Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-grxwn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-07T03:42:51.620Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Redeployed functions versus spreading activation: A potential confound

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 October 2010

Colin Klein
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Illinois at Chicago, Chicago, IL 60607. cvklein@uic.eduhttp://tigger.uic.edu/~cvklein/links.html

Abstract

Anderson's meta-analysis of fMRI data is subject to a potential confound. Areas identified as active may make no functional contribution to the task being studied, or may indicate regions involved in the coordination of functional networks rather than information processing per se. I suggest a way in which fMRI adaptation studies might provide a useful test between these alternatives.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2010

That there is a many-to-one mapping between cognitive functions and brain areas should now be beyond dispute. The tricky part is figuring out what to say about it. Anderson's massive redeployment hypothesis (MRH) is a plausible position in the debate. Good engineers often find new uses for old tricks; we should expect nature to be no less clever.

A crucial piece of evidence for the MRH is Anderson's impressive meta-analyses of fMRI experiments (Anderson Reference Anderson2007b; Reference Anderson2007c). These show that phylogenetically older areas tend to be more active, across a variety of tasks, than phylogenetically newer ones. Crucially, Anderson assumes that the areas identified as active make a functional contribution to the experimental tasks being studied. That is often assumed in fMRI experiments, and so may seem unproblematic. This assumption is subject to a potential confound, however, and one that becomes especially troublesome when doing large-scale meta-analyses.

The BOLD response on which fMRI depends is a measure of physiological change. Which physiological change fMRI tracks is a matter of considerable debate. There is increasing evidence that the BOLD response better tracks regional increases in synaptic activity, rather than increased output of action potentials (Logothetis et al. Reference Logothetis, Pauls, Augath, Trinath and Oeltermann2001; Nair Reference Nair2005, sect. 2.2 reviews; Viswanathan & Freeman Reference Viswanathan and Freeman2007). Crucially, this means that observed BOLD activity may represent a mix of both excitatory and inhibitory inputs. A region which receives subthreshold excitatory input, or one which is both excited and inhibited enough to suppress further activation, may nevertheless show a measurable – even strong – BOLD response (Logothetis Reference Logothetis2008). However, these “active” regions would make no functional contribution to the experimental task.

Hence the potential confound. The fact that phylogenetically older areas are more often active may be explained by redeployment. It may also be explained by assuming that older areas simply receive more input than do newer ones. This potential confound may be manageable in individual fMRI experiments. Meta-analyses increase statistical power, however, making even small effects more likely to be noticed. Further, meta-analyses necessarily lack the fine-grained detail that might normally allow these functional by-products to be explained away.

This is not a merely academic worry. To give one example: Mahon and Caramazza (Reference Mahon and Caramazza2008) recently reviewed the fMRI evidence for the sensorimotor account of conceptual grounding (including many of the studies reviewed by Anderson in sect. 4). They conclude that the evidence is consistent with a view on which the semantic analysis of a sentence activates motor areas as an inevitable consequence of spreading activation within a complex neural system. Hence, although the motor system may often be activated during semantic analysis tasks, this activation need not represent a functional contribution to semantic analysis itself. It would instead be the natural consequence of a system in which the typical consumers of representations were primed for action, but inhibited (or simply under-excited) if their further, functionally specific, contribution was unnecessary. Note that a reliance on subtraction-based imaging does not obviate this problem: distinct semantic terms may well prime distinct motor regions.

Spreading activation and massive redeployment are not mutually exclusive hypotheses. Indeed, it seems to me that the redeployment model should accept some version of the former. If the brain does consist of pluripotent regions that flexibly combine into functional networks, problems of coordination – and especially the necessity of inhibiting preponent but contextually inappropriate dispositions – become paramount. Further, phylogenetically newer areas evolved in the context of organisms which already had well-functioning brains. We should expect newer areas to project heavily to older areas, both because the information they provide might be relevant to these older adaptive repertoires and because those older functions will need to be coordinated in light of newer capacities.

The crucial question, then, is how we might get experimental evidence that favors redeployment over the alternatives. Anderson suggests several plausible possibilities for testing his hypothesis. I suggest a further possibility: the use of fMRI adaptation. This technique exploits the fact that recently active neurons tend to show a decreased response to further stimulation; a decreased BOLD response across experimental conditions thus provides evidence that a region is making the same contribution to both tasks. Adaptation would allow one to distinguish areas which are truly redeployed from those which have simply parcellated into functionally specific areas that are smaller than the resolution of fMRI (an open evolutionary possibility; Streidter 2005, Ch. 7 reviews). Further, adaptation would allow us to distinguish areas that are truly reused from areas that are involved in the coordination of complex networks.

Crinion et al. (Reference Crinion, Turner, Grogan, Hanakawa, Noppeney, Devlin, Aso, Urayama, Fukuyama, Stockton, Usui, Green and Price2006) used this technique to distinguish the contribution of various cortical and subcortical areas in language processing. Proficient bilingual speakers showed both within- and cross-language priming in the left anterior temporal lobe, suggesting a shared substrate for semantic information (and thus supporting a form of reuse). Activation in the left caudate, in contrast, did not show a priming effect. This supports a hypothesized role for the caudate in language control: Plausibly, the caudate helps inhibit contextually inappropriate responses, a real problem when distinct languages partially share the same substrate. fMRI adaptation might thus allow us to disentangle the contribution of frequently activated areas in a variety of tasks, and so provide a further test of Anderson's intriguing hypothesis.

References

Anderson, M. L. (2007b) Massive redeployment, exaptation, and the functional integration of cognitive operations. Synthese 159(3):329–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, M. L. (2007c) The massive redeployment hypothesis and the functional topography of the brain. Philosophical Psychology 21(2):143–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crinion, J., Turner, R., Grogan, A., Hanakawa, T., Noppeney, U., Devlin, J. T., Aso, T., Urayama, A., Fukuyama, H., Stockton, K., Usui, K., Green, D. W. & Price, C. J. (2006) Language control in the bilingual brain. Science 312(5779):1537.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Logothetis, N. K. (2008) What we can do and what we cannot do with fMRI. Nature 453:869–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Logothetis, N. K., Pauls, J., Augath, M., Trinath, T. & Oeltermann, A. (2001) Neurophysiological investigation of the basis of the fMRI signal. Nature 412(6843):150–57.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mahon, B. Z. & Caramazza, A. (2008) A critical look at the embodied cognition hypothesis and a new proposal for grounding conceptual content. Journal of Physiology-Paris 102(1–3):5970.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nair, D. G. (2005) About being BOLD. Brain Research Reviews 50:229–43.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Striedter, G. F. (2005) Principles of brain evolution. Sinauer.Google Scholar
Viswanathan, A. & Freeman, R. D. (2007) Neurometabolic coupling in cerebral cortex reflects synaptic more than spiking activity. Nature Neuroscience 10(10):1308–12.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed