Introduction
There is often a lurking suspicion in the popular imagination that the Catholic Church holds a vast repository of ancient documents that threaten to destroy the Church's authority if they ever reached the light of day. These noncanonical documents, as the stories generally go, were deemed heretical at some point in time and nearly destroyed, and are now allegedly stored deep within the secret vaults of the Vatican's archives, so that their testimony—their contradictory witness to the normative historical record—could be confidently suppressed, and the Church could go about dominating history as it deems fit.Footnote 1 The truth, of course, is that the Catholic Church has at times engaged in tactics such as these, though such acts of erasure and censure, one hopes, are nearing their end. The tantalizing power of these “repressed” narratives eventually coming to light, however, is often enough to provoke the desires of those who feel their stories too are marginalized and in need of mainstream representation within the given media of their community. Such desires, for example, have been behind calls to admit the Bible's hegemonic status among other texts and likewise to open the canon of Scripture to other “noncanonical” works.Footnote 2
What this all-too-contemporary tale does not take into account, however, are the dynamics that govern the nature of canonical (and hence scriptural) representations themselves, the historical evolutions that mark Scripture's core coming-to-be—those processes termed canonicity.Footnote 3 It is these processes themselves that offer us an insight into how any such “repressed narrative” might be capable of finding its own story reflected, not only in the ever-changing (more or less) open literary canons of the world, but in the sacred, closed form of the canonical as well—a text that, by definition, is certainly capable of containing the opposed tensions of a desire for law and a call for justice simultaneously within its own pages. This is not to suggest, however, that every closed or sacred canon performs such an act; indeed, this article intends to produce a series of criteria centered on the principle of violence—as developed through the works of Jan Assmann and René Girard—by which various sacred canons might be evaluated and therefore in some sense rendered distinguishable from one another.
Canons, in their earliest forms, were a refinement of cultural and religious archives, a solid body of normative “texts” transmitted from one generation to another in order to identify and shape a given community. Such canons were either orally transmitted or written and could be used for either cultural or religious purposes (or both at the same time, as was often the case in the ancient world). However, it was only the latter purposes (and even then generally in written form only) that led to the formation of a sacred scripture as we know it today in its Western monotheistic forms.
The question that the creation of such normative structures raises, however, is this: what are we to make of the place of such selected texts within a particular culture, given that other texts, indeed other archives, were not chosen to identify the community? Are such texts (like the early Gnostic writings, for example) simply to be burned or buried in the sands of history? Should (or even could) they be placed alongside the more normative canonical texts? In other words, the basic question is whether or not selected canonical texts are capable of being distinguished from one another with regard to their relationship to noncanonical, archival, and “excessive” texts. That is, do some canons welcome their noncanonical counterparts within the same archive (or particular tradition) while others support an institution that would suppress, distort, or discard them? What kinds of violence are canonical texts able to enclose within themselves in order to achieve canonical status? Or can such a normative status be achieved otherwise than by violent means? And what would such a canonical form look like?
In essence, I argue in this article that the canonical form can be seen to fluctuate along a sliding scale of normative texts that serve to either (1) deal with their noncanonical counterparts and hence acknowledge their omission as necessary to the formation of normative texts (the definition of the “violence” that any canon could be said to perform), or (2) conceal or repress those very same violent acts. It is with the former, however, that a new avenue for understanding the canonical (and hence scriptural) form is opened up. Such an understanding in fact could be considered as “nonviolent” (or perhaps simply “less” violent) insofar as it is able to provide narration for those persons whose stories are repressed in their particular sociocultural contexts. Such canonical texts could possibly also lead to further contestations against the violence of unnecessary repressions or exclusions. This form of a canon, if openly demonstrated, can provide a way for socially marginalized figures to rewrite their own personal or communal narratives within the stories of that particular (often sacred) canon and thereby find avenues for the representation of their socially constituted identities. This is so because their stories of marginalization and repression will have already been present in the canonical text as stories that themselves reveal the violences of repression. In this fashion, revelation becomes structurally bound to the canonical form itself and as such truly becomes an ongoing well-spring of justice found in canonical scriptural forms, as I hope to make clear in what follows. This characteristic could moreover be said to be guaranteed by the processes of canonicity themselves, which continue long past the formation of an actual canon.
It becomes even more important to make this distinction between canonical forms when one stops to consider recent sustained criticisms levied against the monotheistic worldview brought about by the Judeo-Christian canon.Footnote 4 Such critiques are often directed toward religious scripture, though, as we will soon see, these critical voices also indicate that a general call toward opening the canonical form is not isolated to the recent past or a contemporary popularized cultural imagination. They demonstrate how the issue with canons extends beyond religious scripture and toward a perspective on canonical texts as a whole. Accordingly, engagement with these dynamics needs to occur within a more contemporary theological framework if the canonical form is to be shown as necessary for religious-cultural signification and as the basis of religious identity formation in general, and not simply as a source of an unnecessary and detestable violence.
In what follows, I hope to show that it is no coincidence that many scholars locate the site of a particular (monotheistic) violence in the nature of canons themselves.Footnote 5 This is so because the establishment of the canon actually functions as a fundamental act of violence insofar as its construction and representation of the “other” are thoroughly invested in the processes of marking boundaries—of separating oneself from others (traditionally, those subject to another canonical culture). This feature is considered in fact to be a mark of a canon's “nontranslatability,” as we will see—a trait that renders the canon less fluid in cultural terms and causes canons to be firmly rooted in a particular religious or national context.Footnote 6 I will show, moreover, that this feature is a necessity for identity formation and representation in general, and is inherently connected to the establishment and prominence of cultural canonical forms. It would seem, then, that there are only those canons that conceal the violence they perform—and thus multiply its effects and aftereffects—or those that disclose their proximity to violence and thereby offer an ever-increasing sense of justice a chance to flourish instead.Footnote 7 And it is precisely by allowing these general characteristics of canons to unfold before us that we will begin to see just how relevant the specifically Judeo-Christian Scriptures can be amid so many competing canons today.
1. On Monotheism and Violence
It has long been recognized within scholarship on the canonical form that the canon itself has what James Sanders refers to as a “monotheizing tendency”—a habit of dividing existent reality into binary forms. This fact is often responsible for the clichéd stereotyping of the “us-versus-them” mentality, though such a characterization does bear a certain political truth.Footnote 8 From this perspective, it should come as no surprise that reactions to the biblical canon's partitioning of reality into such demarcated spaces have been frequent and often harsh.Footnote 9 One of the more recently influential and thus exemplary studies to put forward a general condemnation of the canonical form is Regina Schwartz's The Curse of Cain, a polemically structured critique of the monotheistic (biblical) canon. For Schwartz, the biblical narrative became in fact the foundation for “Western culture's central myth of collective identity.” Utilizing the linked concepts of “scarcity” and “oneness” (associated with the exclusivity of a monotheistic worldview), she opposes them throughout her analysis to the preferred notions of “generosity,” “plentitude,” and “multiplicity” (with their polytheistic undertones). By providing this contrast, she embarks on a quest to eradicate the seeds of what she sees as collective violence embodied in the deity who would promote a relative frenzy of ownership for scarce resources (e.g., land, food, spouses) in favor of a deity who would ensure peace through an offer of generosity and an embracing of differences that resist becoming permanent and remain nomadic. In this scenario, the former is found in the god of monotheism; the latter, in the polytheistic impulses of the Near East that were quickly overshadowed by their powerful opponents.
Accordingly, she posits that whereas scarcity provokes a response focused on establishing greater definition in terms of political and sexual identity (thus giving shape to subsequent notions of what is to be considered “familial” or “natural”), plentitude resists such limited characterizations, eschewing the “preoccupations” of a narrative that sets people at odds with one another.Footnote 10 Like those critics of the canonical form who would argue for a return to a more egalitarian polytheistic worldview (as idealistic as it might appear at times), Schwartz contemplates a similar gesture in her condemnation of this monotheistic ideological identification. In the end, she reasons, scarcity thinking would seem to impose a need for transcendence that ultimately ends up creating a distant and inaccessible deity.Footnote 11 Latent in this critique is a profound call to a sort of immanent, polytheistic worldview, one that opposes the politically powerful transcendence of a monotheistic outlook on the world.
What remains central to Schwartz's critique of monotheism and is of heightened interest to this article is the illustrative position of the canonical form. Her depiction of the Hebrew canon's formation as a response to the impending crisis of a loss of national identity prioritizes the fixation of communal boundaries and the rigidity of a Jewish identity constructed on the seminal event of the Exile.Footnote 12 It was at this precise moment, in her view, that the fluid and evolving memories of the Jewish people were unjustly subjected to a process of canonization that effectively closed what should have otherwise remained open to the multiple views more prominently circulating within ancient Israel. For Schwartz, normative religious structures were much looser at this time in history, and the creation of a canonical scripture and tradition actually undermined the polyvalent Judaisms present at the time. The Hebrew canon thus served in a very literal sense as an ideological constraint imposed on otherwise often widely divergent narratives. In turn, this creation of a canon subsequently gave rise to the canonical form's resistance to “translatability,” perhaps the defining feature of its “monotheizing tendencies.”Footnote 13 Instead of many voices crossing many boundaries, people within such a canonical community were forced to remain within a shell that could be seen as either protective or isolating.
Employing the twin witnesses of the ancient prophet Jeremiah, with his insistence on “rewriting Scripture,” and contemporary psychological insights concerning an individual's inability to ever fully provide closure to their own personal narrative, Schwartz concludes her critique with a call to open the biblical canon to new stories beyond the canonical boundary, and thereby also to the truth that enriches and proliferates within the multiplicity of narratives possible.Footnote 14 Such is the only just way forward, she contends, and her conclusions have the potential to strike a deep chord with contemporary Western culture.
Despite the obvious popular appeal that Schwartz's claims hold, her account of the Western monotheistic canonical form is not without its counterclaims—or at least subtle nuances that push us in other directions of thought. Another somewhat similar voice can be found in the work of Mark S. Smith, who offers a critique that runs parallel to most of Schwartz's and yet starkly registers the opposite conclusion. Smith, in fact, provides a richer look into monotheism's encapsulation of earlier polytheistic beliefs. He diverges from Schwartz in his conclusions concerning the overall status and role of the canonical form within a given religious context.Footnote 15
Smith locates the three primary trends of monotheism's incorporation of polytheism as (1) a convergence, or the assimilation of all the other deities into one, (2) a differentiation, or denying the other gods an existence, and (3) a reinterpretation of the older polytheistic stories into monotheistic ones.Footnote 16 Each of these maneuvers could be classified as a tactic of rewriting previously existent canonical traditions in a bid to create a more stabilized identity under the threat of an imminent historical crisis, much as Schwartz had argued. Indeed, for the most part, Smith's critique parallels that of Schwartz, even going so far as to offer monotheism as an interpretive lens of reality that shaped Israel's worldview in a particular nationalistic (ideological) manner.Footnote 17
Smith departs from this general critique, however, through his deepening of the notion of a collective memory within the text. It is this feature, in his view, that serves to reflect God's revelation, “what God selected to be remembered and forgotten of God's relationship to Israel and the world,” thus turning any perceived ideological script into a divine directive.Footnote 18 This, it should be carefully noted, is at once an effort to acknowledge a canon's selective reading of history and a way to illustrate how the processes of canonicity cannot be so quickly dismissed as an inherently reactionary form of violence. Such a reading of the canonical form might be seen as a critique of those who would jettison the significance attached to any subsequent historical development of particular faith traditions and their relation to the canonical form. Smith's decisive rendering of the biblical canonical narrative as a divine choice likewise places him among those who would see the integrity of the canon maintained, though the way we think about it is altered.Footnote 19 In other words, in Smith's estimation there is indeed a violence performed by the canonical form (or, one might say, by God) if a canon is to be perceived as sacred revelation at all. It is a necessary violence that grants religious identity, akin to the marks of circumcision or tattooing made on the body. This is the price of religious and cultural signification—a reality that the canonical form directly signifies.
The sustained capacity for religious and cultural signification found in a canon forms the basis for what Smith, in another context, calls the “non-translatable core” of the biblical canon, or that which allowed the early Hebrew people to resist the colonial powers of empire.Footnote 20 By offering this reading and thereby furthering our understanding of how and why a canon might actually be utilized, Smith is able to illustrate a direct line of continuity between the biblical critique of empire and contemporary postcolonial critiques, at least insofar as both clearly draw from and yet resist the dominant cultural forms of a colonial power.Footnote 21 The opening of this argument toward the political implications of canonical forms, especially with regard to the violence said to proceed from them, is crucial to expressing Smith's overall concern toward those who would like to free the canon from its “non-translatable core,” something that Smith goes to great lengths to stress cannot be done without rendering the biblical canon bereft of its identifying (signifying) power. Canons, by this count, are not just about narrowing the multiplicity of narratives available within a given community; they are also about protecting a community's identity when faced with external threats concerning its dissolution.
What becomes uniquely discernible in Smith's account is the fundamentally intertwined nature of both cultural and religious canons and the political and historical contexts in which they are born. As I will contend, cultural and religious canons exert a social power aligned with a conception of politics as being essentially a polarized division: us versus them. As such, canons tend to reflect the core identifying features of a given political landscape. To transcend canonical, normative divisions would effectively be a claim to transcend politics as we know it. Such a configuration of the political and the canonical can also help explain the often insurmountable difficulty encountered when trying to transcend the particularities of a given political paradigm (its “nontranslatability” so to speak).
In Smith's view and in other accounts that I will mention, the biblical canon utilizes its essential trait of nontranslatability precisely as a powerful and necessary source of cultural signification so that communal identifications might develop as a form of “counter-resistance” to the types of violence imposed on a particular canonical community. Canonicity is therefore a move to posit “nontranslatability” as being (though at times obscurely) the cornerstone of a (pre)formed cultural-canonical identity, something that can never really be suspended between two different canons and that can be altered only through a “conversion” from one cultural-canonical signifier to another.
To summarize the point, I would suggest that the validity of these varied contentions on either side of the debate, despite their differences, rests on the reality of whether or not they correspond to a fuller understanding of the dimensions and consequences of the canonical form as a whole. That is, we must ask ourselves whether certain canons promote violence while others seek to lessen its effects. One might further inquire whether all canonical forms could be said to perform an act of violence that could otherwise have been avoided and replaced by a more diffuse, seemingly primordial (though perhaps vaguely stated) multiplicity devoid of any canonical form, or (here following Smith) whether this violence of the canonical form simply alters our perception of the text itself, creating the blatant, though perhaps necessary, entrance of an often terrifying God.
Resolving this impasse is not easy. As I will argue, both sides in some sense also fail to account for the desires of canonicity that exist over and beyond any particular manifestation of the canonical form (especially in a religious sense). That these critical appraisals of Judaism's monotheistic origins have so much in common in their overall analysis, diverging only in the manner in which they draw their conclusions from the material given, is partial evidence that there is no single answer to the problem of imposing canonical norms when one assesses the situation of the canonical form historically.
In order to provide a constructive account of canons, what is necessary is a more proper distinction of the tensions that arise within canons themselves, such as what I will examine later in this article. In this way, these particular tensions might begin to reveal how the presumption of regarding a canonical “monotheizing” text as an inherently violent text worth disregarding lacks a more rigorous account of the multiple forms of violence culturally present to us today also in canonical form and already indebted to the various and competing canons present within any given society. This repositioning of the argument might therefore provide an account of canons that could actually serve to justify the cultural position of canons in the first place. At the same time, it might also serve to demonstrate the need to distinguish between different canons, that is, to clarify the relationships already existent between differing canonical forms.
Rather than perceive this logic as a justification for colonialist domination or for one canon's reign over another, the imposition of a particular canon on other canons and canonically formed cultures could actually present an interesting though complex vantage point from which to see anew the problem of the canonical form and its relation to violence. For example, we might begin by looking into the myriad forms of resistance to particular canonical cultures that arise within any given society, and indeed within the same canonical form (e.g., typical “heretical” movements). As Smith has already indicated, postcolonial theory, as only one example of this type of resistance, becomes a genuinely visible vantage point within a canonical culture—an embedded position from which to critique the canonical form.
It is no surprise moreover that postcolonial theory in particular has often allied itself with a deconstructionist philosophical framework in an attempt to dismantle the canonical forms of power that have exerted control over their cultures. Such theories inquire whether there is a dynamic at work in the desire for canonicity that functions as an “imperialist assimilation of the Other” for which we must now give an account.Footnote 22 To invoke a postcolonialist critique in such a fashion is not a rhetorical or coincidental strategy, as Smith has already demonstrated. Rather, it is one that highlights “marginal” knowledges that appear to be “noncanonical” and that are other than the ethnocentrism of any given canon (akin to the production of “Western knowledge”) because they interpret already-existing canons differently, with an ear to the violences with which they are complicit or to which they are opposed.Footnote 23
Hence, following Smith's appropriation of postcolonial theory, we could state that the canonical form does in effect promote a certain violence of introducing a fundamental division enacted by a monotheistic worldview, though not one that can simply be replaced or discarded. To see the validity of the canonical form in this way, we must first explore a fuller exposition of the “violence” introduced through canons, which in many ways has served only to arouse suspicion regarding the overt imposition of particular canons on others.Footnote 24 As canons are a necessary part of all cultures, however, they are not so easily either dismissed or deconstructed.
As will become clear in the analysis of the work of both Jan Assmann and René Girard that follows, by focusing on the differences within the canonical form itself we will perhaps find a way through this apparent impasse, as well as a more lucid account that might serve to highlight the extreme political relevance of canons and of the Judeo-Christian Scriptures in particular.
2. Jan Assmann on the Canon
The initial consensus reaction to Sigmund Freud's later work Moses and Monotheism was that it was a speculative exposition of an almost absurd claim, that Moses was in fact an Egyptian and that it was a repressed version of Egyptian monotheism that he revived and propagated in what was to become the Judaic form of faith.Footnote 25 This initial scholarly reaction, however, subsided with time and gave way to a growing interest in Freud's work on the part of philosophers, critical theorists, and psychoanalytic schools of thought that not only embraced his work on Moses but saw it as a exemplary forerunner of contemporary cultural studies.Footnote 26 One of the most significant, and recent, contributions to this large body of work has come from the Egyptologist Jan Assmann, whose work on Freud, Moses, and any alleged Egyptian ties has actually led him to reconsider the role that the canonical form plays in formulating a cultural-religious worldview—that is, its role in creating historical representations and repressing desire (its latency). Assmann, for his part, has indeed constructed a more developed and more encompassing speculative system of his own, one that expands beyond Freud's project in order to depict specifically the role of canons in introducing a particular cultural and ideological violence of division within a given culture.
Assmann's redefinition of the Freudian project owes an obvious direct debt to Freud's work on Moses, although he also takes a substantially nuanced position toward it. According to Assmann, the revealing of the centrality of the canonical form to Western religious and political identity has been a project of the “unthought,” which need not arise from beneath the surface of the text, as Freud himself sought to indicate through his depiction of the “unconscious” of a text. This is the case for Assmann because texts dealing with historical representations, exemplified but not limited to the canonical form, actually reveal their truth on the surface:
What Freud unearths and dramatizes as a revelation is not the historical truth, but merely some theoretical constructs that turn out to be superfluous. The truth can be found in the texts themselves. They speak of memory, remembrance, forgetting, and the repressed, of trauma and guilt. In order to uncover this network of meanings we have no need to practice the hermeneutics of distrust; nor need we read these texts against the grain. We need only listen to them attentively.Footnote 27
In contrast to Freud, Assmann undertakes what he terms a “mnemohistory,” a study of the past not as it historically occurred but as it is remembered by the texts themselves. The task of such a study is to listen to the text in such a way as to unveil any ideological script that unfolds in the narrative, not to dig beneath it for one presumed to be repressed. This is actually a process, he states, that intends on getting behind the “mythical elements” embedded within traditions themselves. Any history passed through a tradition is already a myth, while still maintaining a sense of historicity once it is “remembered, narrated, and used.”Footnote 28 And in return, this discourse consisting of myth, once materialized as tradition, reproduces itself through its subjects.Footnote 29 As we will see, Assmann reads Freud in this manner precisely in order to dislodge what he sees as the ideological script of monotheism presented in its canonical Judaic form, although in the end he might not be as free of canonical forms as his work seems to suggest.
For example, Assmann contends that the book of Deuteronomy contains theories of individual, collective, and cultural memory. It confronts the Jewish people with the presence of a “counterfactual” memory and truly issues an imperative: they are called to remember a “framework” outside their present reality (e.g., a nomadic life in the midst of the Promised Land, or hunger in the midst of abundance). This task is given to the people of Israel to keep “present to the mind a yesterday that conflicts with every tomorrow.”Footnote 30 The presence of counterfactual memory not only arises from the consolidation of forty years of memory as a mnemonic technique but is closely bound to the monotheistic conception of revelation, especially since both manifest characteristics of an “extraterritorial” nature. That is, situating the divine granting of the Law in the wilderness becomes symbolic of nomadic wandering—an “extraterritorial” mandate that situates the Law as separate from any specific locality. As Assmann puts it, “This means that the laws that they are to remember and abide by are not the laws of the land, but the extraterritorial laws from Mount Sinai.”Footnote 31 This (re)defining of revelation and its relation to the canonical form is intended to expand Freud's project of perceiving writing as a nomadic exercise always displacing itself in order to reveal the “fuller” consequences of producing a written, sacred canon.Footnote 32
In general, this reading of Freud allows Assmann to complete a reformulation of the canon itself—to see the desire for canonicity as a form of “counter-religion” that bears a constantly displaced revelation.Footnote 33 “Counter-religions,” as the name implies, seek to counter already existing religious trends by positing a “counter-history” of their own, one always set in motion by and thereby inherently connected to an established canonical text. These counter-histories aim to distort the self-image, identity, and memory of their adversary, offering their own “official” version of these constituent features through the instantiation of the canonical form.Footnote 34 For Assmann, history in any form, including the canonical, becomes mythical again once it is “remembered, narrated, and used,” thus providing a baseline ideological usage for itself, though not actually serving to negate the historicity of its account.Footnote 35 Even an “imagined community” based on a canonical foundation (to appropriate Benedict Anderson's celebrated phrase) can accurately represent history, though it functions politically in a polarized and polarizing ideological manner.Footnote 36 Again, all normative canonical forms are inherently intertwined with the political landscape in which they originate.
Assmann, through recognizing the pivotal role that an Egyptian monotheism played in forming the Israelite religion, establishes a structural parallel between two poles: revelation, which is itself bound by the processes of the canonical (e.g., characterized by remembering, progression, and a monotheistic or “Mosaic distinction” between true and false); and translation, which remained more ancient and bound to an oral culture (e.g., characterized by forgetting, regression, and a polytheistic worldview).Footnote 37 As this tension outlines, Assmann links revelation and canonization as fundamentally intertwined projects, since religions based on a written revelation (and not simply the monotheistic ones) “are all founded on a corpus of canonical writings and thus on a highly authoritative codification of memory. To belong to such a religion calls for this codified memory to be accepted and taken to heart. Evidently, the importance of the codification and canonization of memory is linked to the structure of the revelation. All revealed knowledge is by definition knowledge of something outside the world.”Footnote 38
In this manner, faith becomes equated with memory, and, thanks to Freud, an “inner spiritual guide” viewed as a progression from an antiquated desire for natural evidence, which was once sought so heartily to justify religious belief. For Assmann, the decisive point remains the internal split in the subject brought about by monotheism's claims to divide reality into true and false, a split that renders the human heart itself subject to the dual traumas of desiring to be at home in the world (its pagan element), and of being told to reject and forget the false idols of paganism (its monotheistic element).Footnote 39 It is also a division of the world brought about by the canonical form itself and is as such instrumental to certain political and ideological scripts.
At the end of the discussion of Freud's role within cultural canonical analysis, then, we are left with a decentering of the trauma of monotheism, locating it not in the “Oedipal deep structure of the human psyche, but in the Mosaic distinction between true and false” that the canonical introduces into culture. It could be enacted only perpetually because it is grounded as revelation and in a very literal sense runs parallel to the sovereign's legitimation of power through recourse to a divine (transcendent) mandate.Footnote 40 The binary divisions introduced by the “Mosaic distinction,” in Assmann's view, begin to perform what will become a “monotheizing” tendency of the canonical form. As we have seen already in the cases of Schwartz and Smith, the canonical work introduces a fundamental division into culture, one that in effect could be said to generate a system of cultural significations and to create thereby the apparently “noncanonical” or marginalized elements on its fringes.
Though all of this attests to the canonical form's ability to generate cultural norms, our focus on the “return of the repressed” or a resurgence of the marginalized within (at times even seemingly against) canonically instituted divisions can help us to discern the cultural role of canonicity on a whole new level (as with its postcolonial reading by Smith). The canonical form, as it were, is often said to “forget” the heretical and/or apocryphal texts only to face their reemergence later, often during periods of religious renewal—an acknowledgment that is Assmann's strongest claim concerning polytheism's relation to monotheism.Footnote 41 Functioning as signifier for an entire cultural-symbolic system, the canonical form produces a context that could be said to perform some degree of violence on the marginalized elements otherwise excluded from representation.
This line of argumentation has been at the heart of several criticisms concerning Assmann's work as a whole, which he addresses in his more recent work Of God and Gods.Footnote 42 Noteworthy in this regard is the criticism offered by Joseph Cardinal Ratzinger (Pope Benedict XVI) of Assmann's alleged linkage between monotheism and violence, which moved Ratzinger to remind those in the Catholic tradition of Christ's proclamation of peace, as well as to point out how other, noncanonical religions have brought various violences into the world as well.Footnote 43
Responding to critics such as Smith and Ratzinger, who have seen his work as advocating something of a return to polytheism through the erasure of the true/false dichotomy, Assmann has nuanced his position by referring to the “latent monotheism within polytheism” as well as by offering a further distinction (beyond the simplified “Mosaic” one he offered earlier) between an intrasystemic violence (which is translatable between cultures, and perhaps best exemplified by acts such as child sacrifice) and extrasystemic violence (which is nontranslatable, hence only serving as part of one's conversionary experience). Within this grid of violences, Assmann is able to critique monotheism's basic contention that it is opposed to intrasystemic violence while yet simultaneously giving rise to extrasystemic violence through its acts of (often forced) conversion or destruction.Footnote 44
By later giving nuance to his position in response to his critics, Assmann has actually come to in part defend a monotheistic worldview by illustrating its indebtedness to a particular historical conceptualization of justice. In his view, the real contrast is that between an implicit theology (the cosmogony of a polytheistic worldview) and an explicit theology (the created order of the monotheistic one).Footnote 45 Monotheism, from this perspective, becomes the inventor of “religion” as a concept as well as an embodied political practice, bringing a developed concept of justice from outside the traditional realm of (mythical-violent) religion into its inner self-definition. Again, canonical forms, religion, and politics are inextricably linked together as the central identifiers of “culture,” an originally Western conceptualization that has spread more widely since its “monotheistic” origins. The traffic among these three conceptual realms is therefore fluid. In this fashion, the monotheistic worldview is not only able to stand up as a critic of existing political structures but is also capable of narrating a history based on a divine notion of justice.Footnote 46
In Assmann's view, Judaism was able to prevent itself from becoming indebted to a system of violence by refusing to universalize its historical claims, leaving them open to the processes of an eschatology never foreclosed within history and thereby also maintaining justice as an always open horizon against which all (“righteous”) religious acts are formed.Footnote 47 By this route of recirculation around his most analyzed concepts, Assmann comes very close to espousing a similar claim made in the last century by Walter Benjamin concerning the relation of the messianic to a divine and bloodless violence. By such means, Assmann is also able to denounce any religion associated with manifest violent forms and to declare that the “power of religion rests on nonviolence.”Footnote 48 The “weak form of truth” espoused here is a less violent or even nonviolent appeal to be sure, one coupled with its basic position as a counterforce to political power. This can be found at the origins of all monotheistic, canonical claims, according to Assmann, though the history of their reception has often proved anything but nonviolent.
