patterns in need of explanation. Stibbard-Hawkes criticizes their “provisional assumption” that symbolic expression in a population would have left some material trace, but we see this as a disagreement about probabilities rather than a logical fallacy. Importantly, Kelly et al. (Reference Kelly, Mackie and Kandel2023) provide a balanced discussion of possible factors other than cognition that might contribute to the observed pattern. This is productive and can lead to further research.

This also applies to experimental evidence. Stout and Hecht (Reference Stout, Hecht, Wynn, Overmann and Coolidge2023, p. 6) review the epistemology of experimental cognitive archaeology, emphasizing that it is not possible to use modern data “to demonstrate the presence/absence of particular neuroanatomical structures [or] functions” at particular points in the past. Rather, the objective is to characterize patterns in the expression of particular capacities in order to identify the somatic, social, and ecological factors that favor their expression (i.e., evolutionary causation broadly construed). For example, Stout and Chaminade (Reference Stout and Chaminade2012) wrote that Lower Paleolithic toolmaking studies to date had not found “significant activation of ‘ventral stream’ semantic representations” suggesting that this behavior is not particularly demanding of such representations. They note that this pattern could simply reflect experimental design, but that “if this trend continues” it might suggest that such semantic representation “evolved later and/or in a different context.” This is a probabilistic argument about likely selective contexts rather than an attempt to date the emergence of a particular semantic capacity (as is unfortunately suggested by the highly selective quote in the target article). Rather than attacking straw men, we propose that cognitive archaeology should focus its energy on identifying potential causal pathways leading to, and likely evolutionary consequences arising from, the expression of behaviors across time and space, rather than attempting to date the “appearance” of particular capacities along a unilinear sequence leading to modern humans. Evidence presented by Stibbard-Hawkes can contribute to this project.

Financial support

This work received no specific grant from any funding agency, commercial, or not-for-profit sectors.

Competing interest

None.

References

Kelly, R. L., Mackie, M. E., & Kandel, A. W. (2023). Rapid increase in production of symbolic artifacts after 45,000 years ago is not a consequence of taphonomic bias. Journal of Archaeological Science, 160, 105885. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jas.2023.105885CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Killin, A., & Pain, R. (2021). Cognitive archaeology and the minimum necessary competence problem. Biological Theory, 18, 269283. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-021-00378-7CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kissel, M., & Fuentes, A. (2021). The ripples of modernity: How we can extend paleoanthropology with the extended evolutionary synthesis. Evolutionary Anthropology: Issues, News, and Reviews, 30(1), 8498. https://doi.org/10.1002/evan.21883CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kuhn, S. L. (2021). The evolution of paleolithic technologies. Routledge.Google Scholar
Latour, B. (1993). We have never been modern. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McBrearty, S., & Brooks, A. S. (2000). The revolution that wasn't: A new interpretation of the origin of modern human behavior. Journal of Human Evolution, 39(5), 453563. https://doi.org/10.1006/jhev.2000.0435CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Meneganzin, A., & Currie, A. (2022). Behavioural modernity, investigative disintegration & Rubicon expectation. Synthese, 200(1), 47. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03491-7CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shea, J. J. (2011). Homo sapiens is as homo sapiens was. Current Anthropology, 52(1), 135. https://doi.org/10.1086/658067CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stock, J., Will, M., & Wells, J. C. K. (2023). The extended evolutionary synthesis and distributed adaptation in the genus Homo: Phenotypic plasticity and behavioral adaptability. PaleoAnthropology, 2023(2), 205233. https://doi.org/10.48738/2023.iss2.123Google Scholar
Stout, D., & Chaminade, T. (2012). Stone tools, language and the brain in human evolution. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 367(1585), 7587. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2011.0099CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Stout, D., & Hecht, E. (2023). Evolutionary neuroarchaeology. In Wynn, T., Overmann, K. A., & Coolidge, F. L. (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of cognitive archaeology (pp. C14.S1C14.S11). Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780192895950.013.14Google Scholar
Stout, D., Rogers, M. J., Jaeggi, A. V., & Semaw, S. (2019). Archaeology and the origins of human cumulative culture: A case study from the earliest Oldowan at Gona, Ethiopia. Current Anthropology, 60(3), 309340. https://doi.org/10.1086/703173CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tylén, K., Fusaroli, R., Rojo, S., Heimann, K., Fay, N., Johannsen, N. N., … Lombard, M. (2020). The evolution of early symbolic behavior in Homo sapiens. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 117(9), 45784584. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1910880117CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wallach, E. (2019). Inference from absence: The case of archaeology. Palgrave Communications, 5(1), 110. https://doi.org/10.1057/s41599-019-0307-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar