Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-cphqk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T10:12:11.132Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Epistemological Disjunctivism and the Value of Presence

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 September 2020

David de Bruijn*
Affiliation:
University of Pittsburgh, Pennsylvania, USA
*
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Epistemological disjunctivists make two strong claims about perceptual experience's epistemic value: (1) experience guarantees the knowledgeable character of perceptual beliefs; (2) experience's epistemic value is “reflectively accessible”. In this paper I develop a form of disjunctivism grounded in a presentational view of experience, on which the epistemic benefits of experience consist in the way perception presents the subject with aspects of her environment. I show that presentational disjunctivism has both dialectical and philosophically fundamental advantages over more traditional expositions. Dialectically, presentational disjunctivism resolves a puzzle disjunctivists face in their posture vis-à-vis skeptical scenarios. More systematically, presentational disjunctivism provides an especially compelling view of disjunctivism as an internalist view of perceptual consciousness by explaining the way perceptual presence manifests the subject's rationality in a distinct way.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2020. Published by Cambridge University Press

Introduction

Let's assume that subjects are, by and large, justified in their perceptual judgments. In ordinary situations, when I judge that there is a red cup before me, I do so with some type of epistemic warrant. Reliabilists ground this type of epistemic warrant in the reliability of perceptual judgment. By contrast, experientialists hold that subjective conscious experience contributes independently to perceptual justification and knowledge.Footnote 1 For experientalists, it is my experience of the red cup that somehow provides my justification for judging that there is a red cup before me. Call the epistemically meritorious character that experientialists attribute to conscious experience its “epistemic value”.

Experience's epistemic value is at the heart of internalist approaches to perceptual justification and knowledge. While perception's reliability is not typically considered as subjectively available, conscious experience is or can be.Footnote 2 But the way experience is supposed to be epistemically valuable is notoriously complicated by the existence of misleading experiences, like illusions and hallucinations. Consider the way experiences include “good cases” and “bad cases”: cases in which the subject is actually perceptually confronted with her environment, and cases where she is not, though indiscriminably so. The existence of these “bad cases” can appear to undermine experience's epistemic value. How does an experiential episode contribute to perceptual justification or perceptual knowledge if, as far as the subject seems able to tell, the experience could be wholly misleading?

A recent, provocative approach to the problem of “bad cases” has come to be known as “epistemological disjunctivism”.Footnote 3 For the epistemological disjunctivist, the possibility of “bad cases” does little to diminish the idea that conscious perceptual experience bears an especially strong sort of epistemic value. For the disjunctivist, the epistemic value of perceptual experience (1) guarantees the truth of propositions that can be believed on its basis (in McDowell's terminology, the value of experience does not “stop anywhere short of the fact” (McDowell Reference McDowell1994: 29))Footnote 4; and (2) is “reflectively accessible”, such that the subject is in some suitable sense aware of the truth of (1).Footnote 5 In an example: experiencing the red cup before me, the disjunctivist holds that I can rest assured that my corresponding judgment will be true; moreover, I can know this to be the case. Defined this way, disjunctivism has understandably been referred to as the “holy grail” of perceptual epistemology, since it promises to relegate to epistemic irrelevance the perennial problems associated with hallucination and illusion (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2012: 1).

My aim in this paper will be to present a new solution to a puzzle disjunctivists are typically taken to face.Footnote 6 Much like the holy grail of medieval lore, most philosophers of perception suspect the promise of disjunctivism to be illusory. After all, disjunctivism seems to amount to a straightforward denial of the problem of “bad cases”. If a subject can know that her perceptual judgments will be true, then it seems she can know that her experience is not a hallucination. But ex hypothesi skeptical scenarios are construed such that the subject cannot know this. Accordingly, the problem is that disjunctivists seem merely to reject rather than to resolve skeptical scenarios. I call this puzzle disjunctivism's “dialectical infelicity problem” vis-à-vis skeptical scenarios. My aim in this paper is to show that there is a way that disjunctivists can solve this problem.

In resolving the disjunctivist's dialectical infelicity problem, the payoff of my argument will not be merely to improve disjunctivism's argumentative appeal – rather the upshot will be a re-evaluation of the philosophical substance of disjunctivism as a view of experience's epistemic value. As I will argue, at a fundamental level disjunctivism's dialectical infelicity problem arises because of the fact that even some prominent disjunctivists conceive of the view as a claim about the strength or status of experience's epistemic value.Footnote 7 Instead, I will argue that disjunctivism is best understood as a view of what experience's epistemic value consists in, namely the presentation to the subject of the very items of which she is thereby in a position to obtain knowledge. As I will suggest, understanding disjunctivism this way brings out a natural intuition that goes missing in competing versions: a perceiving subject is aware of being able to make true perceptual judgments because in experience objects are simply there for her, manifestly available for knowledge. Moreover, I will argue that appreciating experience's presentational character is critical to resolving the “dialectical infelicity problem”.

I proceed as follows. In §1 I introduce the classic version of epistemological disjunctivism developed by Pritchard. In §2 I characterize Pritchard's disjunctivism as a species of what I call an “evidentialist” internalist epistemology. By contrast, in §3 I introduce my novel version of disjunctivism as grounded in a “presentational” internalist epistemology. In §4 I show how Pritchard's version of disjunctivism faces the dialectical infelicity problem, and I discuss the way presentational disjunctivism resolves this difficulty. In §5 I discuss some important objections. Finally, §6 concludes by reflecting on the philosophical substance of the presentational approach to disjunctivism and what it means for disjunctivism as a type of internalism about perceptual epistemology.Footnote 8

1. Pritchard-style disjunctivism

The statement of disjunctivism in terms of (1) and (2), from which I started this paper, derives from Duncan Pritchard's influential exposition of the view. As Pritchard writes (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2012: 13):

In paradigmatic cases of perceptual knowledge an agent, S, has perceptual knowledge that p in virtue of being in possession of rational support, R, for her belief that p which is both (1) factive (i.e. R's obtaining entails p), and (2) reflectively accessible to S.Footnote 9

From this passage, it is clear that Pritchard envisages a certain division of labor in the way the disjunctivist conceives of experience's epistemic value. Specifically, the knowledge-guaranteeing character of a disjunctivist conception of experience's epistemic value centers in (1). If it is a slogan that, for the disjunctivist, the epistemic value of experience does not “stop short of the facts”, then for Pritchard this points to a more literal place that facts hold in a disjunctivist conception of experience's epistemic value. Specifically, perceptual experience is a factive state, which therefore entails the truth of a relevant proposition p. For example, a factive state pertaining to a tiger pouncing at me entails that there is a tiger pouncing at me. Now, for Pritchard it is clearly because experience's epistemic value entails the truth of perceptual beliefs that experience's epistemic value guarantees the subject an opportunity for knowledgeable belief (whether or not the subject manages to avail herself of this opportunity).

In turn, on Pritchard's view the type of “reflective accessibility” articulated by (2) specifies merely the way the subject is in a subjective position to exploit the epistemic value of her experience for knowledge. On this account, the subject reflectively appreciates her possession of entailing grounds for p, and therefore appreciates her being in a secure position to knowledgeably judge that p. Accordingly, the heart of Pritchard's rendering of disjunctivism centers on a specific explanatory connection between the epistemic value of experience and the beliefs it grounds, viz. a connection grounded in entailment.

For Pritchard's version of disjunctivism, it is important that perceptual experience relates subjects to facts, since it is perception's factive character that grounds the way experience entails propositions (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2012: 14). However, it is controversial to claim that we perceive facts,Footnote 10 and more recently philosophers have suggested that disjunctivists can preserve Pritchard's general model while avoiding the commitment that we perceive facts. On this view, disjunctivism can be grounded not in seeing facts, i.e. true propositions, but in seeing the truth-makers for such propositions (i.e. some set of objects and/or properties oon).Footnote 11 Since seeing is a relation, seeing oon entails the existence of oon. In turn, given that oon are truth-makers for propositions like p, the existence of oon entails the truth of propositions like p. Accordingly, even while seeing oon is not strictly a factive state since it does not take facts as its objects, it nevertheless entails the truth of p. In French's terms, the idea that experience presents the subject with truth-makers grounds a “quasi-factive” relation between experience and propositions, which suffices for disjunctivist purposes.

As French's reference to “quasi-factivity” illustrates, while we can distinguish different disjunctivist accounts in terms of whether they characterize experience as fact-relating or truth-maker-relating, nevertheless Pritchard's model captures something these accounts share in common. As printed in the table below, while truth-maker views deny Pritchard's connection between disjunctivism and strict factivity, these views maintain Pritchard's more fundamental gloss on the disjunctivist thought: the idea that experience's epistemic value guarantees true perceptual judgments by entailing the relevant propositions.

In the rest of this paper I will group together these various forms of disjunctivism as “Pritchard-style disjunctivism”. I will diverge from Pritchard's focus on entailment, and suggest that a better version of disjunctivism centers on a different fundamental paradigm: presentation.

2. Disjunctivism: Evidentialist

As the centerpiece of an experientialist perceptual epistemology, the epistemic value of experience plays a pivotal role in internalist accounts of perceptual justification. Experience's epistemic value is the support that experiencing subjects are supposed to have internalistically available such as to equip them to judge. In what does such internalistic support consist? To bring my version of disjunctivism into view, we should start from what is a broad consensus internalist answer to this question. On this consensus, experience equips the subject with a type of “evidence” for belief.Footnote 12 I will say that this idea marks “evidentialist” types of internalism.

To appreciate the structure of evidentialist internalism, consider a familiar internalist view:

Dogmatism: if it seems to S that p, then S has immediate prima facie justification for the belief that p.Footnote 13

Defined in this way, dogmatism in effect exploits a central feature of an evidentialist conception of perceptual justification to treat the way experience comes in “good” and “bad” cases. Specifically, the operative idea is that evidential support can fall short of guaranteeing the truth of the proposition it supports.Footnote 14 Accordingly, for the dogmatist experience provides some evidence for belief – evidence that is sufficient for the subject to be justified in forming beliefs based on how things seem to her in experience. But such justification is always prima facie. In a “good case”, if things are as the subject's evidence would make them seem, then the subject gains perceptual knowledge. But if things are not as they seem, as in the bad case, the subject was no less justified in responding to her experiential evidence. Rather, since the justification provided by her experiential evidence was prima facie and therefore defeasible, the subject merely fails to gain knowledge.

Of course, disjunctivism dissents from the dogmatist idea that perceptual justification is merely prima facie. After all, the Pritchard-style disjunctivist holds that in the good case experience's epistemic value entails the truth of perceptual judgments. But while rejecting the dogmatist's conception of perceptual justification as prima facie, Pritchard does not depart from the more fundamental paradigm of evidentialist internalism. On Pritchard's view, the relevant contrast is that dogmatists hold that evidence experience provides for belief is “prima facie” or “defeasible”, while for disjunctivists it is “indefeasible” or “conclusive”. Being “conclusive” and “indefeasible” are predicated of evidence: these qualifications characterize the way particular pieces of evidence locate on a spectrum of evidential support, specifically as located beyond a point where the obtaining of the evidential support entails the truth of the proposition supported. In this way, in Pritchard's rendering the disjunctivist's dispute lies not in what experience's epistemic value consists, but rather in the strength or status of experiential evidence. By contrast, I will now introduce an alternative paradigm for an internalist perceptual epistemology, intended not to qualify a type of degree of evidence, but to replace evidence as the relevant mode of epistemic support.

3. Disjunctivism: Presentational

Perception famously has a presentational character. As Scott Sturgeon puts the point:

your visual experience [of a moving rock] will place a moving rock before the mind in a uniquely vivid way. Its phenomenology will be as if a scene is made manifest to you. This is the most striking aspect of visual consciousness. It's the signal feature of visual phenomenology. (Sturgeon Reference Sturgeon2000: 9)

Clearly perception's presentational character is not that it presents one's environment in a “uniquely vivid way”. While it is true that perception stands apart from thought in its qualitative character, the point is not that perception is a particularly striking show of color- and object-experiences. Rather, the central point is that perception does present its objects; that, unlike in thought, the objects of perceptual experience appear quite literally present to one.

If presentational character is an important feature of perceptual experience, Broad has noted an interesting aspect of the phenomenon:

It is a natural, if paradoxical, way of speaking to say that seeing seems to ‘bring one into direct contact with remote objects’ and to reveal their shapes and colours. (Broad Reference Broad1952: 32–3; italics original)

As Broad notes, the presentational character of experience may seem in some sense “paradoxical”. Objects are external to us, yet in experience they seem “right there, available to us” (Valberg Reference Valberg1992: 4). The version of presentationalism at issue in this paper amounts to the idea of taking Broad's paradox at face value. Perceptual awareness appears to present environmental items precisely because perceptual awareness is the presentation of such items. Experience consists of awareness in which the subject is presented with aspects of the environment, i.e. objects and (arguably) their properties, such that the relevant features are present to the subject.

Before moving to give my account of perceptual presence, I should briefly note that by understanding perceptual presentation specifically as a conception of experience's epistemic value, there are other familiar associations with presentation to which I lay no claim. One such association is presentational phenomenology. Several recent philosophers have exploited presentation specifically as an aspect of perceptual phenomenology to answer questions about perceptual justification.Footnote 15 For my purposes, this is not the right notion since for these views it is experience's merely appearing to present truth-makers for representational contents that provides the subject with justification for belief. That is, presentational phenomenology is not unique to cases of perception, but also can be true of cases like hallucinatory experience. Accordingly, such a notion of phenomenal presence can never guarantee the truth of judgments it justifies.Footnote 16

My notion of presence also does not mark a naïve realist or anti-representationalist position, which is the idea that objects are presented in a way that makes them part of what metaphysically constitutes the experience in which they are presented. Characterizing the epistemic value of experience in presentational terms is a different issue. As has recently been pointed out (Genone Reference Genone2014), naïve realism is at least partly to be understood in terms of the idea that perception is not fundamentally a representational state.Footnote 17 By contrast, it is open for me to claim that epistemic value is best understood in terms of a type of representational content.Footnote 18

Finally, the position at issue in this paper must also be distinguished from the epistemological view that the objects of experience constitute so-called “objectual reasons” which perception provides the subject.Footnote 19 The idea of an “objectual reason”, on which this view centers, is that presented objects constitute reasons for judgment. This view is more specific than the presentationalism at issue here. My view is that the epistemic significance of experience can be understood through the notion of presentation, whether or not it is reasons that perception thus presents. As I will suggest, perceptual presentation constitutes a fundamental gloss on the link between experience and knowledge, which is something not captured by the notion of a reason as such.

What, then, is presentational disjunctivism? The key to this understanding of disjunctivism lies in a notion to which Pritchard-style disjunctivists frequently pay mere lip service: the subject's mode of “reflective access” to the epistemic value of her experience.Footnote 20 Recall the two clauses of Pritchard's disjunctivism: (1) experience's epistemic value guarantees the truth of her perceptual judgments; and (2) subjects can become aware of this epistemic value by having suitable “reflective access” to her experience. Pritchard-style entailment-based forms of disjunctivism focus on (1): entailment is an explanation of how experience's epistemic value is supposed to guarantee true perceptual judgments. But what about (2)? On my presentational view, it is only through a particular way of understanding (2) that we are in a position to understand (1), and to appreciate what it is that disjunctivism fundamentally tells us about perceptual epistemology. To state the relevant explanatory connection in a third table,

What is our “reflective access” to our mind? How do human subjects come to know the character of their conscious experiences? According to the answer that I will here follow,Footnote 21 such self-knowledge is simply internal to the conscious state itself. Compare the question how I know what I am presently thinking. Plausibly, such knowledge is partly constitutive of the act of thinking itself: there is no thinking a thought T that does not partly involve self-awareness of thinking T. The present proposal is that the same goes for the character of experiential states. In having an experience E I can become aware of features of my environment, but I also become aware of features of my mind, namely having E. More specifically, according to the view I have in mind this latter feature of conscious sensory experience is owed specifically to our rational nature as thinkers. States that are constitutively self-conscious are proper to thought, and extend from there to our sensory states.Footnote 22

Understood in this way, the way perceiving subjects enjoy “reflective access” to their experiences is critical in appreciating the way perceptual presentation grounds a version of disjunctivism. In experience, subjects are presented with the environmental features of which they are thereby placed in a position to gain knowledge: the chairs, tables, people around them, etc. Moreover, just in having such experiences, subjects are also self-aware that these items are presented to them in their experience. But then it follows that the relevant experiences are such that they simply could not be had should the relevant items not exist, or should relevant propositions about them be false. After all, in that case the relevant items could not have been presented in the way they are. Accordingly, perceptual presence guarantees (1) the truth of the perceptual judgments that the subject is positioned to make – and (2) that the subject can be aware of (1).

To further clarify, consider John McDowell's expression of the same line of thought (McDowell Reference McDowell2011: 30–1; emphasis in original):

when all goes well in the operation of a perceptual capacity of a sort that belongs to its possessor's rationality, a perceiver enjoys a perceptual state in which some feature of her environment is there for her, perceptually present to her rationally self-conscious awareness. If a perceptual state can consist in a subject's having a feature of her environment perceptually present to her, that gives lie to the assumption that a perceptual state cannot warrant a belief in a way that guarantees its truth. If a perceptual state makes a feature of the environment present to a perceiver's rationally self-conscious awareness, there is no possibility, compatibly with someone's being in that state, that things are not as the state would warrant her in believing that they are, in a belief that would simply register the presence of that feature of the environment.

As McDowell sets out noting, the way mature human conscious experience involves self-awareness gives content to the idea that capacities for such experiences belong to a subject's rationality: the subject's experience is a form of “rationally self-conscious awareness”. In turn, if the subject's experiences can include “having a feature of her environment perceptually present to her”, then this means that experience can ensure the truth of certain judgments. After all, the subject being in such an experiential state, in which certain environment features are present, is simply inconsistent with the falsity of these judgments.

Accordingly, we can now state the way in which conceiving of the epistemic value of experience through a presentationalist paradigm provides a non-evidentialist gloss on the disjunctivist view. In being self-conscious of being presented with features of her environment, the subject is aware of being in a position that ensures the truth of (appropriate) perceptual judgments. In contrast with Pritchard-style views, experience placing a subject in such a position is not a matter of the strength of the subject's experiential evidence or, in Pritchard's precise formulation, such evidence entailing propositions. Rather, it is a matter of the subject's self-conscious awareness being such as to have objects manifestly presented to her. The subject's awareness of standing in a perceiving relation to her environment is non-evidentiary.

So far I have distinguished my presentational disjunctivism from Prichard-style evidentalist disjunctivism. But I have not yet provided grounds for preferring the presentational paradigm over Pritchard's variant. Ultimately (§6) I will suggest that there is a fundamental way in which the presentational paradigm captures disjunctivism as a form of internalism about perceptual justification. But I will first turn to a more specific dialectical advantage.

4. The dialectical infelicity problem

My discussion in this paper has so far focused on disjunctivism's positive claim, viz. the disjunctivist's positive conception of experience's epistemic value. To bring out the present challenge to disjunctivism, I will now turn to its core negative claim, i.e. its treatment of the relevance of bad cases. Classically, disjunctivism's negative claim can be stated as the denial of a thesis along the following lines:

Highest Common Factor: the epistemic value of experience (understood as subjectively accessible) in the good case cannot exceed the epistemic value of experience in the bad case.Footnote 23

There are many ways of denying claims that philosophers have described as “Highest Common Factor” theses. However, we should here note that on the above claim the highest common factor concerns specifically the epistemic value of experience as it is accessible to the subject. This produces a problem. Perceptual experience equips a subject with an indefeasible, self-consciously possessed opportunity for perceptual knowledge. It would seem to follow that the subject thereby possesses indefeasible grounds for believing anti-skeptical propositions. After all, such propositions are straightforwardly entailed by the truth of perceptual judgments. But then it seems that the subject is capable of distinguishing her condition from the obtaining of skeptical scenarios. But ex hypothesi skeptical scenarios are such that the good and bad cases are subjectively indiscriminable.Footnote 24 This seems sufficient to suggest that disjunctivism occupies a dialectically poor position vis-à-vis the skeptic.Footnote 25

However, appreciating what I call disjunctivism's “dialectical infelicity problem” requires discussing one more wrinkle, since the disjunctivist has a response available to the initial worry introduced in the previous paragraph. The disjunctivist response is that the common skeptical description of good and bad cases as “indiscriminable” relies on an implicit argument.Footnote 26 The implicit argument goes as follows. In a skeptical scenario, the subject in the bad case cannot know, based on her experience, that she is in the bad case. By contrast, the disjunctivist claims that in the good case the subject can know, based on her experience, that she is in the good case. How exactly do these claims seem in tension? The implicit argument bringing these two commitments in tension centers on the premise that if the subject in the bad case cannot know, based on experience, that she is in the bad case, then the subject in the good case cannot know, based on experience, that she is in the good case. Or again, if the subject in the bad case cannot rule out that she is in the bad case, then the subject in the good case cannot rule out that she is in the bad case, either.

According to the disjunctivist, this implicit argument should be rejected. In effect, the argument introduces an auxiliary premise to skeptical arguments to the effect that a subject's knowledge of the nature of her experience must be due to a general ability for self-knowledge, such that the capacity for self-knowledge is operative in the bad case just as it is in the good case. On the assumption of this premise, as experience in the good case allows the subject to know some type of facts F about the character of her experience, experience in the bad case must also put the subject in a position to know facts of type F about the character of her experience. But the bad case shows that F cannot extend to whether or not an experience is perceptual. Therefore, the subject in the good case cannot, on grounds of her experience, know that she is perceiving.Footnote 27 Consider accordingly the auxiliary premise on which the implicit argument hinges:

Auxiliary Premise: If experience in the good case puts the subject in a position to know that she is perceiving, then this must be part of a general capacity for self-knowledge such as, contrary to fact, would apply to the bad case.

Understanding the dialectic vis-à-vis the skeptic this way, the disjunctivist's next move is to deny this Auxiliary Premise. For the disjunctivist, we can deny that experience in the bad case provides the same basis for self-knowledge as experience in the good case. Accordingly, in denying the Auxilliary Premise, the disjunctivist marks a distinction between the way the subject's capacity for self-knowledge operates in good and bad cases. Specifically, the disjunctivist seeks to suggest that what the subject in the good case can know about her experience is different (and “more”, so-to-say) than the subject in the bad case. In particular, in the good case what the subject can know includes that she is in the good case, but in the bad case what the subject can know does not include that she is in the bad case. Accordingly, the disjunctivist is committed to the following

Asymmetry Claim: the subject in a bad case is not in a position to know that she is in the bad case, but the subject in the good case is in a position to know she is in the good case.

This is where I suggest the disjunctivist faces the “dialectical infelicity problem”. Consider: what non-question-begging ground can the disjunctivist offer the skeptic in support of the Asymmetry Claim, other than that her position requires this claim to be true? That is, what recommends the Asymmetry Claim over the Auxiliary Premise? As a first pass, the disjunctivist may hope to exploit the general shape of her view. Specifically, the disjunctivist may hope to transpose her negative claim from perception to self-knowledge. In the good case, experience ensures an opportunity for perceptual knowledge, even as in the bad case it does not. Just so, in the good case experience ensures an opportunity for self-knowledge, even as in the bad case it does not. Accordingly, the dialectical position for the disjunctivist might appear as follows. The Asymmetry Claim appears to flout the indiscriminability of the good and bad cases. However, this appearance merely trades on the same illicit assimilation of the good case to the bad case that the disjunctivist is in general concerned to deny, this time as experience supports self-knowledge.Footnote 28

But this reply is too quick. The reason is that where in the perceptual case the disjunctivist's negative claim picks up on a natural distinction between the good and the bad case, this is not obviously true in the case of self-knowledge. Consider some set of environmental properties G, like redness and so on. It is entirely natural to think that perception is a capacity to pick up properties belonging to G, and that in the good case properties belonging to G are plausibly available for knowledge, whereas in the bad case they are not. But contrast the set of mental properties F. The question concerning the nature of perceptual self-knowledge is precisely whether “is a perceptual experience” is a member of F. Indeed, the upshot of the bad case can plausibly seem that it is not. But then the disjunctivist seems to lack natural grounds for the Asymmetry Claim.Footnote 29

Accordingly, this is the disjunctivist's “dialectical infelicity problem”. Disjunctivism requires the idea that self-knowledge is asymmetrical between the good and bad cases, but we have not been given grounds to favor this view over the view that self-knowledge in two cases is symmetrical. Specifically, the very aspect of experience that is supposed to be subjectively accessible in the good case, i.e. that a state is perceptual, is the aspect that the bad case seems to show is not obviously within a subject's capacity to detect (based on experience alone). Accordingly, the disjunctivist's best result seems a stalemate.

This is where I suggest that, in its reliance on a specific model of self-awareness, the presentational conception of epistemic value bears the unique value of resolving the “dialectical infelicity problem” for the disjunctivist. The central idea is that it is a subtle misreading to take the disjunctivist to repeat or transpose her core strategy of denying inferences from the bad to the good case, now concerning the way experience grounds self-knowledge. Rather, the disjunctivist's strategy at once distinguishes bad from good cases – both as grounds for perceptual knowledge and as grounds for self-knowledge. The reason is that on the presentational paradigm experience's epistemic value is conceived as intrinsically self-conscious, i.e. a single state intelligible only insofar as it provides grounds for perceptual knowledge and as grounds for self-knowledge. That is, the way a presentational state serves as a basis for perceptual knowledge itself resides in its nature as a basis for a relevant type of self-knowledge.Footnote 30

Appreciating the “dual character” of a single state of perceptual presence allows the disjunctivist to provide the following more specific version of the Asymmetry Claim:

Defectiveness Claim: The badness of the bad case consists not merely in a defective condition with respect to the subject's capacity to gain knowledge of her environment through perception. It also consists in a defective condition with respect to the subject's capacity to gain self-awareness of her state. That is, the subject in a bad case is not in a position to know that she is in the bad case because her state exhibits a specific type of defectiveness vis-à-vis the subject's self-knowledge. By contrast, the subject in the good case does not exhibit this type of defectiveness, and accordingly the subject is in a position to know she is in the good case.

What the Defectiveness Claim provides is a particular grounding of the Asymmetry Claim that allows the disjunctivist to overcome her dialectical infelicity problem. The grounding is that, given the foregoing, just as the bad case constitutes a malfunction of perception, so it constitutes a malfunction of self-knowledge.Footnote 31 Consider a case where the subject appears to be presented with some item, but is in fact not. This is uncontroversially a defective exercise of the subject's perceptual capacities. But now, if the subject's capacity for self-knowledge is implicated in the very same aspect of this state, it must also be a defective exercise of the subject's capacity for self-knowledge. That is, it goes to the very heart of the disjunctivist view to see it as a mistake that we can picture the bad case as involving a subject's functioning capacity for self-awareness in abstraction from a functioning perceptual capacity. A subject cannot merely appear to be in a state of presence where this is a failure of perception but not of self-knowledge, since being in a state of presence is a single modification of a subject's self-consciousness. In the register of self-knowledge, the bad case will make it seem to the perceiving subject that she is in the same type of state as she would be in the good case. But this is no different than that it seems to her that she is confronted with environmental realities, when she is not. The environmental realities are not there, and neither is she in a position that is like the good case.