It is striking, however, that Assmann's clarifications have themselves gravitated toward a reading of the nonviolence at the center of the biblical canonical framework. This brings his position into sharp relief against the backdrop of opinions already formed concerning his work. One of the large conceptual problems here, of course, is that there is a significant difference between nonviolence and less violence. As Smith claims, canons are inherently violent, and this would be a stark challenge to Assmann's proposal of a nonviolent core to the Western monotheistic canon—if such a thing could even be said to exist.
In order to sift further through such complex problems, and as an extension of where Assmann's arguments may ultimately lead, I now turn to the work of the French literary theorist René Girard in order to clarify the distinctions of the canonical form in relation to violence and to analyze how the monotheistic canon might be said to reject or work beyond some of the extrasystemic violence still attached to its name.
3. René Girard on Violence in Different Canonical Forms
An account of the canonical form can be deepened in two ways. On the one hand, one can pursue the foundations of the canonical form itself (its canonicity), which, in turn, may be seen to ground necessary cultural distinctions and thus allow us to see how a necessary violence could be possible as a sign of cultural identity, albeit one that remains relatively “bloodless.” On the other hand, one can (as Assmann does) distinguish the types of canonical violences, opening our horizon of understanding toward the processes of canonicity themselves and thereby producing evidence of the differences between canons. Hence there are canons that reveal violence and those that conceal it. By making these distinctions, we are developing a modified version of Freud's initial textual hermeneutic, which was intended to uncover what underlies canonical or normative texts, even if these “texts” are an individual's personal narrative. This textual hermeneutic has been extended furthest not only in the work of Assmann, but also through the work of Girard.
In many ways, Girard's reading of cultural and religious texts is a reapplication of Freud's most basic insights, though it also shares in some of Assmann's contentions that the “truth” of the text can be read on its “surface.”Footnote 49 Consequently, Girard develops a fuller and deepened hermeneutic that combines fundamental insights from both Freud and Assmann: seeking what is repressed by reading what is already on the surface of the canonical text. This is key to understanding the actual forces and violences latent within the processes of canonicity.
By addressing the distinction between texts that reveal violence and texts that conceal it, I wish to move beyond the overly simple appellations and condemnations of a general violence that is said to proceed from “monotheizing” canonical texts. Such designations, as we have seen in Schwartz, often fail to produce an adequate account of the cultural forces necessary to signify a social reality. They normally make a vague reference to a more primordial state of existence (e.g., polytheistic, multiple) and fail to explain how any “primordial state” might be realized among canonical cultures as they are defined today. They also fail to indicate how we are to realize such noncanonical configurations politically. In this sense, there needs to be more regard for discerning how a canonical-cultural index could actually be dismantled, discontinued, or converted, if such a thing were desirable or even possible to do within a given cultural context.
What becomes apparent is the need to be more specific in defining the forms of violence performed by the “monotheizing” canonical work, and to inspect the nature of the divisions it serves to create, deconstructing them when necessary in order to let justice proliferate. Accordingly, the contrast between the version of monotheism inherent in the canonical form and another version of a cultural-canonical foundation that might arise in its place hinges on how the distinction between the concealing of violence (as one form of the canonical) and the revealing of violence (as another form of the canonical) becomes more pronounced.
For Girard, as we will see, the contrast illuminates an unconscious process of concealing the violence that gives rise to a particular civilization itself and that divides the canonical form into differing factions: those that testify against a particular violence and those that promote it, while both signify differing cultural-canonical distinctions between what is true or false.
Over the last few decades Girard's work has acquired something of a legendary status among certain scholars, especially those working within biblical or literary fields. Its ability to detail the intimate dynamics of desire and to overlay such descriptions onto a rich and vast literary heritage has attracted a great many admirers, though it has also been criticized for its sweeping claims. In many ways, it would not be going too far to compare Girard's “grand theory” to the Freudian corpus that preceded it.
Essentially, Girard's theory of the scapegoat—the seminal figure at the base of all societal formations—runs along these basic coordinates: the mimetic desiring of a given historical community must limit itself in order to function. As can be imagined, desires that are produced merely through the imitation of another person's desires (e.g., as can often be found in a “love triangle” or in advertising) over time begin to run amok and risk the destruction of the community (or the “institution,” such as the family, a sport's team, or a particular organization). Rather than confront its own limitations directly, however, the community (often portrayed in literature as a “mob” or “crowd”) simply and often ritualistically selects a scapegoat, either arbitrarily or on account of the future scapegoat's crossing of established cultural boundaries. Such a figure, once designated, will then have to be “sacrificed”—either ritualistically killed or exiled from the community—in order for the community to continue its normal state of affairs. In sum, the desire to deal with a crisis, itself a result of mimetic rivalry, generates a scapegoat who is dispatched and excluded from the community so that the community might regain its sense of peace. In reality, however, such sacrifices are only a temporary alleviation; the core of mimetic desiring itself has not been directly addressed, and thus this cycle must repeat itself again and again.Footnote 50
In a reading that mimics Freud's essential insight concerning Moses' death, the memory of this violent event—so central to the community from which the myth originates and on which the community itself is founded—is repressed in the mythical narrative and expunged from historical record, leaving only traces of its “truth” hidden behind the thin veil of a cyclical scapegoating process. The order now established within a society becomes mythically based on this falsified narrative, and peace becomes a temporary constraint on mob violence—a matter of an impermanent alleviation, not an actual solution.Footnote 51
Girard, for his part, chooses to focus on the manner in which the mythical text hides the violence at the origins of society, in strong contrast to how biblical texts reveal the mechanisms of scapegoating and the accompanying logics of exclusion as a false means of achieving communal solidarity. By carefully unpacking literary-historical (and many mythological) texts alongside the canonical biblical ones, Girard aims for a project of demythologization. Yet this project also ends up restoring legitimacy to biblical texts through an illustration of their power to reveal the mechanisms of a mimetic desire that proves to be a means to the end of the cycle of mimetic violence. This power of the text, then, serves as a confirmation and legitimization of the canonical work in the Judeo-Christian tradition, which eventually takes the side of the victim of mimetic violence (the excluded or sacrificed figure) while still maintaining the need for a canonical form. This alignment tends to redefine the relation of the canonical form in sociocultural terms as opposed to the mythological canon, which glorifies and justifies the violent founding acts of a society's order.
As one example of this mechanism, we might cite Girard's analysis of the contrast between two founding myths of society. First, there is the Roman legend of Romulus and Remus, brothers who clash over the boundaries of the ancient city, with Romulus eventually killing Remus. In this particular myth, no judgment is passed by the narrative itself on Romulus's actions; he simply becomes the founder of Rome. Next, there is the biblical story of Cain and Abel, in which Cain kills his brother Abel out of jealousy at God's having bestowed his favor upon Abel. This story differs from the typical myth, in Girard's view, in that there is a negative judgment passed on Cain as God sides with Abel's innocence. According to the biblical text, even though Cain goes on to found civilization, his actions are viewed as contrary to the canonical viewpoint—in absolute contrast to the Roman legend.Footnote 52
Like Freud, Girard reads what would generally be considered as both “canonical” and “noncanonical” texts, especially as it is the varied and often noncanonical texts that bear direct witness to the unconscious dimensions of violence inherent in the processes of mimetic desiring.Footnote 53 Though Girard himself does not utilize this distinction as such between texts, it is important to note that his chosen texts, whether biblical or mythological, could be perceived as cultural-foundational, and, in that sense, always “canonical” in the culturally specific sense in which this article uses the term. Indeed, his entire theory rests on the manner in which ancient texts are said to be canonical, that is, constitutive of culture, and hence forming communal-ideological positions based on the outcome of a particular mimetic rivalry.
While any direct reflection on canonical form seems absent from Girard's work, in fact canonical form becomes the necessary link in establishing an alternative process of historical memory apart from mythology. In a sense, any community that adopts a textually based ritualistic prohibition against mimetic violence and seeks to end the cyclical processes of violence instituted through scapegoating is indeed paying homage to certain processes of canonicity: those processes that side with the excluded (and not merely marginalized) victim, as opposed to the mythological forms of canonicity that endorse sacrificial violence. This is a careful distinction that we must make with regard to Schwartz's critique, since Girard functions as the critic of her position insofar as he sees the Bible as fundamentally different from myth in its obsessive preservation of repressed narratives.Footnote 54
At this point, Girard's distinction between canons becomes a central addition to our notion of canonicity, as it contains the potential for either an obsessive recording of a particular, repressed history (viewing the canonical as an attempt to do justice to the memory of an excluded people) or an obstruction of the violent truth behind the narrative (viewing the canonical as a legitimization of a particular dominant and exclusory ideology). At its core, then, the canonical form either exposes or conceals the violence at the center of human desiring. Either way, though, it is a process essential to social collective formations as we witness them in our world today.
Canonicity is thereby further defined through these insights as itself a mimetic structure that responds to a crisis and then follows either a “truthful” relating of the actual processes of mimetic desiring, or a “falsified” relating that seeks to cover over its literal truth. The former definition, for its part, would seem to open us toward the foundation of an ethics, whereas the latter would open directly onto the field of ideology.
The formulation of canonicity is in fact the juxtaposition of an ethically less (but not non-) violent canon, wherein the powerless are allowed representation and the potential for justice to be done is increased, and an ideological mythical canon, wherein the powerless are scapegoated (not just marginalized) and perpetually at risk of being removed from society in general. The latter is a position that inherently opens the door to extrasystemic violences, as Assmann had earlier defined them. This emphasis elevates the principle of justice (seeking after the lesser violence) as a central hermeneutical key to reading canons and to mediating any conflict of methodologies when dialoguing over a canonical text. This also grants a space for representation not only of the excluded victim of an exclusive society, but also of the marginalized person within a particular nonexclusive community, bringing their right to assert subjectivity within a public forum created by the “truth-telling” canonical work. This responds to those who criticize Girard for being too simplistic or idealistic with regard to the distinctions drawn between different societies. It is also, I would add, one productive way to enact a “democracy of words” in the face of ongoing ethical violence.Footnote 55
4. Conclusions: Redefining the Canonical
The canonical form, in this context, could thus be said to function as a dominator over its oppressed elements, continuously seeking their exclusion from representation and considering them “unthinkable” within its “matrix of intelligibility.” But the canonical could also be said to function as engaged with its marginalized elements, making them “thinkable” when necessary, even central at times to the construction of any future cultural identity.
In this latter sense we can perceive the canon as capable of being aligned with a history of particular repressions, as potentially also bearing witness to them, and as performing a certain justice to their memory when situations or events deem that it be so. Seeing this act of justice within a given canonical community, tradition, or text is essential if we are to move beyond the ideological suppression of marginal persons or histories. The very presence of a cry for justice within certain canons can function as a permanent fissure in any claims to totality or dominance that might otherwise arise. Rather than doing away with canonical forms and their binary division of reality, what such a reading of canonical forms offers us is a “division of division” itself, one starkly reminiscent of the Pauline attempt to turn the division of Jew and Gentile into one involving another level of flesh and spirit (Romans 8).
Drawing distinctions between the varying forms of violence present in our world thus assists us in forming a more complete picture of how different cultural formations arise based on different notions of the canonical form generated, in turn, by different processes of canonicity. What emerges from this analysis is a powerful critique of social norms, differentiating between those that derive from a truthful exposure of violence (siding with the excluded or repressed elements) and those that derive from a falsified justification of violence (siding with the exclusive or dominant elements). The potential for utilizing this schema in discerning cultural conflicts is perhaps as vast as the implications for evaluating canonically derived ethical paradigms.
In the formation of (ethical) subjects, produced by a given canonical form and therefore bound to certain historical processes of canonicity, the grounds for establishing the canonical form as a site of power are revealed most fully. It might seem paradoxical to suggest that the canonical form has the potential to preserve what appears as “noncanonical” (the echo of the marginalized), but that is the ethical import that follows from this analysis.
The stark contrasts of canonical presences within varying cultures, which each of these authors helps to illuminate, encourages us to reconsider in what ways those who are excluded or marginalized might benefit from a greater understanding of canons and their constitutive power. The force of this redefinition of canons discloses a profound connection between canonical texts and the collective, cultural memories of repressed peoples who engage with such texts. The “revolutionary” tactic of assimilating canon to memory, a tactic that allows repressed memories and histories to be recognized as events that bring their own understanding before the canonical norm, must be seized on and continuously repeated.Footnote 56 The power of such negotiation between these two poles of narration is not only a service to the representation of those whose memories would otherwise quickly be forgotten in history, but also a model for reinterpreting the canonical texts themselves, opening them still further to new interpretations. This is also a task that theology must learn to take seriously, especially when performing its own acts of self-reflection.
Consequently, an ethical dimension is revealed within the nature of the canonical form and the preservation of memory, a dimension that elicits our theological response as communities of a sacred canon.Footnote 57 The canonical form must not be harnessed to justify dominant oppressive cultures, unjust hierarchical forms, or other totalitarian powers, though it undoubtedly can be utilized to do so. Rather, it must be seen as a guarantor of the voices of the marginalized throughout history, if it is to express itself as a site of truth, expose the falsity of a violence-oriented society, or become a site of revelation.
In a seemingly paradoxical inversion, the truthful canonical form actually has the potential to preserve the marginalized figure at its core through its fidelity to a sense of messianic justice that is always increasingly on the rise and always to-come. It opens itself to the voices of the marginalized within who do not threaten to undo the canon so much as offer a possibility of less violence being done in the canon's signification of cultural subjects. The marginalized thereby serve as a constant disruption of any attempt to totalize canonical representations, a disruption that is starkly more or less welcomed by differing cultural viewpoints.
This is not to suggest, of course, that every apparent noncanonical representation is aligned in near-perfect symmetry with a marginalized element, but only to suggest that a possibility lies open already within a given, particular canonical form. Eric L. Santner points out, in a critique of Assmann's position, that his “Mosaic distinction” is correct in a certain sense and yet misses the larger point: the trauma induced by this fundamental cultural division with which we identify is what enables us to relate to the trauma of the other and thereby greet them as our neighbors.Footnote 58 This would undo canonical forms from within and render their divisions less divisive—a “division of division” itself.
Moreover, this paradoxical act of unveiling the unconscious of a text at the level of its conscious readability constitutes a self-reflexive movement wherein the canonical form stands “exposed” as it were, not as a prelude to its eventual decanonization, but as a gesture of self-reflexive understanding formed in relation to the desire for canonicity itself. Those who are subjects of the text and invested in the life of canons and their communities, who wish to stand in good faith with the canonical form itself, must begin to (re)read their own identities in light of the dynamisms generated not only between canonical forms and perceived noncanonical ones, but in the canonical form itself, a collection of multiple, dynamic desires therein united. Subjects of the text must likewise play host to a certain unveiling of their unconscious desires for (re)producing a text and for writing themselves into its narrative time and again—a decisive and consequential reworking of the roots of those theological accounts of confession normative to many a religious tradition. This dynamic process of interaction with the canonical form can thus evolve over time as a basic foundation for ethical paradigms, in order that a more proper interpretation of a particular canonical text might itself further evolve over time.
Beyond simply being an apologetic account of sacred scripture, the study of canonicity and its relation to the canonical form has manifold and varied theological implications, since in a foundational sense these processes can be said to generate culture and politics themselves. Perhaps most significant are the implications for what a self-reflexive study of theology as a truth-telling, violence-exposing discipline might be.