Conciliation, Counterterrorism, and Patterns of Terrorist Violence
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 15 February 2005
Abstract
What causes the increase in terrorism that reportedly often follows government concessions? Given this pattern, why do governments ever conciliate terrorists? I propose a model in which terrorist organizations become more militant following concessions because only moderate terrorists accept them, leaving extremists in control. Governments nonetheless are willing to make concessions because their counterterror capabilities improve because of the collusion of former terrorists. Former terrorists undertake this collusion to insure the credibility of government promises. The model also yields hypotheses regarding the level of government investment in counterterror, when moderates accept concessions, the terms of negotiated settlements, the duration of terrorist conflicts, incentives for moderate terrorists to radicalize their followers, and incentives for governments to encourage extremist challenges to moderate terrorist leaders. The model is illustrated with an application to the Israeli/Palestinian conflict.Professor Ehud Sprinzak, who died an untimely death on November 8, 2002, first introduced me to the study of terrorism. He is greatly missed. I received valuable comments from Scott Ashworth, Bob Bates, Mia Bloom, Bruce Bueno de Mesquita, Charles Cohen, Eric Dickson, Amanda Friedenberg, Orit Kedar, David Lake, Macartan Humphreys, Matthew Price, Todd Sandler, Ken Shepsle, David Andrew Singer, Alastair Smith, and Matthew Stephenson.
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- Copyright
- © 2005 The IO Foundation and Cambridge University Press
One of the most puzzling facts reported by scholars of terrorism is that the level of terrorist violence often increases following government concessions.1
For discussions of increases in violence following concessions, see Hewitt 1984; and Wilkinson 1999. Further note that, although I will not engage in a lengthy definitional discussion in this article, it is important that I am describing domestic-level terror that happens more or less within the target country, as opposed to transnational or international terrorism. For thorough treatments of definitional issues in terrorism studies, see Crenshaw 1995; Gibbs 1989; Hoffman 1998; and Laqueur 1977.
See Silke 1999; and The Irish Times, 12 March 2001, 7.
In this article, I present a formal model of the interactions between terrorist organizations and governments that accounts for both of these puzzles. Importantly, I do not treat terror groups as unitary actors. Rather, consistent with the actual structure of most terror organizations, I assume they are composed of ideologically heterogeneous cells, factions, and individuals.5
See Chai 1993; and Crenshaw 1981.
Two factors drive the results. First, militancy increases following concessions because it is the moderate terrorist factions that accept concessions, leaving the extremist factions in control. Second, as has been noted by others, governments face a commitment problem when offering concessions to armed insurgents.6
See Crenshaw 2000; Fearon 1998; and Walter 1997.
This commitment problem has two implications. First, it may be difficult for a government to end a conflict by offering concessions to all terrorist factions. This is because such concessions are not credible in the absence of ongoing violence. Second, it provides an endogenous account of why governments are willing to make concessions despite the increased militancy they engender. The benefits of counterterror aid from former terrorists may outweigh the costs of heightened militancy.
Indeed, there are empirical cases in which governments, with the help of former terrorists, have succeeded in thwarting the efforts of residual extremists. Such cases include the destruction of the Québec separatist Front de Libération du Québec (FLQ) in the 1980s,7
the combined British and Hagannah efforts to prevent terrorism by Zionist organizations such as the Irgun and Lohamei Herut Yisrael (LEHI) in the 1940s in British-Mandate Palestine,8 the Italian use of former-terrorist informants to infiltrate left-wing terrorist organizations,9 and the crackdown on the radical Real Irish Republican Army (IRA) carried out by both the police and the Provisional IRA after the bombing of Omagh.10See Dingley 1999; and The Express, 6 August 2001,12.
The analysis generates additional hypotheses. I allow the government to choose its level of investment in counterterrorism endogenously and explore how both the expected level of violence and the aid of former terrorists affects this investment decision. I also discuss hypotheses regarding the terms of negotiated settlements between governments and terrorists, when moderates accept concessions, the effect of concessions on the duration of terrorist conflicts, the incentives for moderate terrorists to radicalize their followers, reasons for governments to encourage radicals within a terrorist organization to challenge the moderate leadership, and changes in moderate control over extremists before and after negotiated settlement. I illustrate the model through a discussion of the conflict between Israelis and Palestinians.
The Extant Literature
Others have noted the division between extremists and moderates. In his ground-breaking formal study of political violence, DeNardo demonstrates how government willingness to make concessions can lead to a split within a revolutionary movement between pragmatists and purists, although he does not develop the increased-militancy argument I present here.11
Sandler and Arce provide a model in which government uncertainty over terrorist types leads to adverse selection.12 Both Stedman and Kydd and Walter argue that extremists (“spoilers,” in Stedman's terminology) may attempt to prevent compromise and peace by engaging in terror that undermines the government's confidence in ongoing negotiations.13See Stedman 1997; and Kydd and Walter 2002.
A variety of other explanations have been offered in the literature for the increase in terrorist violence that sometimes follows government concessions. Discussing the ETA, Shabad and Llera Ramo conclude that the cause of the increase in terror following the granting of Basque autonomy was a “culture of violence” that prevented ETA from abandoning violent tactics.14
Darby argues that violence erupts during negotiations because of a combination of nervousness over the coming decrease in terrorist activity and demobilization of the security forces responsible for counterterror.15 Ross and Gurr suggest that violence may increase after concessions because compromise constitutes an existential threat to terror organizations.16 Lapan and Sandler present a game-theoretic model in which they show that, when there is uncertainty regarding a government's resoluteness, the government may be concerned that concessions will lead to an increase in violence by signaling weakness.17A fuller understanding of the politics of terrorism would incorporate all of these factors and many others. The model developed here does not constitute a complete description of the complex and nuanced politics underlying terrorism. Rather, I have attempted to isolate two important features of these politics—increased militancy following concessions and the commitment problem—and explore their implications before adding additional complexity or attempting a richer theoretical synthesis.
The Model
Consider a model of the interaction between a terrorist organization and a government, G. The terrorists attempt to defeat the government (for example, overthrow the regime or force them off a piece of land) and extract concessions, while the government tries to defeat the terrorists, minimize the amount of terror inflicted on society, and limit concessions. Further, the terrorist movement is made up of two factions: moderates (m) and extremists (e).
The game is played as follows. The government makes an offer of concessions to the moderate terrorist faction. These terrorists decide whether to accept the government's offer or not. Accepting involves laying down weapons and coming out of hiding. Once the moderates have concluded their negotiations with the government, the extremist faction decides whether or not to accept concessions. If a terrorist faction chooses not to accept the government's offer, it continues to engage in terror in an attempt to defeat the government. If a terrorist faction accepts concessions, it becomes unable to return to terror because it demilitarizes and the government knows its whereabouts. Factions that accept concessions must then decide whether or not to aid the government in its counterterror efforts. The government simultaneously chooses whether or not to honor promised concessions. The still-active terrorist factions then choose a level of terror in which to engage, and finally, the government chooses how much to invest in its counterterror program.
Once all of these decisions are made, outcomes are realized. These outcomes take two forms. First, the success of government counterterror efforts is determined. If the still-active terrorist factions survive government crackdowns, then the success of terrorist violence is determined. The game is repeated until one side or the other defeats its opponent.18
As will be shown in remark (3), it is a property of the equilibria of this game that a total peace involving all terrorists cannot be achieved.
Having described the basic outline, I now turn to the detailed assumptions underlying the model. In round τ the government offers concessions kτ ≥ 0. I assume that an exogenously determined fraction (β ∈ (0,1)) of these concessions are public goods, such as a grant of political autonomy, the benefits of which are reaped by all terrorists whether or not they accept the concessions. Then (1 − β) of the concessions constitute private goods that can only be accessed by those terrorists who accept concessions.
The government also attempts to eradicate the terror organization through counterterrorism. The government's probability of successfully defeating the terrorists is a function of two variables: the amount the government invests in counterterrorism in round τ (aτ ∈ [0,a]), and whether former terrorists are helping the government (hτ ∈ {h,h}), where h represents the former terrorists providing aid. The government has probability σ(a,h) of defeating the terrorists, where σ : [0,a] × {h,h} → [0,1] . I assume that the probability of success is increasing in the level of government effort (∂σ/∂a > 0), and that the probability of success is higher if former terrorists aid the government (σ(a,h) > σ(a,h), for all a). I also assume that the help of former terrorists increases the efficiency of government counterterror efforts by focusing government efforts in the proper place. That is, an increase in government counterterror has a greater marginal impact if the government has received aid from former terrorists. Formally, this implies that for all a′,a′′, if a′ > a′′, then σ(a′,h) − σ(a′′,h) > σ(a′,h) − σ(a′′,h). Government counterterror efforts are also costly. The government bears cost γ(a), where γ(·) is increasing and convex. If the government defeats the terrorists, it receives a payoff of W, which represents the utility associated with governing in peace.
Denote the total amount of terror attempted in round τ by Tτ. The probability that the terrorists defeat the government in round τ, conditional on surviving government counterterror efforts, is given by π(Tτ), where π : R+ → [0,1] is increasing and concave.19
There is an important distinction here. π gives the probability that the terrorists defeat the government if they survive the government's counterterror. The actual probability that the terrorists defeat the government is given by (1 − σ) π—the conditional probability (π) multiplied by the probability that the government fails (1 − σ).
In any given round, there are three possible outcomes. The government wins the conflict with probability σ, in which case it receives a payoff of W and the game ends. The government loses the conflict with probability (1 − σ)π, in which case it receives a payoff of 0 and the game ends. Neither side wins the conflict with probability (1 − σ)(1 − π), in which case the government receives a payoff of B − γ − T − k and the game continues. Denote a history of the game up to round τ by Hτ and let VG(Hτ) be the government's continuation value for the game, given Hτ and neither side winning the conflict in round τ. I assume that W ≥ B + VG(Hτ) for all Hτ and all τ. That is, the government would always prefer to win the conflict rather than have it continue. Further, I assume that

for all Hτ, where

is the amount of concessions that will be offered in equilibrium (to be shown later) and R is the maximum amount of terror that can be perpetrated. This assumption implies that the government always prefers to continue the game rather than lose the conflict. If this were not true, presumably the government would surrender. The government's expected utility is given by the following:

The terrorist movement is endowed with resources R in each round. Those terrorists who do not accept an offer from the government must choose an amount of the movement's resources to expend on terror. I assume that if one faction accepts concessions but the other does not, some percentage (1 − η) of the resources available to the faction that remains active in terrorism are lost. This may be due to donors withdrawing support once a compromise is reached, the former terrorists taking resources with them, loss of control over criminal activities, or a host of other factors. The remaining resources (ηR) accrue to the terrorists continuing to engage in terror.
Terrorist faction i's preferred amount of violence in round τ is labeled tiτ. A terrorist i derives utility θi from defeating the government. This represents the utility of winning the conflict. The relative “extremism” of a terrorist faction is parameterized by θi, i ∈ {m,e}, where θe > θm. That is, the difference between extremist and moderate terrorists, in this model, is the extent to which they value defeating the government. This is a reasonable description of the difference between, for example, Hamas and the Palestine Liberation Organization (PLO), the extremist ETA-militar and the more moderate ETA-politico militar, or the radical members of the Liberation Tigers of Tamil Eelam (LTTE)—also known as the Tamil Tigers—as compared to more moderate Tamil separatists. If the terrorist organization is defeated, the terrorists receive a payoff of 0 for all subsequent rounds.
Each terrorist faction also benefits from any resources that the organization does not invest in terror. This may be because they expropriate resources not utilized for terror or spend them on other valuable activities.20
Hamas, for instance, has an extensive network of social welfare and health care organizations—see Mishal and Sela 2000; the IRA provides vigilante police services for the Catholic population—see Silke 1999; and the Irgun smuggled Jews from Europe into Palestine—see Bell 1977; all costly, nonterrorist activities.
There are three potential events that could occur in any given period. The terrorists win the conflict with probability (1 − σ)π, in which case they receive a payoff of θi. The terrorists lose the conflict with probability σ, in which case they receive a payoff of 0. Neither side wins with probability (1 − σ)(1 − π), in which case the terrorists receive a payoff of βk(Hτ) and the game continues. k(Hτ) = 0, if no concessions are accepted by any terrorists; and k(Hτ) = kτ, if some terrorists accept concessions. This is because active terrorists only gain the public goods portion of governmental concessions if concessions are actually made. Let Vi(Hτ) be a terrorist faction i's continuation value of the game. I assume that

for all H. That is, the terrorists would prefer to defeat the government rather than have the conflict continue. A terrorist faction i has expected utility for engaging in terror given by the following:

If a terrorist faction accepts an offer of concessions k and those concessions are honored by the government, then its members gain utility k. If they are not honored by the government or if the government is defeated, the former terrorists receive a payoff of 0.
Within a terrorist organization, the moderates and the extremists will disagree over how much terror in which to engage. I assume that each group has an exogenously given level of power or influence within the movement. If only one group remains active (because the other group accepted concessions), then that remaining group has all the power. If both groups remain active, then the extremists have influence λ ∈ (0,1) and the moderates have influence (1 − λ).
A terror organization with both moderates and extremists will choose to engage in a level of terror given by Tm,eτ = λteτ + (1 − λ)tmτ. Note that this decision rule does not represent voting; rather it is a reduced form representation of the power politics within the terrorist movement. Relative power might represent the number of cells that each faction controls, the size of each faction, or their influence with donors. For this reason, I assume that each terrorist's sincere preference (ti) is used to determine the movement's behavior.
A terrorist faction that has accepted concessions enters into a commitment game with the government. The terrorists choose whether or not to aid the government in its counterterror efforts (at cost c) and the government chooses whether or not to honor promised concessions. The stage game of the commitment subgame is represented in Figure 1. The full game is played as shown in Figure 2.

Stage game of the commitment subgame

Time line of the stage game
Equilibrium
Multiplicity and Equilibrium Concept
Because this game is repeated, there are many subgame perfect equilibria. I will restrict attention to a class of focal equilibria. There are conditions, in repeated games, under which it is natural to examine history-dependent equilibria in which players are able to achieve higher payoffs by conditioning play on nonpayoff-relevant aspects of the history of the game, and conditions under which it is not natural. The “problem” with conditioning future play on nonpayoff-relevant histories is that the players have to coordinate perfectly on the punishment mechanism they are using. The standard argument, based on the intuition of the Coase theorem, is that players who have a relationship in which they can communicate with one another should be able to coordinate on the use of nonpayoff-relevant histories to achieve an equilibrium that ensures them a payoff on the Pareto frontier. Players who are unable to communicate are more likely to fail to coordinate on such an equilibrium and, rather, play equilibria that are only dependent on payoff-relevant histories.21
I apply these criteria to the analysis of this model. In most of the subgames I analyze, the players are enemies. As such, in these subgames I solve for Markov Perfect Equilibria—equilibria in which players condition only on payoff-relevant histories—on the assumption that such players do not actively communicate to establish coordination mechanisms. This solution concept excludes equilibria in which the government and terrorists agree to a joint reduction in counterterror and terrorism, respectively, based on history-contingent punishments if either side defects.
There is one part of the game in which a communicative relationship exists. This is the commitment subgame in which the former terrorists and the government have already reached a negotiated agreement. These players could use communication during the negotiation process to coordinate on a mutually beneficial outcome. Consequently, in this subgame I solve for subgame perfect, history-dependent equilibria that achieve payoffs on the Pareto frontier. For convenience, I will refer to this equilibrium concept—in which players play Markov Perfect equilibria except in subgames in which communication is possible, in which case they play Pareto-optimal, history-dependent, subgame perfect equilibria—as a Communicatively Efficient Markov Equilibrium (CEME).
Level of Counterterror
The government will choose a level of counterterror to maximize its expected utility, given the concessions it has made, the expected level of attempted terror, and whether former terrorists are aiding it. Given these payoff-relevant pieces of information about earlier stages of the game, no other facts about the history of the game impact the government's decision. As such, I drop the round-of-play indicator (τ). Contingent on the level of concessions, the expected level of terror, and the aid of former terrorists, the government will play the same strategy in each round. The maximization problem is given by:

An interior solution is characterized by the first-order condition:

Equation (1) implicitly defines the optimal level of counterterror (a*). The left-hand side represents the marginal benefit that an increase in counterterror has on the government's likelihood of defeating the terrorists. The right-hand side represents the marginal costs in terms of resources devoted to counterterror.
There are two facts that can be gleaned from the optimization decision. They are summarized in the following remark.
Remark 1: At an interior solution, the level of counterterror the government chooses is increasing in the expected level of attempted terror (T) and is greater if the government receives counterterror aid from the terrorists.
The proof is in the Appendix. The remark has a clear intuition. First, the more violence the government expects, the greater its need to prevent attacks. Consequently, the government invests more in counterterror when it faces a more violent opponent. Second, when the government receives aid from former terrorists, its counterterror is more efficient because it can use the intelligence from former terrorists to direct its efforts productively. This implies that the marginal benefit of an increase in counterterror is greater when the government receives counterterror aid, while the marginal costs remain the same. Consequently, the government chooses a higher level of investment in counterterror when it is aided by former terrorists.
Level of Violence
Recall that the level of violence in which the terrorist organization engages (Tτ) is a function of the preferences of the still-active factions. A faction's sincere preference is determined by maximizing its expected utility as though its preferred level of terror (ti) will be the level of terror actually carried out. Because only payoff-relevant histories are considered, I drop the time indicators:

The first-order condition characterizes the optimal choice at an interior solution. For the sake of readability, I drop the arguments of functions and define P = βk(H) + Vi(H), which is the terrorists' payoff if neither side wins. The first-order condition is:

Increasing the level of resources invested in terror has three effects on the expected utility of a terrorist. The first term ((1 − σ)dπ/dti(θ − P) > 0) represents the direct impact on the probability of defeating the government of an increase in resources devoted to terror. The second term (−∂σ/∂a* ∂a*/∂ti(πθi + (1 − π)P) < 0) represents the fact that an increase in resources devoted to terror has the indirect effect of increasing the level of counterterror in which the government engages, which increases the probability of the terrorists being defeated. The third term (−ν′ < 0) represents the opportunity costs of using scarce resources for violence.
From equation (2) it can be determined how different terrorist factions will behave as a function of type and resources. These results are stated in the following remark.
Remark 2: At an interior solution, ti* is increasing in θi and R.
The proof is in the Appendix. Intuitively, the more extreme a terrorist faction (higher θi) or the more resources to which they have access, the more terror in which that faction wishes to engage.
I can now characterize the level of violence that a terrorist movement will choose. If a terror organization is made up of both moderates and extremists, it will choose a level of terror given by Tm,e = λte* + (1 − λ)tm*. If a terror organization is comprised only of extremists it will choose a level of terror given by Te = te*.
Note that it is an immediate consequence of remark (2) that if resources do not diminish after concessions (η = 1), then Te > Tm,e. A terror group composed exclusively of extremists engages in more terror than one composed of both moderates and extremists, if they are equally well financed. However, if the level of resources to which the terrorists have access following concessions decreases enough (η sufficiently small), then the effect of a diminution in resources may more than compensate for the increased militancy of the group. In such a case, there will be a decrease in violence despite increased militancy, because the extremists will lack the wherewithal to engage in the amount of violence they would like. For the remainder of this article, I derive results contingent on resources not diminishing this much. However, I return to this possibility in the conclusion with an illustrative example.
Commitment
As Figure 1 shows, the commitment subgame is a prisoners' dilemma. The government would prefer to extract aid from the terrorists without making concessions, and the terrorists would like to extract concessions without providing counterterror aid. Recall that in this subgame, the equilibrium concept allows for history-dependent strategies because the players are in a communicative relationship. Further, the equilibrium concept (appealing to the Coase theorem) requires, if possible, that the players arrive at an outcome on the Pareto frontier. There are many such equilibria (with different punishment strategies). Any equilibrium in which cooperation is sustained will support the relevant equilibrium path in the larger game.
I will refer to the players as having solved the commitment problem if they are playing an equilibrium of the commitment subgame in which concessions are honored and counterterror aid is provided. Thus we have the following lemma.
Lemma 1: There exist subgame perfect equilibria of the commitment subgame in which cooperation is sustainable if the level of concessions is neither too small nor too large relative to the probability of the game ending. Moreover, if any such equilibria exist, then all subgame perfect equilibria with outcomes on the Pareto frontier solve the commitment problem.
Proof. Because the commitment problem being solved is the Pareto-dominant outcome of the stage game, it is clear that all equilibria on the Pareto frontier must solve the commitment problem if doing so is possible.
I provide a proof of the existence of such an equilibrium by constructing one.
The simplest example of such an equilibrium involves trigger strategies. Consider the following profile of strategies for this subgame. The former terrorists provide counterterror aid in every period unless the government in at least one instance has not honored concessions, in which case the former terrorists do not provide aid ever again. Similarly, the government honors concessions in every period as long as the former terrorists have always provided aid. If the former terrorists have failed in at least one instance to provide aid, the government never again honors concessions. To see the conditions under which this set of strategies forms an equilibrium in which the commitment problem is solved, I have to check that neither player has an incentive to engage in a one-shot deviation.
The former terrorists' expected utility from these strategies is given by:

If the former terrorists deviate they receive a payoff of:

Thus, the former terrorists will play this cooperative strategy as long as

Note that the right-hand side of the equation is the probability that either the government or the terrorists wins the conflict. Thus for the former terrorists to be willing to provide aid to the government, the probability of the government or the terrorists being defeated cannot be too large relative to the size of the concessions.
I now turn to the government's actions. Label the probability of the government succeeding in counterterror when it is aided by former terrorists as σ, and the probability when it is not aided by former terrorists as σ. Similarly, label the amount invested in counterterror with aid γ, and without counterterror aid γ. It is an immediate consequence of remark (1) that σ > σ and γ > γ. Finally, label the amount of terror when the government has the aid of the moderates Ta, and when it does not have the aid of the moderates Tna. The government's expected utility from the cooperative strategies is:

The government's payoff from deviating is:

Some algebra shows that the government will play the cooperative strategy if

Thus the government will play the cooperative strategy as long as the concessions it makes are not too large relative to the increase in expected utility the government realizes by increasing its probability of defeating the terrorists.
The former terrorists will not act cooperatively if they believe that the probability of the conflict ending quickly is sufficiently high. This has two implications. First, moderates are unlikely to abandon particularly strong terrorist organizations because they do not want to forgo the opportunity to defeat the government. Second, moderates are unlikely to strike a deal with overwhelmingly strong governments because they believe those governments will not honor concessions in the long run, because the government is likely to quickly win the conflict outright. Importantly, the need to sustain cooperation places both an upper and a lower bound on the level of concession. Label these bounds k and k, respectively.
There are two further points worth noting. First, it is clear that in any CEME of the whole game (as opposed to just the commitment subgame) in which concessions are made, the commitment problem must be solved. No terrorists will accept concessions if they know that the government will not honor them. Second, this subgame demonstrates that if both terrorist factions accept concessions, so that no terrorist movement remains, the government will not honor its concessions. Consequently, there cannot be an equilibrium of the larger game in which both terrorist factions accept concessions. This result is summarized in the following remark.
Remark 3. There does not exist a CEME in which both terrorist factions accept concessions.
Proof. The proof follows from the argument in the text.
Because concessions can only be accepted by one faction, once concessions have been offered and accepted, the still-remaining terrorists can no longer hope to achieve concessions. Nonetheless, they are willing to continue fighting because of the chance of defeating the government.
Accept or Reject
A terrorist faction will only accept concessions if the commitment problem is solved and the expected utility from the concessions is greater than the expected utility from engaging in violence.
The probability that the government defeats the terrorists or the terrorists defeat the government in any given round is given by σ + (1 − σ)π. Consequently, the probability that the game continues to the next round is given by one minus this probability or (1 − σ)(1 − π). Thus the expected utility to terrorist faction i if both moderates and extremists engage in terror is given by:

Similarly, the expected utility to a faction i when the other faction accepts a deal is given by:

The following remark will play an important role in developing the equilibria.
Remark 4: There exists a level of concessions that is acceptable to the moderates but not to the extremists.
The proof is given in the Appendix. The intuition is that a terrorist faction i will consider accepting a deal if k ≥ EUi(T). Moderate terrorists derive less expected utility from the possibility of defeating the government. Consequently, the moderates are willing to give up the possibility of complete victory for a lower level of concessions than are the extremists.
There are two cases to consider in determining whether the two terrorist factions will accept concessions in equilibrium: k < EUm(Tm,e) and k ≥ EUm(Tm,e). If k < EUm(Tm,e), then no terrorists have an incentive to accept concessions. If k ≥ EUm(Tm,e), then moderate terrorists have an incentive to accept concessions. Once the moderates have accepted, the extremists will not accept because the concessions will not be honored if both factions accept, as demonstrated in remark (3). Note that the sequential structure of the terrorists' decision process is not particularly important. As shown in remark (4), the moderates are willing to accept a smaller level of concessions than the extremists. Consequently, assuming it is in the range that solves the commitment problem, the smallest offer that the government can make that will be acceptable to a terrorist faction is k = EUm(Tm,e), which is acceptable to the moderates but not the extremists.
At this point, it will simplify matters to add a little notation. The following results have been established: (1) the level of investment in counterterror is increasing in the amount of attempted terror; and (2) assuming resources do not diminish too much, the amount of terror when the extremists control the organization is greater than when both extremists and moderates control the organization. These results jointly imply that the investment in counterterror, the probability of preventing terror attacks, and the amount of attempted terror are highest when the extremists control the terror organization. I will label the equilibrium level of investment in counterterror when the extremists control the terror organization ae and when both groups control the terror organization am,e, where ae > am,e. Similarly, I will label the equilibrium probabilities of successful counterterror σe and σm,e, where σe > σm,e. The costs of counterterror are labeled γe and γm,e, where γe > γm,e. Finally, the probabilities of the government being defeated (given that government counterterror fails) are labeled πe and πm,e, where πe > πm,e.
Level of Concessions
Given the terrorists' best responses, the government can determine what concessions to offer. If k < max{EUm(Tm,e),k}, then no terrorists accept the offer. Total attempted terror in this case is Tm,e, which implies that the government's expected utility is:

The government can also make an offer of concessions that is acceptable to the moderates but not to the extremists. If the government makes such an offer, it will make the lowest possible such offer (because the government is trying to minimize the amount of concessions). Consequently, in this circumstance the government will offer

. The total attempted terror in this case is Te. Using similar algebra, it is clear that the government's expected utility in this case is:

The government never has an incentive to offer concessions greater than

, because the moderates will accept any offer at least as large as

. Consequently, the government chooses to “buy” the moderates at the lowest level of concessions possible.
Depending on parameter values, either of these outcomes can arise in equilibrium. The key features of the equilibria of this game are characterized in the following proposition.
Proposition 1: In a CEME, if it is not feasible for the commitment problem to be solved, then no concessions are offered, the government chooses a level of counterterror given by equation (1), and the terrorists choose a preferred level of violence according to equation (2).
If it is feasible to solve the commitment problem, then the government chooses whether to make concessions by comparing the expected utilities in equations (5) and (6). If the latter is larger and

, then the government offers concessions

, honors the concessions if they are accepted, and chooses a level of counterterror according to equation (1). The moderates accept any offer of concessions greater than or equal to

and provide counterterror aid. The extremists never accept an offer along the equilibrium path. Terrorists who do not accept concessions choose a preferred level of violence according to equation (2).
Proof. If concessions will not be honored, then no terrorist has an incentive to accept them. Given this, the optimality of the government's and terrorists' actions follow from equations (1) and (2).
If the commitment problem can be solved, then the government makes concessions if the expected utility of a deal is greater than the expected utility of no deal. That the level of concessions will be

follows immediately from the government's objective function. That concessions will only be made if

follows from lemma (1). The optimality of the players' behavior then follows from equations (1) and (2).
Of primary importance for this analysis are the outcomes associated with two different equilibrium paths and the parameter values that lead to them. These are summarized in the following corollary.
Corollary 1: There are 2 equilibrium paths of this game when cooperation occurs in the commitment subgame.
- The “No Deal” path occurs if concessions
are offered. The total level of attempted terror in this case is Tm,e.
- The “Buying the Moderates” path occurs when an
offer of concessions
is made. In this case the moderates accept, the extremists reject, and the total level of attempted terror is Te.
Proof. The results follow directly from proposition (1).
Analysis
Level of Violence
The first point of interest is the level of terrorist violence with and without concessions. As demonstrated in remark (2), the terrorist organization engages in more terror after concessions (Te > Tm,e) as long as the loss of resources is not too large. When the government offers concessions, only the moderates are willing to accept. This leaves the extremists in control of the terrorist organization. Once the influence of the moderates is removed, the extremists choose to direct more of the available resources toward terrorist activities. The government faces a trade-off when making concessions. On the one hand, the probability of succeeding at counterterror increases and the resources to which the terrorists have access diminish. On the other hand, the amount of violence may increase because the terrorist movement is composed exclusively of the extremists who refused to accept concessions.
Duration of Conflict
This trade-off also allows for a comparison of the expected duration of a terrorist conflict as a function of whether or not a compromise settlement has been reached. The probability that a conflict continues in any given round is (1 − σ)(1 − π). Thus the expected duration of a conflict is:

This function is decreasing in both σ and π. Since σe > σm,e and πe > πm,e (assuming η is sufficiently large), terrorist conflicts are expected to have a shorter duration if a negotiated settlement has been reached. Thus conflicts in which the government negotiates with terrorists are, in expectation, shorter but more violent. These results are summarized in the following proposition.
Proposition 2: Assuming resources do not diminish too much, the level of terror is higher following concessions to the moderates. However, the expected duration of the conflict is shorter following concessions to the moderates.
Proof. The results follow from remark (2) and equation (7).
This result has implications for the empirical study of terror. First, it provides a theoretical understanding for the frequently observed, but somewhat perplexing, phenomenon of increases in terrorist activity following concessions: when moderates accept concessions the extremists are left in control of the terrorist organization. The model also explains why governments nonetheless are sometimes willing to make concessions. The probability of government victory increases and the expected duration of the conflict decreases. This is because of two factors. First, the former terrorists aid the government in its counterterror efforts in order to insure the credibility of government concessions. Second, because of the increase in attempted terror and the increased efficiency of its counterterror efforts, the government increases its investment in counterterrorism.
Terms of the Settlement
The model also lends some insight into the terms of negotiated settlements between governments and terrorists. Assuming that the minimal level of concessions that can sustain cooperation in the commitment subgame is less than EUm(Tm,e), if the government makes concessions to the moderates, those concessions will be worth:

which is equal to the moderates' expected utility from remaining active terrorists.
First, notice that the level of concessions is decreasing in the probability of the government winning the conflict.

The more likely the terrorist organization is to lose the conflict, the more attractive it is to the moderates to strike a deal with the government.
Further, recall that Tm,e = λte* + (1 − λ)tm*. Because equation (8) represents the moderates' objective function, it is clear that it would be maximized if the amount of terror chosen was the moderates' preferred amount, tm*. That is, the level of concessions would be maximized if Tm,e = λte* + (1 − λ)tm* were to equal tm*. This leads to several implications for factors that would improve the offer made to the moderates.
The more radical the moderates are (the higher θm), the better the offer made by the government. Hence, strategic moderate leaders may have an incentive to recruit and indoctrinate members into the moderate faction with relatively extreme preferences. By shifting the preferences of the moderates toward the extreme, they create a bargaining tool that compels the government to make more concessions if it wishes to strike a deal. This helps shed light on the puzzling phenomenon of moderate terrorist leaders engaging in behavior that radicalizes their supporters to the point where those “supporters” may no longer be willing even to endorse the positions of the moderate leaders who recruited them. Of course, to fully explore this phenomenon one would want to model a strategic relationship between the moderate leadership and the moderate rank-and-file explicitly. But this comparative static suggests an intuition about strategic moderate leaders' incentives.
Another implication of this line of reasoning is that the more control the moderates have over the terrorist organization (low λ), the better the offer from the government. Thinking of this intuition within a more dynamic framework yields the prediction that moderate leaders will be particularly interested in seeking out a deal with the government when they believe their control over their organization is beginning to decline. This is because if they wait too long and the extremists take control (high λ), then the deal they will ultimately strike with the government will not be as favorable. This suggests an intuition for why governments might aid extremist challengers to moderate terrorist groups. By doing so, the government both increases the moderates' incentives to accept concessions before their power slips away and decreases the ultimate level of concessions granted. Such a strategy was followed, for instance, by the Israeli government during the first Intifada when it lent support to the emerging extremist Islamic movement—which gave rise to groups such as Hamas and Islamic Jihad—in order to encourage an internal challenge to the PLO.22
Indeed, the result was that the PLO's control over Palestinian terrorism was weakened and, eventually, this brought the relatively moderate PLO to the negotiating table.Finally, combining this intuition with the commitment problem between the moderate terrorists and the government yields another result. For the reasons just elucidated, while moderates are actively engaged in terrorism, they have an incentive to limit the power of the extremists within the organization. However, once the moderates accept a deal, the continued existence of extremists helps to insure the credibility of government concessions. As such, the model suggests that moderate terrorists might demonstrate an ability to control extremists within their ranks while they are still actively engaged in terror, yet be reluctant to do as much to eradicate those extremists after accepting concessions.
An Application to the Israeli/Palestinian Conflict
A full empirical treatment is beyond the scope of this article. However, it is instructive to see how the fundamental workings of the model map onto a real-world case of government concessions to moderate terrorists, as illustrated by the Israeli/Palestinian conflict.
The first peace negotiations between Palestinians and Israelis took place in 1991 in Madrid. These negotiations eventually led to the signing of the first Oslo accord in September of 1993, followed by a series of interim peace agreements. The basic framework for negotiations revolved around land for peace. The Israelis agreed to withdraw gradually from occupied lands and grant the Palestinian Authority increasing levels of autonomy in exchange for demilitarization, the cessation of violence, and the PLO's recognition of Israel's right to exist. One of the conditions for the implementation of Israeli concessions was a Palestinian Authority crackdown on extremist violence.23
See Hermann and Newman 2000; and Shlaim 1994.
The Oslo accords created a split among Palestinian nationalists. Extremist factions, including the Popular Front for the Liberation of Palestine, Hamas, Islamic Jihad, and the al Aqsa Martyr's Brigade, rejected the agreement. As Article 13 of the Hamas Charter states:
[Peace] initiatives, the so-called peaceful solutions, and international conferences to resolve the Palestinian problem all contradict the beliefs of the Islamic Resistance Movement. Indeed, giving up any part of Palestine is tantamount to giving up part of its religion. The nationalism of the Islamic Resistance Movement is part of its religion, and it instructs its members to [adhere] to that and to raise the banner of Allah over their homeland as they wage their Jihad.24
Translated in Mishal and Sela 2000.
As recent events have demonstrated, the Israelis seem to have concluded that they overestimated the helpfulness of the Palestinians in counterterror. This has led them to renege on promised concessions, which has led the Palestinians to reduce their aid in counterterror. This is consistent with the intuitions underlying the commitment subgame, if the Israelis and Palestinians are playing some sort of tit-for-tat strategy.25
Of course, with perfect information, noncooperation should never occur on the equilibrium path. But standard intuitions regarding the introduction of uncertainty into this repeated game yield results similar to the patterns observed in the Israeli/Palestinian conflict.
Consistent with the model, an increase in violence occurred concomitant with the relatively moderate PLO's decision to negotiate with the Israelis, leaving the terror campaign in the hands of more extreme factions. As resources given by donors who support armed resistance and control of terrorist activity and recruitment shifted to the still-active factions, the extremists were able to increase the level of violence. The annual fatalities from Palestinian terrorism are reported in Figure 3.26
Throughout, I examine the number of fatalities attributed to terrorism rather than the number of attacks (which is the statistic examined by, for example, Kydd and Walter).27 The number of people killed better captures the idea of the level of terrorist violence. In particular, there are significant strategic differences between a bombing that kills several dozen people and a knifing that leaves one casualty.
Annual fatalities from Palestinian terrorism, 1978–1998
An important alternative explanation for this increase is the spoiler effect suggested by Kydd and Walter. The radicals wanted to undermine the peace process and so engaged in more terrorism than they otherwise would have.
Though different, these two arguments are not mutually exclusive. The spoiler model predicts a short-term spike in violence during peace negotiations. The increased militancy effect that I propose is longer term, having to do with a change in the composition of the terrorist movement rather than a shift in short-term incentives. Consequently, while the spoiler effect will produce a spike and then a drop in terrorist violence, the increased militancy effect (contingent on the failure of counterterror) is expected to produce a long-term increase in the base level of terrorist violence. While these two accounts imply different empirical predictions, both causal mechanisms could operate simultaneously. If so, one would expect a large spike during a peace process, reflecting both effects, followed by a sustained period of heightened violence (although perhaps at a level somewhat lower than during the peace process but higher than previous levels of violence), reflecting the continued heightened militancy effect and disappearance of the spoiler effect. Because the Palestinians and Israelis are still in the midst of on-and-off negotiations, the key challenge in assessing the validity of my model is to separate out violence caused by the spoiler effect to see if there is also explanatory space for my increased-militancy argument.
Spoiler violence is only expected to occur before major agreements and perhaps just after those agreements. The key spoiler opportunities in the Israeli/Palestinian conflict are summarized in Table 1. Following Kydd and Walter, I have classified Palestinian and Israeli elections, in addition to important negotiations, as spoiler opportunities. I consider a larger set of spoiler opportunities than did Kydd and Walter, leading to somewhat different conclusions.
Key “spoiler” opportunities in the Israeli/Palestinian peace process

Figure 4 gives monthly fatalities from Palestinian terror for the time period between Oslo and the onset of the second Intifada in September of 2000, and Figure 5 from the beginning of the second Intifada through December 2002.28
The full data are available from the author's Web site at 〈www.artsci.wustl.edu/∼ebuenode〉. These data are collected from the International Policy Institute on Counter-Terrorism in Herzliya: 〈http://www.ict.org.il〉. I have counted any person that was killed directly by a Palestinian terrorist attack (other than the terrorist him or herself) in the Occupied Territories or in Israel proper. This includes accidental killings of sympathetic Palestinians as well as attacks on Israeli military personnel. It does not include bystanders (whether Israeli or Palestinian) caught in the cross-fire and killed by Israeli forces. While inherently mired in political debates, I do not intend this codification to carry a particular political message. Changing the coding rules would not qualitatively alter the results.

Monthly fatalities due to Palestinian terror, September 1993–August 2000

Monthly fatalities due to Palestinian terror, September 2000– December 2002
As can be seen in Figures 4 and 5, while there were spikes in violence before the signing of the Cairo agreement, the Israel-Jordan peace accord, and the Palestinian elections, there were not spikes before Oslo II, the Israeli elections of 1996 or 1999, the first Taba negotiations, the Wye Accords, the Sharm el-Sheik Memorandum, or the Camp David negotiations. Because they fall near the beginning of the increase associated with the second Intifada, it is debatable whether there was a spike before the joint statement from Taba in January 2001 and the Israeli elections in February 2001. While some of the increase in violence that followed Oslo was likely the result of the spoiler effect, much of it occurred during periods when there were not significant spoiler opportunities. This suggests that other factors, such as the increased militancy that resulted from groups such as Hamas and Islamic Jihad taking control of the terrorist movement, also play a role in explaining the increase in violence.
The evidence for this claim can be further solidified by determining whether the average level of monthly fatalities is greater during spoiler opportunities than during other time periods. It is unclear how long a period constitutes the spoiler opportunity surrounding a negotiation or election. The periods around major events that Kydd and Walter examine range from a couple of weeks (before the Israel-Jordan Peace Accord) to several months (prior to Wye). The typical period they look at is approximately a month. Following their lead, I treat the month of, as well as the months before and after, a major strategic event as a spoiler opportunity. I partition the monthly data into two groups: violence that occurred during a spoiler opportunity and violence that occurred when there was not a spoiler opportunity. The summary statistics for these data are given in Table 2.
Summary statistics of monthly fatalities due to Palestinian terror, September 1993– December 2002

Surprisingly, the mean level of violence during spoiler opportunities (5.1) was lower than during periods where there were not spoiler opportunities (10.2), contradicting the spoiler model. This anomalous result can be explained by the fact that there have not been spoiler opportunities since early 2001, while there has been a significant increase in violence after the advent of the second Intifada. Of course, this increase in violence in the absence of spoiler incentives is itself evidence that factors in addition to spoiler effects are at work. Also, in support of my model, it has been the extremists that have stoked the flames of violence.
Nonetheless, it is worthwhile to examine whether the spoiler effect explains most of the increase in violence that occurred after Oslo before the second Intifada, or whether there is room for additional explanatory theories, such as increased militancy. To examine this, I consider the same partition of the data but only look from September 1993 through September 2000 (when the second Intifada began). The summary statistics for this procedure are shown in Table 3.
Summary statistics of monthly fatalities due to Palestinian terror, September 1993– September 2000

In the more limited set of data in Table 3, the level of violence is slightly higher during spoiler opportunities than during other periods, as the spoiler model predicts. However, the difference in levels of violence with and without spoiler opportunities is not statistically significant.29
The null hypothesis is that the two means are equal and the alternative hypothesis is that there are more fatalities during spoiler opportunities. The t-statistic is 0.052, while the critical value for rejection of the null at the 95 percent confidence level is approximately t > 1.67.
Conclusion and Potential Extensions
The model developed in this study yields three key results. First, it suggests an explanation of the observation that government concessions often lead to an increase in the militancy of terrorist organizations. Namely, concessions draw moderate terrorists away from the terrorist movement, leaving the organization in the control of extremists. Second, it provides an answer to the question of why governments make concessions in light of the increased militancy they engender. The government's probability of succeeding in counterterrorism improves following concessions because of the help of former terrorists that directly improves counterterror and leads the government to invest more resources in its counterterror efforts. Thus terrorist conflicts in which concessions have been made are more violent but shorter. Third, it demonstrates how the ability of former terrorists to provide counterterror aid to the government can solve the credible commitment problem that governments face when offering concessions.
The application to the conflict between Israelis and Palestinians suggests avenues for extension of the model. The comparative statics regarding the terms of the negotiated settlement led to the intuition that moderates want to appear to have control over the extremists before an agreement but then, after concessions, might be reluctant to crack down too strongly for fear of undermining their bargaining leverage. This pattern seems to have occurred in the Israeli/Palestinian case. While the current model provides an intuition about the incentives for such behavior, an extension would offer a more nuanced understanding.
I have assumed that the government knows whether or not the former terrorists have provided counterterror aid and can reward or punish them accordingly. In reality, the Israelis are uncertain of the extent to which the Palestinian Authority is trying to reign in militants. Further, the Israelis may be uncertain of the Palestinian Authority's ability to control extremists. Hence, there is both a moral hazard and a learning problem. Explicitly modeling these dynamics might yield insight into when the government will give up on negotiated settlement as well as when former terrorists are likely to exert significant effort (perhaps when the government is close to giving up on them) and when they are likely to shirk. Thus building on the current model along these lines might shed further light on the dynamics underlying the Israeli/Palestinian conflict and others like it.
Another extension that the application suggests relates to the strategic interaction between terrorist factions. Extremists can respond to moderates who negotiate with the government in a variety of ways. They might attempt to make a counteroffer to persuade the moderates not to accept concessions. They might also engage in violence against the former terrorists to prevent them from aiding the government in counterterror. Indeed, empirical cases of terrorism reveal a range of outcomes along these lines. While extremists within some insurgent groups have explicitly decided not to take action against moderate factions—Hamas's refusal to engage in violence against the PLO or the Irgun's decision not to fight back against the Hagannah—in other cases violence amongst terrorist factions is quite extreme—the Sri Lankan LTTE's brutal attacks against competing and moderate Tamil groups.30
On Hamas and the PLO, see Abu-Amr 1993; on the Irgun and Hagannah, see Bell 1976; on the LTTE, see Saravanamuttu 2000.
Finally, the results of this model were contingent on the size of the diminution of resources following concessions to moderates. It is important to think about when this decrease will be large or small. The main sources of terrorist funding are legitimate businesses, organized criminal activity, and donations.31
Moderate donors are likely to cease giving to the terrorist organization following concessions, though extremist donors may be inclined to increase donations as the organization becomes more ideologically pure. Further, former terrorists may be able to maintain ownership of legitimate businesses, though they are more likely to lose control of criminal enterprises if they relinquish their weapons as part of their deal with the government.If resources diminish too much, the extremists, despite their militancy, lack the wherewithal to increase violence to the level they would like. Concessions, then, lead to an increase in militancy, but this does not translate into an increase in violence, due to a lack of resources. Such a scenario might, for instance, describe the situation in Northern Ireland following the Good Friday accords. Leaving the terrorist campaign in the hands of radical splinter groups, such as the “Real” IRA, led to an increase in militancy. These extremists engaged in terrorist attacks—the bombing of Omagh, a missile attack on MI6, the assault on Ebrington Barracks in Derry, and the bombing of the BBC—that were qualitatively more violent than anything in which the Provisional IRA had engaged.32
See Dingley 2001; The Irish Times, 12 March 2001, 7; and The Express, 6 August 2001, 12.
See Dingley 1999; The Irish Times, 12 March 2001, 7; and The Express, 6 August 2001, 12.
Appendix
Proofs of Remarks, Lemmas, and Propositions
Proof of Remark 1. To show that at an interior solution a* is increasing in T note that

The first term is positive by assumption

, otherwise the government would surrender. The other two terms are clearly positive. Thus the whole expression is positive, so UG has strictly increasing marginal returns in T and a, which means that Edlin and Shannon's Monotonicity Theorem implies that a* is increasing in T.
35To show that a*(h) > a*(h), notice that the government's expected utility function can be rewritten as follows:

Because W > B + VG(H), it is clear that the first term is strictly positive. Further, it then follows that from the fact that σ(a,h) has increasing differences that UG has increasing differences in a and h. Thus Topkis's Monotonicity Theorem implies that a* is increasing in h.36
Vives 1999, theorem 2.3.
Proof of Remark 2. That ti* is increasing in R can be seen by noticing that

because ν(·) is concave. Thus Ui has strictly increasing marginal returns in t and R, so Edlin and Shannon's Monotonicity Theorem implies that t* is increasing in R.
To see that ti* is increasing in θi notice that,

Recall that the first-order condition is:

Note that if the first term of this first-order condition is not larger than the second term, then the whole condition is strictly negative. This is because, in that scenario, the actual level of terror is decreasing in the amount of resources devoted to terror because the positive effect of resources on terror is swamped by the indirect effect of an increase in counterterror by the government. This leads to a corner solution in which the terrorists choose ti* = 0. Thus at an interior solution, the first term must be larger than the second term. Formally this implies that:

which can be rewritten

The right-hand side of this equation is strictly greater than:

Thus, the first-order condition implies that

which implies that

Given this, equation (9) is strictly positive, so Ui has strictly increasing marginal returns in t and θ, which, by Edlin and Shannon's Monotonicity Theorem, implies that t* is increasing in θi at an interior solution.
Proof of Remark 4. I need to show that there exists a k such that EUm(Tm,e*) ≤ k < EUe(Tm,e*). If this is true, then the moderates would like to accept but the extremists would not.
The existence of such a k can be confirmed by direct comparison of equation (3) for moderates and extremists. The claim is true if:

which is clearly true because θe > θm.
References
REFERENCES

Stage game of the commitment subgame

Time line of the stage game

Annual fatalities from Palestinian terrorism, 1978–1998

Key “spoiler” opportunities in the Israeli/Palestinian peace process

Monthly fatalities due to Palestinian terror, September 1993–August 2000

Monthly fatalities due to Palestinian terror, September 2000– December 2002

Summary statistics of monthly fatalities due to Palestinian terror, September 1993– December 2002

Summary statistics of monthly fatalities due to Palestinian terror, September 1993– September 2000
- 27
- Cited by