This now allows us to appreciate the way the disjunctivist's original argumentative move can be “transposed” to the case of self-knowledge. Just as in the case of ground level perceptual knowledge there is no inference from the defective nature of the bad case to the nature of the good case, so the same inference fails insofar as it relates to self-knowledge. For the disjunctivist, the epistemic value of experience in the good case is such that, by the subject's own self-conscious lights, experience puts her in a position to gain knowledge of the environment. The existence of defective states of this type does not bear on the description of the good case, neither in its perceptual knowledge-granting nor in its self-knowledge granting aspects. Accordingly, indiscriminability is fundamentally asymmetrical between the good and bad cases, since the indiscriminability involves a failure of self-knowledge in the bad case. Accordingly, the disjunctivist need not face a dialectical infelicity problem in her response to skepticism. Perhaps the “holy grail” of epistemology is after all a treasure worth chasing.Footnote 32 In any case, doing so requires the resources of the presentational version of disjunctivism.

5. Objections

In the next section I will conclude with a reflection on the relation between presentational disjunctivism and what has been called “luminous” self-knowledge. However, first let me answer some concerns that may arise at this point.Footnote 33

First, it may be unclear in what sense precisely the presentational paradigm differs from the evidentiary one. It may seem the difference is merely verbal, turning on the colloquial meaning of the word ‘evidence’. But the distinction is more substantial: evidence and presence mark out two distinct modes of conceiving of the rationality of a state of knowledge. When evidence supports a proposition, it does so by providing a certain type of grounds for the subject's belief: grounds that may be very strong, indeed may entail a proposition, but are qua mode of rational support consistent with other relevant evidence or considerations. That is, when in possession of evidence for a proposition, the subject may find the evidence entails the proposition, but this is a contingent fact that the subject needs to glean from her understanding of the nature of the evidence. By contrast, the present suggestion is that perception is a paradigm of a different mode of rational support for knowledge. In being self-aware of perceiving, the subject is self-aware that the support for her judgment is right there: the nature of the perceptual mode of rational support is per se such as to be conclusive. That is, a perceived object is not an especially strong bit of evidence for a proposition, which the subject can glean to be conclusive. Rather, in self-consciously perceiving, the subject is aware that she is enjoying a state that by its nature presents conclusive support for beliefs. In this sense, the evidence/presence distinction is far from inconsequential or merely verbal. Indeed, the distinction explicates the substance of epistemological disjunctivism as a view of perceptual epistemology. Disjunctivism is not merely the view that, as opposed to the reigning consensus, perceptual support can be conclusive. Instead, it is that the reigning consensus, under apparent force from the possibility of hallucination, is led to altogether mistake the mode of rationality that perception involves.Footnote 34

A second worry concerns the claim that hallucinating subjects lack self-knowledge of a certain sort. On this worry, there is sufficient intuitive support behind the claim that hallucinating subjects are capable of correctly observing the phenomenal character of their experience that this claim cannot effectively be challenged by what appears to be a highly theoretically sophisticated claim that experience involves self-awareness. If this is true, then it can seem to revive a version of the dialectical infelicity problem: epistemological disjunctivism seems to depend on the mere assertion that experience involves the relevant form of self-awareness. However, there are two responses to this concern.

First, it cannot simply be accepted that an introspective claim about the character of hallucinations is immediately straightforward and unassailably “intuitive”. The claim that hallucinations lack phenomenology has been sustained by sophisticated observations about the character of introspection and buttressed by ample responses to objections by such philosophers as Martin (Reference Martin2004, Reference Martin, Gendler and Hawthorne2006) and Fish (Reference Fish2009, Reference Fish2013). Much more generally, “Cartesian” assumptions about introspective infallibility have long been a target of criticism in contemporary epistemology.

Second, we should be careful on the topic of how theoretically sophisticated is the view that experience is self-aware, and exactly what consequences it entails. The claim that experiential states of rational subjects include a self-aware element is not merely popular in recent philosophy of mind, figuring in higher-order theories of consciousness, self-representational theories of consciousness, various forms of disjunctivism and first-order self-consciousness views.Footnote 35 Instead, the claim is also among the animating ideas in philosophers like Kant and Aristotle. As one of Aristotle's paradigmatic statements of the view has it: “we perceive that we perceive” (De Anima 425b12-25). The upshot is that assumptions about the nature of introspection are highly fraught, and self-consciousness is a topic of profound historical attention. To be sure, it can rightly be said that I have not positively argued for the relevant view in this paper. However, given my aim in this paper of explicating epistemological disjunctivism in a critical respect, conclusively arguing for a view of self-consciousness must lie beyond my purview. I'm happy to establish the more limited claim that epistemological disjunctivism turns on a historically storied view of self-consciousness in rational subjects.

Moreover, we should be nuanced about what the epistemological disjunctivist is required to claim. The critical claim is that the subject's self-awareness is deficient, and she can therefore not differentiate her position from a perception – which is not a deficiency that is mirrored in a perceiving subject. However, from this it need not necessarily follow that the subject is wrong about every aspect of her experience. While I do not pursue this question here, it may be possible to allow hallucinatory phenomenology, claiming that the subject is right that it seems to her that p but wrong that she is perceiving that p.Footnote 36

6. Concluding reflection: self-knowledge and anti-luminosity

In this paper I have suggested a contrast between presentational and Pritchard-style evidentialist forms of disjunctivism. Moreover, I have suggested that presentational disjunctivism faces an advantage resolving the “dialectical infelicity problem”. In this last section I will conclude by briefly surveying the philosophically deeper significance of presentational disjunctivism in light of a popular argument first proposed in Williamson's Knowledge and its Limits (Reference Williamson2000) and since repeated elsewhere. I here address a version of Williamson's argument specifically tailored to disjunctivism by Haddock (Reference Haddock2011).

As I have argued, disjunctivism trades strongly on an intimate connection between conscious experience and self-awareness, since this connection grounds the subject's awareness of the epistemic value of her experience. The aim of Williamson's argument is to undermine the possibility of this connection, i.e. a form of self-knowledge that is intrinsic or internal to conscious states.Footnote 37 To arrive at this conclusion, the Williamson-style argument starts by positing that if a mental state is to count as knowledge, it must be subject to some reliability constraint. As Haddock phrases the idea:

let us assume a certain sort of reliability principle for knowledge: for any times t and t + 1, where t and t + 1 are any two times spaced only fractionally – say, one millisecond – apart, if at t one knows that something is the case, then at t + 1 this very thing is the case. (Haddock Reference Haddock2011: 30)

What is the idea here? The point is twofold: (i) knowing p requires suitable responsiveness to p being true; (ii) moreover, a capacity for such responsiveness must in some sense be limited in its sensitivity. Humans are simply not perfectly sensitive in detecting truths. As Haddock traces the implication of such a reliability constraint, it follows that where t and t + 1 are some infinitesimally small fraction apart, if a subject knows p at t, then p is true at t + 1. And if she knows p at t + 1, then p is still true at t + 2, etc. Otherwise, the Williamsonian thinking goes, we would not credit a subject with a reliable capacity for detecting the truth of p.Footnote 38

Assume now that p is the subject being in a perceptual state. Then, in an example provided by Haddock (Reference Haddock2011: 30):

if at t I know that I see that your sweater is brown, then at t + 1 I see that your sweater is brown.

But,

Now imagine a stretch of time between two intervals, at the beginning of which I see that your sweater is brown, but at the end of which I do not (perhaps this is a stretch of time during which your sweater is slowly starting to look a different colour, because the lights which make it impossible to tell the colours of things are slowly turning on).

Accordingly, we imagine a time span from t through t + n over which the subject gradually stops seeing something (in this case, that a sweater is brown). So at t + n the subject is no longer seeing that the sweater is brown. From the foregoing it follows that if at t the subject knows she is seeing that the sweater is brown, then at t + 1 it is still true that she is seeing that the sweater is brown. Just so, if at t + 1 the subject knows that she is seeing that the sweater is brown, then at t + 2 it is still true that she is seeing that the sweater is brown. And so on. But now assume that at t + n-1 the subject is seeing that the sweater is brown. Then, if perceptual consciousness were constitutively self-known or self-knowable the subject at t + n-1 is in a position to know that she is seeing that the sweater is brown. From this it follows that the subject at t + n is seeing that the sweater is brown. But we have stipulated that at t + n the subject is no longer seeing that the sweater is brown. Contradiction. It seems there cannot be a constitutive connection between conscious mental states and self-knowledge or self-awareness.

While these Williamson-style arguments have been widely accepted, for present purposes the philosophical interest is in seeing the way presentational disjunctivism would resist the objection. Specifically, the disjunctivism I have developed rejects the Williamson-style argument straight from its starting-point – i.e. the idea that self-knowledge is attended by a reliability condition. This is because for the disjunctivist (as I have specified her) it is the nature of thinking minds to have self-consciousness as a feature of their first-order consciousness. For thinkers, experiential consciousness simply is experiential self-consciousness. Haddock shows awareness of this suggestion when he concedes that “unlike my perceptual knowledge that P, my knowledge that I perceive that P is, for [the disjunctivist], in some sense spontaneous”.Footnote 39 As Haddock describes the idea:

whereas the object of spontaneous knowledge (e.g. the fact that I perceive that P) suffices to put me in a position to know itself (e.g. to know that I perceive that P), the object of receptive knowledge (e.g. the fact that your sweater is brown) does not suffice to put me in a position to know itself; to know the latter, I need to bear a receptive nexus to the object (e.g. I need to perceive that it is brown). (Haddock Reference Haddock2011: 29)

As Haddock here outlines, for receptive knowledge (of which perceptual knowledge is a species) the object is not sufficient for knowledge. Instead, the subject must bear a “receptive nexus” to the object. By contrast, for spontaneous knowledge (of which (the relevant type of) self-knowledge is a species) this is not true: the object of such knowledge suffices for knowledge. Therefore, having a conscious perceptual state eo ipso grounds knowledge of the state. But then the disjunctivist can give the following reply to the Williamson-style argument: the idea of a limited reliability condition applies specifically to receptive knowledge, but it does not apply to self-knowledge.Footnote 40 Therefore, the argument fails.

The disjunctivist's response to Haddock's argument illustrates the way presentational disjunctivism provides a fundamental gloss on disjunctivism as an expression of epistemic internalism. Internalism about perceptual experience is sometimes articulated in the context of the idea that the acquisition of perceptual knowledge is a case of “rationality at work”, since internalism includes the idea that perceptual judgment is a form of rational responsiveness to what subjective experience provides. Traditionally, it was thought that to capture this idea required a notion of perceptual evidence. And of course it is true that responsiveness to evidence is a paradigm of rationality. However, the type of rational self-consciousness that plays a role in presentational disjunctivism now suggests a different view of internalism. The rationality operative in the subject's acquisition of perceptual knowledge need not reside in responsiveness to evidential support. Instead, self-consciousness as such, extending as it does to the very experiential presence of perceived items, itself furnishes a distinctly rational context in which the subject can transition from experience to judgment. Accordingly, experience's epistemic value is anchored to knowledge not in virtue of its strength but rather just in virtue of what it is, i.e. a manifestation of presentational self-consciousness that belongs to a subject's rationality.

Footnotes

1 For experientialists, experiential consciousness is “undeniably epistemically enabling” (Tye Reference Tye2009: 98).

3 Henceforth “disjunctivism”.

4 Here and throughout, this concerns perceptual beliefs and judgments that are suitably formed. Of course a subject can fail to appropriately exploit opportunities provided to her by experience.

5 See Pritchard (Reference Pritchard, Haddock and Macpherson2008, Reference Pritchard2011, Reference Pritchard2012). The combination of (1) and (2) constitutes a statement of disjunctivism's positive claim, i.e. its characterization of experience's epistemic value. Disjunctivism owes its name to its more familiar negative claim, viz. that there is not a single account to be given of the epistemic value of “good” and “bad” experiences. I turn to disjunctivism's negative claim in §4 below.

6 For versions of the objection, see Silins (Reference Silins2005), Madison (Reference Madison2010), Dennis (Reference Dennis2014) and Soteriou (Reference Soteriou2016).

8 Specifically, I address worries about reflective awareness famously introduced by Williamson (Reference Williamson2000), and applied to disjunctivism by Haddock (Reference Haddock2011).

9 Variables altered, numbering added. In Pritchard's terminology, experience's epistemic value is the “rational support” it provides.

10 This is related to the “basis problem” supposedly facing disjunctivism (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2011; Ghijsen Reference Ghijsen2015; French Reference French2016). A subject seeing a fact p may seem to entail the subject seeing that p obtains – but “seeing that p” may seem to presuppose the knowledge of p that the subject is supposed to acquire based on perception. I do not think the version of disjunctivism developed in this paper faces the “basis problem”.

11 Haddock (Reference Haddock2011) and French (Reference French2013, Reference French2016). French (Reference French2016) has advocated cashing out disjunctivism in a form of “thing seeing”, and Haddock (Reference Haddock2011) has suggested a disjunctivist account of “seeing such-and-such”.

12 Clearly a subject does not infer beliefs from her experiential evidence, nor does evidential support need to be “quasi-inferential”. But nevertheless it is supposed that conscious experience supports judgment by providing the subject with a relevant type of evidence.

13 I modify this statement from Ghijsen (Reference Ghijsen2014: 196). Dogmatist views have been advocated by Pryor (Reference Pryor2000, Reference Pryor2004), Huemer (Reference Huemer2001, Reference Huemer2007), Tucker (Reference Tucker2010), Chudnoff (Reference Chudnoff, Miguens and Preyer2012) and Brogaard (Reference Brogaard and Tucker2013).

14 Indeed, this very aspect of evidence provides an early perspective on why disjunctivism is not best understood within the evidentialist paradigm. It is part of the nature of evidence that it can fall short of ensuring knowledge (which of course does not mean that any body of evidence must fall short). As such, the evidentialist disjunctivist will inevitably face questions on how exactly it can be that experience's evidential support can guarantee the truth of propositions. By contrast, presentation by nature is a confrontation with real items – accordingly the question of its support being inconclusive does not arise in the same way.

15 As Chudnoff writes (Reference Chudnoff, Miguens and Preyer2012: 25):

If an experience … justifies you in believing that p, it does so in virtue of realizing the property of having presentational phenomenology with respect to p.

Similarly, for Foster, there is a “[p]resentational feel of phenomenal experience – the subjective impression that an instance of the relevant type of environmental situation is directly presented” (Foster Reference Foster2000:12; italics original). For Huemer experience bears a “forcefulness”, such that “[w]hen you have a visual experience of a tomato, it thereby seems to you as if a tomato is actually present, then and there” (Huemer Reference Huemer2001: 77). For Pryor experience provides “the feeling of seeming to ascertain that a given proposition is true” (Pryor Reference Pryor2004: 357).

16 As Chudnoff concedes (Reference Chudnoff2013: 92; italics mine):

if a perceptual experience puts you in a position to know something about your environment, it does so because of something other than or in addition to its [presentational] phenomenology.

17 “Not fundamentally” because there are many less fundamental senses in which naïve realists can accept representational contents.

18 Indeed, I myself argue for such a representationalist version (de Bruijn Reference De BruijnMS). See also McDowell (Reference McDowell2013).

20 Pritchard does not detail his conception of “reflection”, merely indicating that his view requires a strong version. French explicitly sets reflective access aside (French Reference French2016: 90, 100). Haddock (Reference Haddock2011) and Stuchlik (Reference Stuchlik2015) are exceptions, but neither provides the account I develop here.

21 I cannot defend this conception of self-awareness in this paper that deals with disjunctivism more specifically.

22 This can serve as a gloss on Kant's famous claim that the character of intuition is conditioned by the apperceptive unity that is proper to the faculty of judgment, the understanding.

23 Locus classicus of this understanding of disjunctivism (McDowell Reference McDowell1982).

24 In an attempt to answer the difficulty, Pritchard (Reference Pritchard2012: Part Two) introduces a distinction between “favoring” and “discriminating” epistemic support. Rational support may favor believing that p without allowing the subject being able to discriminate her position from cases where p is false. Applying this distinction to the problem, Pritchard suggests that the type of “introspection” involved in (2) does not allow a subject to discriminate between good and bad cases, although her experience favors knowledge of being in the good case. I am not sure I understand the way experience can favor anti-skeptical knowledge without requiring “discriminating” support (after all, the point of skepticism would seem to be that the hypothesis of indiscriminability appears to undermine any “favoring” support the experience does for propositions about the world). At any rate, my suggestion will be that the disjunctivist does not require Pritchard's innovation.

25 Boult (Reference Boult2018) discusses a similar problem under the heading of an ‘explanatory challenge’ to epistemological disjunctivism. From this angle, the view advocated in this paper is supposed to provide an answer to this challenge.

26 See McDowell (Reference McDowell2018) for an exposition of the line of thought that follows. For other helpful discussions of the same point, see McDowell (Reference McDowell2010: 246ff) and Soteriou (Reference Soteriou2016: Ch. 5).

27 For a dense but compelling exposition of this understanding of the dialectic, see McDowell (Reference McDowell2018: 94).

28 As McDowell presents this point, the equal treatment of good and bad cases that disjunctivists consider problematic in general arises (McDowell Reference McDowell2010: 246; cited in Soteriou (Reference Soteriou2016: 15):

[n]ot only in connection with [perception's] guise as a capacity for knowledge about one's environment, but also in connection with its guise as a capacity for self-knowledge – knowledge that one's experience is revealing an aspect of objective reality to one.

29 To illustrate, let a “bad case” be one of death or dreamless sleep, while a “good case” is one of ordinary waking consciousness. As these cases show, there is no general symmetry of self-knowledge in good and bad cases (Soteriou Reference Soteriou2016: 3). Death and sleep are examples in which bad cases are situations such that you cannot know that you are in them, but good cases are such that you can tell that you are in them, and that therefore you are not in a bad case. On reflection, however, these cases cannot provide a model for the disjunctivist. The issue is that these cases are described such as to include grounds for rendering the asymmetry intelligible. For example, being asleep is not in fact like being awake. But such an intuitive ground for asymmetry is precisely what the disjunctivist lacks: it is not clear that self-awareness of the “good” case is different from self-awareness of the “bad” case.

30 Compare McDowell's characterization of experiential grounds for self-knowledge and experiential grounds for perceptual knowledge as aspects of the exercise of a “single capacity”, such that “the potential for knowledge that the experience is one of perceiving [is] contained in the experience itself” (McDowell Reference McDowell2018: 93).

31 In principle it is possible that the act of a single capacity is defective in one of its aspects, but not in the other. But for the disjunctivist, states of perception are modifications of self-consciousness, rather than presence and self-awareness being two fully distinct aspects of a single act. A malfunction of perception is a malfunction of perceptual self-awareness.

32 To see the appeal of disjunctivism as an anti-skeptical strategy, it is helpful to consider the fundamental way it diverges from neo-Mooreanism as a strategy (compare Pritchard Reference Pritchard, Haddock and Macpherson2008). For neo-Mooreans, anti-skeptical knowledge is inferential knowledge gained on grounds of empirical perceptual knowledge (on the model of inferences like “I know that I have a hand, therefore skepticism about the external world is false”). Disjunctivism offers a different conception, and a different diagnosis of skepticism. For the disjunctivist, perceptual fallibility merely renders philosophically obscure what in fact ordinary experience makes self-consciously available: namely that in experience objects are present, and that therefore skepticism is false. This means that anti-skeptical knowledge is in fact directly included in ordinary self-consciousness, rather than being knowledge that requires inferential reasoning from empirical grounds. For the disjunctivist, once the subject has undergone suitable “philosophical therapy” disabusing her of overreactions to perceptual fallibility, she can once again recognize ordinary perception for what it manifestly is: the presence of the world in her experience.

33 I again thank an anynomous reviewer at Episteme for raising these helpful concerns.

34 I do not claim there is a link between epistemological and metaphysical disjunctivism. But an analogy for presence-evidence distinction can be found in the contrast between the metaphysical disjunctivist's relational view of perception and representational views. Relationalists claim that the idea of perceptual representational content suggests that it is the explicit form of content that allows for rational relations to beliefs. By contrast, relationalists suggest this employs the wrong paradigm of rationality. Standing in a perceptual relation to an object is itself a mode of rational entitlement to belief, distinct from logical relations between representational contents. See Travis (Reference Travis2013) for vivid discussions of this point, cf. also Brewer (Reference Brewer2011).

35 Just a few examples are Rosenthal (Reference Rosenthal1986), Kriegel and Williford (Reference Kriegel and Williford2006), Martin (Reference Martin, Gendler and Hawthorne2006) and Rödl (Reference Rödl2007).

36 This is the view of John McDowell (personal communication). For the denial of this possibility, see Martin (Reference Martin, Gendler and Hawthorne2006, Reference Martin2013).

37 Compare Williamson's formulation of luminosity (Williamson Reference Williamson2000: 95):

For every case α, if in α C obtains, then in α one is in a position to know that C obtains.

“α” here is intended to cover any possible case, and C is intended to cover a mental condition (e.g. being in an experiential state).

38 Compare knowing a cup is red at t. If at t + 1 its color has suddenly altered (and, one assumes, this is generally how the colors of cups behave), one presumably just lacks a capacity for detecting the colors of cups. Changes at infinitesimally small temporal intervals are simply beyond the human senses to detect, and accordingly beyond human capacities to know. Or so the Williamsonian thought appears to go.

39 For more on “spontaneous” self-knowledge, invoked by Haddock, see Rödl (Reference Rödl2007).

40 For example, limited reliability plausibly characterizes the sort of tracking capacities that are required for the subject to bear the appropriate “receptive nexus” to the objects of her receptive knowledge. I cannot count as possessing receptive knowledge of p if I am not within an appropriate range of sensitivity to the obtaining of p. But that does not bear on the relevant sort of self-knowledge.

References

Boult, C. (2018). ‘An Explanatory Challenge for Epistemological Disjunctivism.’ Episteme 15(2), 141–53.10.1017/epi.2016.46CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brewer, B. (2011). Perception and its Objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199260256.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brewer, B. (2018). ‘Objectual Reasons.’ Analytic Philosophy 59(1), 118.10.1111/phib.12123CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broad, C.D. (1952). ‘Some Elementary Reflexions on Sense-Perception.’ Philosophy 27(100), 317. Reprinted in Swartz R. (1965). Perceiving, Sensing, and Knowing (Topics in Philosophy IV). Berkeley, CA: California University Press.10.1017/S0031819100019732CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brogaard, B. (2013). ‘Phenomenal Seemings and Sensible Dogmatism.’ In Tucker, C. (ed.), Seemings and Justification: New Essays on Dogmatism and Phenomenal Conservatism, pp. 270–89. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199899494.003.0012CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chudnoff, E. (2012). ‘Presentational Phenomenology’. In Miguens, S. and Preyer, G. (eds), Consciousness and Subjectivity, pp. 5172. Heusenstamm: Ontos Verlag.Google Scholar
Chudnoff, E. (2013). Intuition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cunningham, J.J. (2017). ‘Are Perceptual Reasons the Objects of Perception?’ In Gersel, J., Jensen, R.T., Thaning, M.S. and Overgaard, S. (eds), In the Light of Experience – Essays on Reason and Perception, pp. 256–80. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
De Bruijn, D. (MS) ‘Perceptual Content and Lucid Looks.’Google Scholar
Dennis, P. (2014). ‘Criteria for Indefeasible Knowledge: John McDowell and ‘Epistemological Disjunctivism’. Synthese 191, 4099–113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fish, W. (2009). Perception, Hallucination, and Illusion. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195381344.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fish, W. (2013). ‘Perception, Hallucination and Illusion: Reply to my Critics.’ Philosophical Studies 163(1), 5766.10.1007/s11098-012-0072-8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foster, J. (2000). The Nature of Perception. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
French, C. (2013). ‘Perceptual Experience and Seeing that p.’ Synthese 190, 1735–51.10.1007/s11229-013-0259-3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
French, C. (2016). ‘The Formulation of Epistemological Disjunctivism.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 92(1), 86104.10.1111/phpr.12105CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Genone, J. (2014). ‘Appearance and Illusion.’ Mind 123(490), 339–76.10.1093/mind/fzu056CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ghijsen, H. (2014). ‘Phenomenalist Dogmatist Experientialism and the Distinctiveness Problem.’ Synthese 191, 1549–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ghijsen, H. (2015). ‘The Basis Problem for Epistemological Disjunctivism Revisited.’ Erkenntnis 80, 1147–56.10.1007/s10670-014-9715-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haddock, A. (2011). ‘The Disjunctive Conception of Seeing.’ Philosophical Explorations 14(1), 2342.10.1080/13869795.2011.544399CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huemer, M. (2001). Skepticism and the Veil of Perception. New York, NY: Rowe and Littleman.Google Scholar
Huemer, M. (2007). ‘Compassionate Phenomenal Conservatism.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74(1), 3055.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kalderon, M. (2011). ‘Before the Law.’ Philosophical Issues 21, 219–43.10.1111/j.1533-6077.2011.00202.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kriegel, U. and Williford, K. (2006). Self-Representational Theories of Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Madison, B.J.C. (2010). ‘Epistemic Internalism.’ Philosophy Compass 5(10), 840–53.10.1111/j.1747-9991.2010.00333.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, M.G.F. (2004). ‘The Limits of Self-Awareness.’ Philosophical Studies 120, 3789.10.1023/B:PHIL.0000033751.66949.97CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, M.G.F. (2006). ‘On Being Alienated.’ In Gendler, T.S. and Hawthorne, J. (eds), Perceptual Experience, pp. 354410. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199289769.003.0011CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, M.G.F. (2013). ‘Shibboleth: Some Comments on William Fish's “Perception, Hallucination & Illusion”.’ Philosophical Studies 163(1), 3748.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, J. (1982). ‘Criteria, Defeasibility and Knowledge.’ Proceedings of the British Academy 68, 455–79.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. (1994). Mind and World. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. (2010). ‘Tyler Burge on Disjunctivism’. Philosophical Explorations 13(3), 243–55.10.1080/13869795.2010.501905CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, J. (2011). Perception as a Capacity for Knowledge. Milwaukee, WI: Marquette University Press.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. (2013). ‘Perception: Both Relational and Contentful.’ European Journal of Philosophy 21(11), 144–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, J. (2018). ‘Perceptual Experience and Empirical Rationality.’ Analytic Philosophy 59(1), 8998.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pritchard, D. (2008). ‘McDowellian Neo-Mooreanism.’ In Haddock, A. and Macpherson, F. (eds), Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, Knowledge, pp. 283310. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199231546.003.0013CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pritchard, D. (2011). ‘Epistemological Disjunctivism and the Basis Problem.’ Philosophical Issues 21, 434–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pritchard, D. (2012). Epistemological Disjunctivism. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199557912.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pryor, J. (2000). ‘The Skeptic and the Dogmatist.’ Noûs 34(4), 517–49.10.1111/0029-4624.00277CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pryor, J. (2004). ‘What's Wrong with Moore's Argument?Philosophical Issues 14, 349–78.10.1111/j.1533-6077.2004.00034.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rödl, S (2007). Self-Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rosenthal, D. (1986). ‘Two Concepts of Consciousness.’ Philosophical Studies 49, 329–59.10.1007/BF00355521CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silins, N. (2005). ‘Deception and Evidence.’ Philosophical Perspectives 19, 375404.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Soteriou, M. (2016). Disjunctivism. New York, NY: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stuchlik, J. (2015). ‘Epistemological Disjunctivism and Easy Knowledge.’ Synthese 192, 2647–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sturgeon, S. (2000). Matters of Mind: Consciousness, Reason and Nature. New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
Tucker, C. (2010). ‘Why Open-Minded People Should Endorse Dogmatism.’ Philosophical Perspectives 24, 529–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tye, M. (2009). Consciousness Revisited: Materialism without Phenomenal Concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Travis, C. (2013). Perception: Essays After Frege. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199676545.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Valberg, J.J. (1992). The Puzzle of Experience. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its Limits. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar