Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-kw2vx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-10T16:23:52.503Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Private Law Critique of International Investment Law

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 January 2019

Julian Arato*
Affiliation:
Associate Professor of Law, Brooklyn Law School.
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This Article argues that investment treaties subtly constrain how nations organize their internal systems of private law, including laws of property, contracts, corporations, and intellectual property. Problematically, the treaties do so on a one-size-fits-all basis, disregarding the wide variation in values reflected in these domestic legal institutions. Investor-state dispute settlement exacerbates this tension, further distorting national private law arrangements. This hidden aspect of the system produces inefficiency, unfairness, and distributional inequities that have eluded the regime's critics and apologists alike.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © 2019 by The American Society of International Law 

I. Introduction

International investment law (IIL) goes further in disciplining states’ internal policy space than is commonly realized. The point has been made time and again that IIL restricts states’ capacity to regulate in the public interest. While this critique is sometimes overstated, it is clear that investment treaties do constrain national regulatory autonomy regarding foreign property to a degree. But what is generally missed is an altogether different way in which IIL disciplines the state's internal legal architecture. I argue that investment treaties subtly, but significantly, constrain how nations organize and balance their internal systems of private law vis-à-vis foreigners—not only with respect to property rights, but also extending to laws of contracts, intellectual property, and corporations. Problematically, however, they tend to do so on a rigid, one-size-fits-all basis, without regard to the wide variation in values reflected in these discrete private law institutions. Moreover, these constraints have been inflated, irregularly and inconsistently, through investor-state dispute settlement (ISDS) case law. Put another way, IIL and ISDS together haphazardly discipline domestic private law policy space, with overlooked consequences for both private and public interests. This hidden aspect of the investment treaty regime produces discrete doctrinal, conceptual, and distributional problems, which are insufficiently understood—by critics and apologists of the system alike.

This Article draws out the private law dimension of IIL as a new frame for understanding the system's promise and pitfalls. IIL has effectively, if unintentionally, created far-reaching swathes of international private lawFootnote 1 across diverse fields—through a dynamic combination of treaty-making by states and interpretation by international arbitrators. Not only does IIL thereby displace particular rules of national private law. Much more seriously, it distorts the logic and functions of core private law institutions—for example by undermining party choice in contracts, and the separate legal personality of corporations.

I make two main claims: one conceptual and one critical. First, I argue that IIL has emerged as a broad, amorphous field of international private law. This development has turned on a common but subtle problem of treaty drafting. Investment treaties typically lay out broad definitions of investment, covering not only standard forms of property, but also “assets of any kind.” By extending their protections to property, contracts, intellectual property, enterprises, and stocks and shares, investment treaties create international private law in relation to each—incompletely, to be sure, but meaningfully disciplining national private law nevertheless. Yet these treaties rarely differentiate as to how their substantive and procedural protections apply to the varied assets they cover. As a result, ISDS tribunals have been left to determine the scope of international property, contract, intellectual property, and corporate law that investment treaties impose—and thus how far IIL displaces domestic private law institutions and values. This they have done expansively, though mostly implicitly.

Second, and more troublingly, I argue that the patterns of interpretation are distorting foundational principles of national private law. The impact is most obvious on relationships between states and foreign investors—but these trends have spillovers for other actors as well. Based on questionable interpretive assumptions, the ISDS case law is producing looming inefficiency and unfairness for investors, host states, home states, and third parties.

The transformation of IIL into a broad regime of international private law has been a quiet metamorphosis. Prior to the 1970s, foreign investment was largely regulated by a thin regime of customary international law. Custom imposed duties of non-discrimination and arguably rules concerning expropriation and due process (denial of justice).Footnote 2 These norms were understood to apply to real and personal property, classically understood, and only in very limited form to contracts.Footnote 3 However, in the 1980s and 1990s, states largely supplanted the customary regime with a network of thousands of bilateral investment treaties (BITs). As is well known, these treaties codified and expanded the international standards of treatment due to foreign investors, and empowered investors to directly sue host states via ISDS. Less understood is that investment treaties almost invariably (1) extend their substantive protections to assets of any kind, without (2) drawing any distinctions as to how their provisions relate to such varied commercial legal relationships. The harm in this under-specification would only emerge in the 2000s, as ISDS exploded in popularity among investors. Concrete cases forced tribunals to determine the relationship between substantive and procedural treaty standards and the broad array of covered investments. But the case law has tended to skate over these questions uncritically, without sensitivity to the wide variety of interests and values at stake. Taken together, through meandering waves of treaty making and interpretation over half a century, IIL has established an invasive field of international private law sub rosa—one whose contours remain fuzzy and unpredictable, often frustrating the very values that investment treaties are designed to promote.

This Article reassesses ISDS jurisprudence from a private law perspective. For the most part, tribunals have broadly and homogeneously applied IIL to all forms of private legal assets. As a result, ISDS has effectively expanded the scope of IIL as a system of international private law, imposing obligations on states regarding the disposition of property, contracts, enterprises, stocks and shares, and intellectual property—all with very little differentiation. Moreover, tribunals rarely consider these matters head on, tending instead to base their reasoning on implicit property-oriented assumptions (or, more recently, assumptions about the level of deference due to states’ public regulatory decisions). The effect is not only to displace particular private law rules, but to distort the varied functions of whole fields of national private law in relations between states and foreign investors.

Investment treaties are clearly designed to protect foreign-owned real and personal property from uncompensated takings, discrimination, and unfair treatment more generally. For the most part, in so doing, IIL reflects the basic structure of property protection found in domestic law—at least in market economies. True, ISDS tribunals have tended to gravitate toward an absolutist “Blackstonian” conception of property, while national jurisdictions tend to exhibit more flexibility, treating property rights as variable “bundles of sticks.”Footnote 4 Domestic property rights are neither absolute, nor equivalent from form to form—let alone country to country—and nations prioritize widely different values in their property institutions. To the extent that IIL requires enhancing these bundles in relation to foreign investors, it can supplement or displace particular national property rules and encroach on the values they embody. Still, the investment treaty regime has not fundamentally distorted how property is protected, leaving the basic animating logic and functions of national property law intact.

Deeper category problems emerge where tribunals consider non-property assets. ISDS tends to resolve such cases in much the same way as property disputes, and with much the same vocabulary. Though subtle, this tendency produces serious normative problems, and it is here that the private law framework I advance has its greatest critical payoff.

Contracts provide the most vivid case. The essence of contract is choice—a logic of customization that contrasts with property's logic of standardization. However, ISDS tribunals implicitly, but routinely, interpret investment treaties as generating wide sets of rigid implied terms applicable to contracts between foreign investors and host states or state-owned entities. Tribunals almost always cast treaty rights as hard property-style rules, with the effect of precluding parties’ contractual choices on matters ranging from substantive duties to excuse, forum selection, and the measure of damages. In contract terminology, tribunals tend to apply treaty rules on all these matters as mandatory terms—or very sticky defaults. This approach turns the logic of contract on its head. In particular cases, it entails effectively rewriting the contractual bargain ex post. This possibility, in turn, constrains states’ and investors’ capacity to efficiently bargain over risk and price ex ante, and may dampen their appetite to contract altogether.Footnote 5 ISDS has also distorted the regulatory functions of contract law in other ways. For example, some tribunals have interpreted IIL as dictating rules on the valid modes of contract formation, thereby requiring states to enforce contracts which would have been invalid ab initio on public policy grounds.Footnote 6 By uncritically and rigidly extending treaty protections to contracts, ISDS tribunals have tended to distort the basic logic of domestic contract law, with unfortunate policy consequences for the very investment-promotion goals that IIL seeks to achieve.

A similar dynamic plays out in the extension of IIL to corporate law. Treaty coverage of both “enterprises” and “stocks and shares” creates jarring ambiguities from a corporate law perspective. For example, BITs generally leave unclear what kinds of claims an investor-shareholder may bring. Tribunals typically assume that investors may bring shareholder claims for losses suffered by the corporation, to vindicate their stocks and shares as covered assets.Footnote 7 This deceptively mundane interpretation erects a rule of international corporate law that cuts against the universal national law presumption that shareholders may not bring claims for indirect diminution in share value caused by third party harm to the firm (except via shareholder derivative suits). Yet ISDS tribunals have displaced this foundational rule uncritically, without any consideration of the strong policies behind the domestic approach, which carefully balances the interests and expectations of the firm, corporate insiders (shareholders and management), and outsiders (creditors and the general public).Footnote 8 The ISDS approach has perverse effects for all concerned, simultaneously subjecting states to multiple claims by the firm, its shareholders, and even indirect owners, while allowing some shareholders to subordinate the rights and interests of other owners, creditors, and management. Tribunals have also muddied foundational questions of corporate agency and authority. For example, in Getma v. Guinea, the tribunal substituted its own ex post assessment of apparent authority for any analysis of the applicable law—an approach that would, ex ante, destabilize the rules of engagement with firms and their agents in the context of foreign direct investment.Footnote 9 In all these cases, ISDS and IIL have displaced key features of domestic corporate law, though only implicitly and without adequate analysis of the tradeoffs, unjustifiably and inefficiently distorting core characteristics and functions of the corporate form—from separate legal personality to delegated management.

By contrast, tribunals have thus far tended to fare better in the few cases involving intellectual property claims. Unlike property, contracts, and corporate law, there is an independent and robust field of international intellectual property law. As the breadth of IIL and ISDS came into focus, some scholars raised alarms that ISDS could be used to subvert both national and international intellectual property arrangements.Footnote 10 However, in the few intellectual property cases that have arisen—all very recent—tribunals have proven more sensitive to the nuances of patents and trademarks, as distinct from real property and other assets. For example, in Philip Morris v. Uruguay the tribunal resisted efforts to cast trademarks in Blackstonian property terms, finding that, unlike with real and personal property, the applicable national and international intellectual property rules endow trademarks with only a right of exclusion, not use rights. In other words, a trademark holder may prevent others from using her mark, but has no separate right to actually use the mark herself—if, for example, the state seeks to limit advertising on tobacco products. Intellectual property is by no means immunized against distortion in the future. But at least the few patent and trademark cases decided thus far suggest a better path toward grappling with the private dimensions of IIL.

In each of these fields, IIL and ISDS are creating new international private law. The seeds lie in the under-specified drafting of investment treaties, which extend broad substantive and procedural protections to a wide range of assets without explaining how these provisions apply to the very different categories of covered investments. ISDS tribunals have tended to assume that treaty norms apply to all covered assets in much the same way. In so doing, they functionally transform IIL into a broad and rigid regime of international private law, constraining states’ flexibility in articulating their internal private law systems—both with respect to choosing which values to enshrine, and how to balance the relevant tradeoffs. In other words, IIL and ISDS not only discipline states’ public regulatory policy space; they also constrain (and distort) how states design their private law institutions—with distinct distributional consequences and implications for societal values.

These problems give rise to two further glaring questions: Why have IIL's private law consequences gone mostly unnoticed? And to what extent may states’ ongoing reform efforts nevertheless address these pathologies? Though not encouraging, the answers turn out to be related.

The rising skepticism of IIL must be understood in light of broader trends in economic globalization. As Poulsen explains, developed states were only able to get BIT programs off the ground in the 1980s and 1990s, as neoliberalism ascended in international economic law and policy more generally.Footnote 11 Thus, the transformative deepening of IIL occurred alongside a more general turn to deep integration strategies among developed and developing states alike in trade, finance, and development policy, all against the backdrop of Washington Consensus ideas.Footnote 12 The backlash against IIL and ISDS in the late 2000s should also be understood in connection with a broader waning of neoliberal ideology—even in mainstream economics.Footnote 13 Here, the particular spark was a series of vivid awards against Argentina arising out of measures taken by that state to weather its financial crisis of 2001–2002. From the beginning, the backlash against IIL and ISDS was heavily influenced by an important, but contingent, intuition that investment treaties unduly constrain national regulatory autonomy—with the dominant scholarly critique oriented around reconceiving IIL in public law terms.Footnote 14 Though highly successful, this line of attack has been overly focused on the general balance between regulatory sovereignty and investor protection.Footnote 15 The outsized influence of these concerns has tended to obscure pathologies in how IIL and ISDS regulate private law—both at the treaty level and within the jurisprudence.

This dynamic also helps explain why recent treaty reform projects have been practically blind to the private dimensions of IIL. Based in large part on perceived imbalances between investor protections and regulatory autonomy, both developed and developing states have embarked on a range of efforts to reform investment treaties—substantivelyFootnote 16 and institutionally.Footnote 17 Laudable as these reforms may be, they have mostly continued to treat the varied assets covered by investment treaties as an undifferentiated mass. The overemphasis on the public law frame has thus allowed a wide range of private law problems to continue unmitigated, and has arguably even contributed to them. Differently designed, IIL could serve as a complement to national private law—one that respects the logic of its various fields as well as the varied policy choices nations make in constructing their discrete private law regimes. But this requires a substantial shift in how we think about investment treaties—not only vis-à-vis interpretation, but, most importantly, at the treaty-making stage.

This Article proceeds in three parts. Part II lays out the private law theory of IIL in broad conceptual terms and situates it alongside the public law approach. Part III then advances a critique of the jurisprudence from a private law perspective. The lion's share of the Article, this Part traces how IIL and ISDS displace and distort national private law across four fields: (A) property; (B) contracts; (C) corporations; and (D) intellectual property. Part IV concludes by laying the groundwork for a refocused project of reform, oriented primarily toward treaty design.

II. The Private Law Theory of International Investment Law

The international law of foreign direct investment regulates state conduct behind the border, by affording special protections to foreign private investors. Investment treaties have two linked goals: to protect foreign investors from certain forms of state action ex post, in order to promote foreign direct investment ex ante.Footnote 18 The evident tradeoff is that such commitments discipline future state action, restricting the state's freedom within its internal domain. An ideal IIL regime would be calibrated to encourage maximally efficient investment while disciplining the state to the minimal extent possible. But such commitments will always prove messy and uncertain in practice. What is important to understand at the outset is that trading off discipline and freedom is a central function of IIL. The real questions are what kinds of disciplines it sets up, what it constrains, and what incentives it produces.

The prevailing view in policy and scholarly circles is that the balance in IIL is off, with the costs of its disciplines outstripping any potential gains in encouraging foreign direct investment.Footnote 19 From a national regulatory perspective, IIL has come under fire for undercutting the state's internal sovereign prerogatives, democratic choice, and self-determination. The concern is that the regime has empowered private investors to collaterally attack all kinds of sovereign regulatory measures, through compulsory, binding, and highly enforceable ISDS arbitration. Further, the sheer volume of investment treaties and arbitral awards has contributed to legal fragmentation and uncertainty. Ad hoc ISDS awards have created significant interpretive inconsistencies, without any institutional mechanism for appeal, review, or harmonization.Footnote 20 These are real concerns, even if occasionally overblown. Even in its best light, this regime at least threatens national regulatory autonomy.

The investment treaty regime is at an inflection point. While very few states have moved toward total exit, very few accept the status quo.Footnote 21 States of all stripes have embarked on significant projects of reform—unilateral,Footnote 22 bilateral,Footnote 23 and multilateral.Footnote 24

The emerging conventional wisdom among reformers holds that IIL must be recast as a system of public law—to better capture its pressure on national regulatory policy. Scholars writing in this vein view the “public law frame” as key to securing national sovereignty and democratic choice, supposing that the language, doctrines, and institutions of public law will be more sensitive to cherished public values.Footnote 25 This turn to public law has not been free of controversy, and important voices remain unconvinced.Footnote 26 But it has clearly reshaped the debate, with states adopting the rhetoric of public law in advocating for reform.Footnote 27

Yet for all this attention, the meaning and consequences of IIL remain poorly understood. Its doctrinal workings are, of course, expounded in countless treatises, monographs, and articles.Footnote 28 And the basic tension between investor protection and regulatory values is now well-known—thanks to the important contributions of the “public law school” of thought. But for all the pages written on BITs and ISDS, there has been very little theoretical consideration of the core private dimensions of a regime established for the protection of foreign property. As a result, major problems of fairness, efficiency, and equitable distribution have been missed. The private law account advanced here seeks to address this lacuna.

For all its significant implications for domestic public law and public values, IIL is at heart about regulating investments—which means property (real, personal, and intellectual), contracts, enterprises, and all sorts of equity interests in local business organizations. The main thing that investment treaties do is establish international law and institutions to discipline how states govern the private rights and interests of foreigners internally. In other words, IIL and ISDS regulate domestic private law. The goal, here, is to reexamine the investment treaty regime from a private law perspective—both on its own terms, and in how it interacts with private law at the national level.

A. International Investment Law as International Private Law

As categories, public and private law should not be segregated too neatly. The classical division understands public law as the law regulating interactions between individuals and the state (or other public authorities), and private law as that regulating relationships between private individuals. As has long been clear, however, these categories do not connote entirely distinct fields of law.Footnote 29 Wide areas of so-called private law regulate interactions between individuals and the state, such as takings law, the law of public contracts, and the regulation of corporations (including mandatory disclosures to regulators and capitalization requirements). Indeed, entire fields of law arguably live in the boundary, such as the law of patents.Footnote 30 Moreover, the state often acts as a commercial party in all kinds of private legal arrangements, from buying and selling property, to contracting with citizens and foreigners, to investing in private business organizations, joint ventures, and state-owned enterprises. IIL disciplines state action in exactly this border zone.Footnote 31 As such, it can be usefully and differently understood through both public and private law frames—both in terms of how far it accomplishes its goals of investment protection and promotion, and in terms of how it affects domestic legal institutions.

The claim, here, is that, whatever else it does, IIL creates surprisingly broad swathes of international private law. In extending their broad, open-textured standards of treatment to “assets of any kind,” investment treaties effectively set out international legal rules to govern property, contracts, corporate law, intellectual property, and many other private legal rights and interests. Their breadth has been further expanded and hardened through ISDS case law, touching on matters from: the scope and content of property rights; to the making, breaking, and content of contracts; to the contours of the corporate form. These rules materially affect the meaning of such covered private rights and interests, even if the latter originate in the national legal order. Private investors and states should factor them in ex ante in constructing their commercial relationships, and they will have a strong bearing on how alleged harms are compensated ex post. As a consequence, IIL also strongly affects the range of choices available to the state in how it regulates through internal private law.

To be clear, I do not seek to replace an essentializing public law theory with an equally dogmatic private one.Footnote 32 As a semantic matter, it is not especially important that IIL is described as either public law or private law, or as some kind of hybrid. What matters is where we focus in evaluating the regime. I deploy the concepts of public and private law here as ideal types—as analytical categories, the purpose of which is not classification in and of itself, but rather achieving a better understanding of the pressures and values implicated by regulating commercial interactions between private individuals and the state.Footnote 33 The private and public law frames serve to draw attention to the different facets involved. And there can be value in overlap, where these frames reveal discrete pathologies, and point to different pathways for reform.

Framing IIL in private law terms reveals tensions and pathologies on both sides of the tradeoff between the state's regulatory capacity and protecting investors to induce foreign direct investment. On the one hand, it illuminates how IIL constrains and distorts regulatory choices across a wide, and underappreciated, range of private legal fields. On the other hand, from this vantage point IIL and ISDS appear to work against the predictability and stability central to IIL's investment promotion goals. Yet, none of this is necessarily implied by the treaties as drafted. A more theoretically satisfying private law approach opens the way to better calibrating the wide range of relationships, interests, and values implicated by IIL and ISDS—with payoffs for interpreting extant treaties, and, more importantly, for future treaty design.

B. International Investment Law and National Private Law

The relationship between IIL and national private law has been mostly missed. Shifting focus, here, brings to light an underappreciated constriction of the state's regulatory policy space—one that has already proven more invasive than IIL's much feared strangulation of the state's ability to regulate health and environmental matters. Before turning to the jurisprudence, it is worth pausing to clarify terms. IIL relates to national law in three discrete, but partially overlapping ways. First, in a general sense, it disciplines the state, limiting its freedom as a matter of international law. Second, this can entail formally displacing national legal rules. Third, IIL can materially distort national law in a deeper functional sense—upsetting the logic of whole fields of private law.

IIL is clearly meant to discipline domestic law at the international level. Indeed, commitment is the investment treaty's core function—a legal promise by the state to refrain from certain actions with respect to foreigners in the hopes of attracting foreign direct investment. Such promises invariably include forbearance from arbitrary and discriminatory action, and generally some broader protections against losses associated with regulation. And ISDS gives these commitments teeth. Thus discipline, here, connotes international legal commitment in the most general sense—the state agrees to act (or not act) in certain ways, and can be held to account for failing to do so through compulsory arbitration and potentially large monetary awards.

But what happens where such disciplines prohibit acts authorized or required by national law—for example, by affording foreign investors more robust takings protections than would be available domestically? Certainly, investment treaties purport to take priority over conflicting national law. But the relationship is only deceptively simple.

At least in the context of ISDS, IIL formally displaces conflicting national legal rules. It is a basic principle that internal law cannot excuse the violation of an international legal obligation.Footnote 34 This does not mean, however, that the latter invalidates the former. Absent a special relationship of direct effect, the national law will remain in place unless the state removes the conflict internally.Footnote 35 But the state will be liable for any breach of the international obligation as a matter of international law. What makes IIL distinctive is that private individuals can enforce their international legal rights directly through ISDS, where IIL obligations take priority over conflicting national law. Taken together, IIL and ISDS thus meaningfully displace conflicting national legal rules at the international level. Furthermore, ISDS is highly enforceable, keying into multilateral treaties for enforcing arbitral awards across the globe.Footnote 36 Thus, ex ante, states and investors should understand IIL as creating justiciable and enforceable rules of substantive private law that supersede national law, and they should price its rules and institutions into any investments accordingly.

That international legal rules displace domestic law is not surprising in and of itself. What comes as a surprise is the sheer breadth of private legal rules arbitrators have read into brief, laconic investment treaties. As explored in the next Part, in applying a handful of standards relating to expropriation and fair and equitable treatment to an expansive range of covered investments, ISDS tribunals have read the treaties to displace a staggering range of national private law rules: from the scope of property rights; to the making, performance, and breaking of contracts; to the relations among corporate constituencies, including particularly the procedural rights of shareholders, and rules of agency and authority.

Moreover, IIL and ISDS distort fundamental principles of national private law. By this I mean something less formal than displacement, but more normatively charged. A rule of international law distorts national law when it interferes with the broader logic and functions of the domestic legal system. For example, a strong international expropriation standard will displace weaker domestic takings protections, without necessarily distorting national property law. But it is also possible that displacing certain keystone rules and principles can undercut the broader functions of property law—for example by blurring the foundational principle fixing the number and content of recognized property forms.

To the extent that investment treaties apply substantive and procedural rules to real and personal property, contracts, intellectual property, enterprises, stocks and shares, they create rules of international private law in each field. Naturally such rules would displace conflicting domestic rules,Footnote 37 though the scope and meaning of a conflict is often murky in private law.Footnote 38 More surprising are the range and scope of private law rules that tribunals have read into investment treaties, and thus the extent to which IIL implicitly invades domestic systems of private law. Most problematically, ISDS jurisprudence has gravitated toward (non-obvious) interpretations of IIL that effectively upend keystone private legal principles. Particularly with respect to contracts and corporations, the case law has distorted whole fields of national private law—mainly vis-à-vis foreigners, but with important spillovers for third parties as well. Such distortions undermine efficiency, fairness, equitable distribution, and other regulatory values—benefitting neither states nor investors as a class.

III. The Private Law Critique of IIL and ISDS

This Part turns to a critique of IIL and ISDS from a private law perspective. The following four sections reassess ISDS case law, each in relation to a discrete private legal regime. Section (A) casts property as the baseline comparator—the case where IIL and ISDS work more or less as expected, even if not entirely comfortably. By contrast, Section (B) highlights contract as the archetypal case of distortion. Here the investment treaty regime goes beyond merely displacing particular rules of national contract law, fundamentally distorting its logic and functions in the context of foreign direct investment. Section (C) examines corporate law as another instance of significant distortion. The case of corporate law further illustrates the robustness of the private law frame, by both elucidating and elaborating problems that have been debated thus far in isolation (such as shareholder suits for reflective loss) and illuminating additional unnoticed distortions (such as apparent authority). Lastly, Section (D) explores how intellectual property offers grounds for (very) cautious optimism, where the few cases decided to date have proven sensitive to the special features and tradeoffs of trademarks and patents vis-à-vis other forms of property.

The following case studies proceed in like fashion, moving from functional analysis to doctrinal critique. Each begins by setting out the core logic and functions of the private law regime in question. Each then examines how ISDS jurisprudence fares in relation to these functions, illustrating how the investment treaty regime has (or has not) distorted these discrete regimes of national private law in the context of foreign direct investment.

A. The Property Model of Investment

Investment treaties work reasonably well in relation to foreign property (in the strict sense). Treaty definitions of investment generally cover classical categories of real and personal property,Footnote 39 and their substantive and procedural guarantees apply straightforwardly to such assets. While IIL and ISDS do displace particular property rules, they not appear to fundamentally distort the logic of property law. The major outstanding question—of only passing interest here—is to what extent IIL protects foreign property relative to national policy and democratic choice.Footnote 40

As with all fields of private law, the law of property serves numerous functions. At the core are (1) an empowering function, providing for the creation and transfer of rights in rem; (2) a delimiting function, articulating the types and scope of property rights, against others and against the state; and, implicit in the latter, (3) a deep regulatory function, in enshrining and balancing national values in the design of particular property forms. A signal feature of property law in all jurisdictions, as opposed to contract, is that the law recognizes only a handful of property forms, each comprising a different bundle of rights (such as rights of use or exclusion) in the service of some particular mix of interests and values.Footnote 41 This principle of numerus clausus (“the number is closed”) pervades all aspects of property law, channeling transactions and interactions with property into relatively rigid lanes. Property law is everywhere marked by a logic of rigid standardization—in contrast to the logic of contract, which prioritizes choice and customization.Footnote 42

Property theorists give varying accounts of the numerus clausus principle, and thus property's logic of standardization. For law and economics scholars, the key lies in the fact that property rights are held in rem (inhering in the asset), as opposed to contract rights which are in personam (inhering in only those persons party to the contract). This means that, unlike contract rights, which are opposable only to contracting parties, property rights are good against the world.Footnote 43 Moreover, property rights “run[] with the asset.”Footnote 44 These features mean that property rights create high information costs—not only for owners and potential buyers, but for third parties more generally. As Merrill and Smith explain, “when property rights are created, third parties must expend time and resources to determine the attributes of these rights, both to avoid violating them and to acquire them.”Footnote 45 If present holders were free to carve up their holdings in any way, shape, or form, future buyers, as well as other market participants and third parties, would face inordinate diligence costs in apprising themselves of the contents of any parcel.Footnote 46 The logic of standardization, then, is to reduce the measurementFootnote 47 and verificationFootnote 48 costs inherent in property rights by strictly limiting the available types of rights in rem. All property systems entail a relatively limited, manageable, and knowable number of property forms, into which the law will funnel owners’ attempts at customization.

Pluralists explain the logic of standardization differently, usefully highlighting important functions of property law beyond efficiency.Footnote 49 In explaining the pervasive logic of standardization, Davidson emphasizes the wide variation in the particular contents of the forms across different societies, and over time.Footnote 50 While acknowledging the efficiency functions of standardization in general, he argues that this cannot explain the diversity in which bundles of rights national systems sanctify as property forms. This variation reveals a regulatory function of standardization—the content of the forms reflects policy choices in the service of particular societal values, ranging from distribution and fairness to environmental concerns.Footnote 51

The bottom line is that the logic of property is, everywhere, one of standardization. National laws recognize a limited number of property forms. Each form entails some bundle of exclusive rights, against other private actors (e.g. trespass or nuisance rules), and rights against the state (e.g. protections from expropriation or regulatory takings). And the precise mix reflects each society's regulatory and democratic choices.

IIL does not substantially distort the logic of property. Investment treaties do displace particular property rules vis-à-vis foreigners, and may strongly affect the relative values enshrined in national law—usually by requiring greater protection of foreign property and leaving less room for state regulation. Thus, they can augment national property forms. But IIL leaves the principle of standardization intact, and it generally relies on national law to define the basic contours of property's different forms.Footnote 52

Take real property as an example. A foreign investor's ownership rights in land originate in the domestic law of the host state. IIL does not purport to create property rights.Footnote 53 But an investment treaty does supplement (or displace) the bundle of domestic rights associated with an investor's parcel via specific protections against state action. Typical substantive commitments include strong protections against expropriation, fair and equitable treatment (including some protection of investor expectations), and non-discrimination—all enforceable through ISDS. These guarantees are typically more robust than their domestic analogues, but still sit well with the deep logic and functions of national property law. Real property is still created, registered, and transferred as before, and entails essentially the same bundle of rights—albeit supplemented, for foreign investors, with additional protections against state action.

Being largely modeled on how developed countries protect property rights, the basic structure of investment treaties more or less mirrors how national law protects private property from state action in market economies. For typical market-oriented states, investment treaties may well affect the level of property protection due to foreigners. But they do not drastically reshape the nature of property protection.Footnote 54 The same cannot necessarily be said for all non-market economies, whose internal law may be less sanguine about private property. In such cases, investment treaties may significantly transform the meaning and function property law for foreigner investors. But here, at least, radical change in the protection of private property is largely the point.Footnote 55

The property right enshrined in IIL and ISDS is by no means beyond reproach. Every property regime, national or international, grapples with an intractable tension between private property and government regulation.Footnote 56 However, the extent of property protection required by investment treaties is left largely undecided by their text—leaving the scope of broad and open-textured guarantees like fair and equitable treatment largely up to arbitral interpretation. Some argue that tribunals occasionally go too far and too fast toward property absolutism.Footnote 57 The objection is that ISDS has tended to strike a balance weighted too heavily in favor of investor property, at the expense of host state regulatory autonomy—though there are signs that the tide is turning.Footnote 58 But whether or not the appropriate level of property protection is too capital-friendly, IIL does not appear to distort the basic functions of domestic (Western-style) property law: providing for legal ownership through particular, verifiable bundles of rights in rem,Footnote 59 and regulating these bundles’ number, content, and outer bounds.Footnote 60

From a private law perspective, then, the criticism of how IIL relates to classical property forms is really about values more than categories.Footnote 61 At the margins, it may be debatable whether IIL paves over conceptual nuance in displacing domestic property rules in particular jurisdictions and thereby increases uncertainty and information costs regarding the full meaning and value of foreign-owned property rights. But most criticisms in this vein reduce to value-based concerns about how far investor property should be protected. It is certainly possible that ISDS could develop in ways that distort core principles in the future, for example by blurring the numerus clausus such that limitations in particular national property forms are cast aside, or by drawing impermissible analogies to other national systems about the balance of rights and values embedded in similar forms.Footnote 62 It is also true that, pushed far enough, expanding the level of property protection may of itself erode the regulatory functions of national property law beyond recognition.Footnote 63 But for now such concerns remain speculative. IIL may impose overly strong property protections on states. But it does not seem to fundamentally denature the logic of property. By contrast, deeply distortive category problems arise where IIL and ISDS grapple with other types of investment—and other fields of private law.

B. Contracts as Investments

Investment treaties typically cover contracts within the definition of investment.Footnote 64 As with property, in extending their substantive protections to contracts, these treaties effectively generate rules of international contract law. Ex ante, both contracting states and investors should view any applicable treaty norms as part of the package of background legal rules framing all contractual negotiations. Here, however, IIL and ISDS do not just supplement or displace particular domestic rules. Investment law further distorts the basic logic of contract, undermining key functions of national contract law.

In contrast to property, the logic of contract law everywhere is one of choice—flexibility and customization instead of rigid standardization.Footnote 65 National contract law does standardize, providing an edifice of background terms that augment party choices. But a key difference between property and contract is that, with the latter, the background rules are mostly optional. While property law is typically mandatory, the law of contracts is mostly comprised of mere default rules. National laws of contracts do impose some rigid rules.Footnote 66 But in general contract law prioritizes the choices of private persons, while property law prioritizes the choices of the state.

Here again, it helps to start from a functional perspective. Contract law has at least four key functions: (1) empowering private parties to create legally enforceable agreements on the terms they prefer; (2) setting rules for interpreting contracts; (3) filling gaps in incomplete contracts; and (4) regulating the outer bounds of acceptable bargaining behavior and outcomes.Footnote 67 The notion of party choice pervades these functions, but not blindly. Where parties have not chosen or their choices are unclear, the state provides terms that it deems appropriate—either in hopes of capturing what most parties would have wanted (majoritarian defaults),Footnote 68 or in the service of other values (as with penalty defaults).Footnote 69 In rare cases, the state will intervene even where the parties have chosen—regulating choice via sticky defaults and mandatory rules and, at the limit, through rules on contract formation and validity.

IIL and ISDS distort the logic and functions of contract law from both sides—by constraining parties’ ability to choose, and by constraining the state's capacity to regulate choice. I first show how IIL and ISDS undercut contract law's basic logic of customization, distorting both its empowering and gap-filling functions with costs for efficiency and autonomy. I then explore the mirror-image problem, where ISDS tribunals water down national mandatory rules that serve values outside of contractual efficiency—such as contract formation rules meant to preserve government transparency and anti-corruption norms. In so doing, the case law further distorts the regulatory functions of contract law.

1. Implied terms and the logic of choice

No legal system expects parties to negotiate every aspect of a contract. All laws of contract provide ready-made implied terms to supplement agreements—ranging from technical matters which parties often do not discuss, like damages, defenses, and forum selection, to bases of substantive obligation (such as warranties)Footnote 70 and even price.Footnote 71 Parties can and do expressly negotiate such terms—all of which affect price and risk allocation. But parties need not negotiate everything, every time. By providing off-the-rack background rules, contract law allows parties to avoid reinventing the wheel from deal to deal. These implied terms are usually optionalmere defaults, around which parties may contract to pursue joint goals as they see fit. Prioritizing party choice serves a wide range of values, from autonomy, to efficiency, to community.Footnote 72

Implied terms differ dramatically across national systems. As with property forms, their content is fundamentally a regulatory question about which values to prioritize and how much to prioritize them. In the United States, for example, contract law typically sets defaults on a majoritarian basis, reflecting the courts’ (or legislatures’) best guess at what contracting parties would have wanted ex ante, had they considered the issue.Footnote 73 But myriad other approaches are possible.Footnote 74 What is common everywhere is that parties may generally bargain around these rules to secure the mix of goods, incentives, and values they see fit.

This is not to say that national laws of contract are only comprised of default rules—or that contracts are completely customizable. The flexibility of any particular background rule is itself a policy choice, and nations vary widely in exactly where and why they introduce rigidity into the law of contracts.Footnote 75 Like content, rigidity reflects its own axis of regulatory values, such as how much faith to place in markets, how much to prioritize individual choice, and the state's proper role in creating the conditions for relational equality in private legal transactions.Footnote 76 Still, for the most part, contract law seeks to empower parties to commit to one another on terms that they deem appropriate.Footnote 77 IIL and ISDS turn this logic on its head.

To capture the problem, it is important to first see clearly how and why national contract law limits choice at the margins. Choice can be limited completely through mandatory rules. But choice can also be constrained more provisionally through “sticky defaults”—rules that parties may contract around, but only through observing certain formalities (by requiring a clear statement, special contractual language, or even a separate signed writing).Footnote 78 Both kinds of constraints can be grounded in values internal to the logic of contract, or on the basis of external values. The first type of justification considers sticky defaults and mandatory rules appropriate where they serve to enhance choice, by putting the parties on equal footing or by correcting for market failures.Footnote 79 These kinds of constraints serve to establish the rules of the game, protect basic fairness among contracting parties, and the like. For example, some sticky defaults correct information asymmetries, by requiring that opt-outs employ special language that forces better informed parties to reveal potentially hidden information to less well-informed parties—like the scope of their default rights.Footnote 80 A second type of justification for constraining choice relies on extrinsic values, such as mandatory rules precluding contracts of enslavement or contracts to commit a crime, mandatory and/or sticky protections for workers, or limitations on one government's ability to tie the hands of a future government through contracts with private parties.

Contract law thus involves two broad, and conceptually discrete, regulatory questions: (1) how to set the content of the background rules, and (2) how flexible or rigid to make them. National laws vary on both, reflecting different priorities and values. But the general spirit always lies in prioritizing the choices of particular contracting parties rather than the general default choices erected by the state. IIL and ISDS muddy the waters for both questions.

In extending to contracts, IIL obviously affects domestic contract rules. But unlike with property, it is not at all obvious what kind of effect investment treaties ought to have on a covered contract. Investment treaties leave unclear both (1) the scope and content of treaty rules applicable to contracts, and, crucially, (2) the way in which such rules interact with contracts (as defaults, mandatory rules, or something in between).

ISDS tribunals have consistently read investment treaties as covering a surprisingly broad scope of contractual matters, ranging from substantive obligations, to defenses, damages, and forum selection terms. All tribunals assume, sensibly, that, whatever their scope, investment treaties displace conflicting background rules in the law of the contract. However, the cases have been all over the map on the core question of choice, with some tribunals viewing treaty rules as mandatory, others viewing the same rules as sticky defaults, and still others viewing them as fully customizable. Such uncertainty is itself a serious problem for all contracting parties ex ante. Moreover, the jurisprudence has tended to drift in the wrong direction, prioritizing treaty over contract, and conflating the logic of contract with that of property. Examples from the case law on three kinds of treaty terms suffice to illustrate the problem: (a) fair and equitable treatment, (b) damages, and (c) forum selection.Footnote 81

a. Fair and Equitable Treatment: Stabilization and Expectations

Fair and equitable treatment is one of the most common investment treaty standards, and among the most controversial. It is also the standard most commonly invoked by investors, and often proves outcome determinative.Footnote 82 In most treaties the standard is stated laconically. The thorniest point of contention is whether the requirement of fair and equitable treatment protects an investor's “legitimate expectations,” and to what extent that entails compensation for losses arising out of regulatory change—i.e., an implied “stabilization” clause, in contracts terminology.Footnote 83 Most tribunals accept that fair and equitable treatment requires protecting investor expectations to some degree.Footnote 84 Of interest here is a second order question: whether (and how) states and investors can contract around the treaty rule. This question arises in every ISDS arbitration involving contracts. However, the cases rarely examine it explicitly, necessitating some reading between the lines.

The Argentine Gas cases provide the archetypal mandatory approach, resolving the issue implicitly and formalistically.Footnote 85 In Sempra, Enron, and CMS, the tribunals read fair and equitable treatment as entailing broad stabilization requirements, applicable to investments arising out of contracts as to any other investment.Footnote 86 Each tribunal assumed that treaty claims are completely independent from contract claims, and found that its jurisdiction was limited to the former.Footnote 87 On this formalistic view, it does not matter if the investment triggering treaty protection is property, contract, or anything else; once triggered, fair and equitable treatment always demands the same level of treatment. The scope and meaning of treaty rights turn not at all on the content of the underlying contract and are unaffected by anything the contract says about the scope of stabilization, or even waiver of treaty rights.

From the perspective of contract law and theory, the reasoning of the Argentine Gas cases is misleading. The formalistic separation of treaty and contract only serves to mask what it implies—that, far from being independent, any immutable treaty provision triggered by a contract-based investment simply rewrites the deal struck by the parties by inserting a new, effectively mandatory term.Footnote 88 On this view, the investment treaty effectively displaces any conflicting rules of national contract law with rigid international standards. If an investment contract always triggers immutable treaty protections then, ex ante, states and investors must assume that IIL will apply whatever they choose to put in the contract—and they must price it in accordingly, whether or not it is efficient. Thus, on these tribunals’ interpretation of fair and equitable treatment, states and investors would always be stuck with an implied stabilization clause, however extremely that affects price—or even the parties’ willingness to contract—and whether or not such a provision is important to the investor.Footnote 89

Although most tribunals follow the Argentine Gas cases in assuming the rigidity of substantive treaty standards, a handful of decisions have hinted at more flexible approaches. In Parkerings v. Lithuania, the tribunal implicitly viewed fair and equitable treatment as a mere default rule. First, it viewed the standard more minimally than the Argentine Gas cases.Footnote 90 However, it considered that states and investors are free to ratchet up the level of protection that fair and equitable treatment would entail by negotiating for a stabilization clause in the contract.Footnote 91 In other words, treaty and contract cannot be neatly separated, and the parties can control the scope of fair and equitable treatment. Parkerings and decisions like it differ markedly from the Argentine Gas cases in treating fair and equitable treatment as a mere default whose scope can be enlarged (and, arguably, reduced or waived) by agreement.Footnote 92

MNSS v. Montenegro provides yet a third option—that fair and equitable treatment (and other treaty standards) are defaults, but only very sticky ones.Footnote 93 To contract around them, states and investors must use exceptionally clear language. The privatization agreement in MNSS included a clause waiving BIT and other international legal rights by name—though it was somewhat murky about how far it disclaimed them.Footnote 94 In principle, the tribunal considered that states and investors could contract around fair and equitable treatment, finding that “investors may waive the rights conferred to them by treaty provided [the] waivers are explicit and freely entered into. . . .”Footnote 95 And it was satisfied that this contract's express and specific opt-out sufficiently demonstrated a mutual intention to contract around the treaty. The tribunal thus gave effect to the disclaimer, but read it narrowly, apparently operating under an unstated presumption against waiver.Footnote 96 Moreover, the tribunal suggested that the treaty might not be entirely optional, indicating opaquely that it might not have given effect to a waiver that contravened the “public purpose” pursued by the BIT.Footnote 97

b. Forum Selection

Most modern investment treaties empower investors to compel host states into ISDS. But BITs and free trade agreements (FTAs) generally do not elaborate on whether their procedural rights turn on the type of investment at issue. Thus, in relation to contracts, any applicable investment treaty will provide a clear background term on forum selection. Left completely unclear is what happens if the contract waives such rights via an exclusive forum selection clause—designating domestic courts or another arbitral mechanism.

Conflicts between treaty and contractual forum selection clauses occur frequently in ISDS. Here too, tribunals have gone in every possible direction. For some, ISDS is a mandatory procedural right, while for others it is just another default with varying levels of stickiness.

SGS v. Paraguay reflects the mandatory view.Footnote 98 Like the Argentine Gas cases, the tribunal accepted the notion that investment treaty claims and contract claims must be cleanly separated.Footnote 99 The relevant BIT included an umbrella clause, purporting to convert a breach of an investment contract into a treaty breach. In the tribunal's view, a contract covered by such a clause would create two separate tracks of rights—a set of purely contractual rights, and a distinct set of treaty rights. The parties can disclaim ISDS for the former by exclusively selecting domestic courts in the contract. But they cannot waive ISDS for breach of treaty rights, even if the latter were generated by the same contract via the umbrella clause. Other tribunals have similarly disregarded contractual exclusive forum selection clauses in fair and equitable treatment and expropriation cases.Footnote 100

Several cases have gone the other way, on markedly similar facts, viewing ISDS as a waivable default. The tribunals in SGS v. Philippines and BIVAC v. Paraguay found that treaty and contract could not be neatly separated.Footnote 101 They held that the treaty cannot alter the bargain struck between the contracting parties. An exclusive forum selection clause opting to resolve all disputes in local courts is obviously part of that deal, presumably bought and paid for ex ante. Each tribunal thus held that breach could only be authoritatively determined by the contractually chosen forum, and thus any umbrella clause claims would be inadmissible prior to an authoritative finding of breach by a local court. Other tribunals have followed this default approach outside of the umbrella clause context.Footnote 102

Still other decisions have viewed ISDS as a sticky default, which states and investors may waive by contract, but only by observing certain formalities—such as by clear statement, or use of magic words. In Aguas del Tunari, the tribunal refused to “read an ambiguous clause as an implicit waiver of [International Centre for Settlement of Investment Disputes (ICSID)] jurisdiction,” adding that “silence as to the question is not sufficient.”Footnote 103 The tribunal in Crystallex went further, finding that “any such waiver would have to be formulated in clear and specific terms,”Footnote 104 and that waiver “is never to be lightly admitted as it requires knowledge and intent of forgoing a right, a conduct rather unusual in economic transactions.”Footnote 105 Here the tribunal rejected an exclusive forum selection clause which expressly required that all disputes be resolved in Venezuelan court.Footnote 106 Though this clause surely reveals that the parties were aware of the scope of their procedural rights under the contract, it might not indicate that the investor knew that it was giving up a treaty right to ISDS. The tribunal suggested, without elaboration, that to be effective such a waiver would need to mention the BIT or ISDS by name.Footnote 107 Reading between the lines, the justification for this approach may have been information-forcing—to protect investors who might not be aware of their rights (and leverage) under an investment treaty ex ante.Footnote 108

c. Damages

All laws of contract include implied damages rules—standards of recovery, such as expectancy, reliance, and restitution, as well as myriad corollary technical rules for valuation. National damages rules are typically defaults, enabling the parties—who are typically best equipped to allocate risk and price efficiently—to negotiate the scope of future recovery as they see fit. Contract law may impose limits, especially to police clauses imposing disproportionate, punitive, or otherwise unconscionable damages. But the parties retain wide latitude to negotiate over future recovery, through liquidated damages provisions, damages caps, and so on. The same is true of government contracts, though here national law often provides for weaker damages provisions by default,Footnote 109 and may make contracting around such defaults more difficult.Footnote 110 The rationale is typically an entrenchment concern about chilling regulatory autonomy—a worry that one government might tie the hands of future governments through privatization.Footnote 111

Investment treaties say very little about damages. They typically provide no general damages rule applicable across their provisions.Footnote 112 Nor do they differentiate among investments for purposes of measuring damages. ISDS tribunals thus typically draw on general international law damages principles and apply them to all types of investments—usually landing on “fair market value” as the applicable measure of compensation.Footnote 113 This entails measuring the present value of the asset, taking into account its capacity to generate income over time.Footnote 114 For contracts, fair market value is typically taken to entail expectation damages.Footnote 115 Tribunals implicitly invoke fair market value as a double default—an implied expectation damages rule in general international law, to be read into the “incomplete” investment treaty absent any special provision on damages, and thereby read into any investment contract to which the treaty applies.Footnote 116 But, here again, tribunals have divided over whether fair market value is negotiable or mandatory.

Several tribunals have simply assumed that international law damages cannot be abrogated by contract, as in the Argentine Gas casesFootnote 117 and the more recent ExxonMobil v. Venezuela.Footnote 118 For the former, the assumption followed from the strict separation of treaty and contract, discussed above. The latter relied on a different but equally inapposite formalism, finding that treaty rigidity followed from the principle that internal law cannot excuse a violation of international law.Footnote 119 As a result, the tribunal held that it could not give effect to potentially limiting compensation provisions in the underlying concession contract.

These tribunals’ explanations are questionable as a matter of both law and economics. First, as a technical matter, a contractual limitation on damages reflects the parties’ choice to limit the scope of their mutual obligations ex ante—not an excuse for breach ex post, as posited by ExxonMobil. There is no reason that international law cannot provide private parties with negotiable default terms—as does the Convention on the International Sale of Goods (CISG).Footnote 120 Second, even under fair market value analysis, any compensation clause in the contract would clearly affect the market value of the investment, and cannot be ignored. As Abi-Saab asks rhetorically, in the related (ongoing) ConocoPhillips case: “how can any homo economicus exercising rational choice as a ‘willing buyer’ … calculate the price he would be willing to pay, without factoring in … the terms of the compensation clauses of the Agreements?”Footnote 121 To ignore contractual limitations on damages effectively implies that fair market value imposes a mandatory rule, providing for full expectation damages, whatever the parties have agreed as between themselves. This approach inexplicably constrains parties’ ability to bargain over damages in allocating contractual risk ex ante.

Other tribunals have understood treaty damages as defaults of varying flexibility. Most spectacularly, Venezuela succeeded in having the ExxonMobil Award abrogated on precisely this point (for failure to state reasons). The ad hoc annulment committee rightly dismissed as a straw man the tribunal's incantation that internal law cannot excuse a breach of international law,Footnote 122 and found that the tribunal failed to otherwise explain ignoring the contractual compensation clause.Footnote 123 The committee stressed that the unjustified implication of the tribunal's approach was to boot-strap fair market value, an international law standard not found in the BIT, into an effectively mandatory rule for all contracts covered by the treaty.Footnote 124 The committee strongly questioned whether the BIT could reasonably be interpreted to prevent parties from contracting around treaty damages, but, given its limited mandate, stopped short of expounding the precise relationship between treaty and contract. With less fanfare, the tribunal in Siag also appeared to view fair market value as a mere default, simply taking contractual compensation clauses into account in assessing damages.Footnote 125 Still other tribunals, like Kardassopoulos, have understood fair market value as a sticky default, with a strong presumption against opt-out, similar to MNSS and Crystallex.Footnote 126

d. Distorting the Logic of Choice

In their application to investment contracts, investment treaties establish rules of international contract law. However, the treaties are invariably silent about how their standards relate to contractual choice. This second order question arises in every ISDS case involving contracts. Yet the cases rarely engage with this issue directly, let alone with the policy matters at stake, generally proceeding on the basis of mere assumptions.Footnote 127 Moreover, tribunals have resolved the treaty/contract relationship in all possible ways. Most tend to assume that investment treaty rules are effectively mandatory, or at least as very sticky defaults. Only a few have viewed IIL as presumptively optional, though this is the norm with background rules at national law and would generally be the better rule here as well.

In the case of contracts, then, IIL and ISDS displace domestic law in two different ways. First, investment treaties clearly displace conflicting national background rules, supplanting domestic implied terms with international ones. This form of displacement is not especially problematic, although it is perhaps startling how broad a range of implied terms have been read into investment treaties. However, under the approach of most tribunals, investment treaties displace national law in another, more troubling way—by supplanting the express choices of the parties to particular contracts, either through mandatory terms or very sticky defaults. This turns the logic of contract upside down.

The investment treaty regime thus distorts national contract law in two discrete ways. First, absent any mechanism for systematizing the jurisprudence, the sheer variation in approaches creates acute uncertainty. This is a second-order problem, sharper than the typical critique of ISDS inconsistency. As is often noted, states and investors always grapple with potentially inconsistent arbitral interpretations of substantive standards of treatmentFootnote 128—a real problem, but not one altogether avoidable in any legal system. One might imagine that states and investors could respond to such uncertainty ex ante, by contracting for what they consider really important. Uncertainty cannot be completely avoided, but it can be mitigated. Here, however, the second-order uncertainty problem exerts its sting. Given the treaty/contract jurisprudence, states and investors cannot know whether their ex ante attempts to define the scope of their obligations through contract will be given effect at ISDS ex post. This leaves the meaning of contracts between foreign investors and states or state-owned enterprises in substantial doubt. All parties will have to take risks associated with such uncertainty into account ex ante, affecting price and potentially dampening the parties’ incentives to contract—precisely the opposite of what investment treaties set out to achieve.

Second, the ISDS jurisprudence tends to gravitate in the wrong direction, toward making treaty rules mandatory for covered contracts. Quite apart from the uncertainty problem, this is a bad rule, needlessly inefficient and likely unjust—even assuming perfect rationality of states and investors. In law and economics (or Coasean) terms, under ideal market conditions (perfect rationality and low transaction costs), the content of investment treaty rules should not matter, because states and investors would bargain in their shadow to achieve an efficient result.Footnote 129 The market would push them to allocate resources efficiently. But even in ideal theory, this proposition only holds if the parties are free to negotiate around the law—meaning the background rules are mere defaults. If the parties are stuck with the background rules, then their content matters a great deal, and will likely prove inefficient under many constellations of market conditions. In other words, it is much more likely that the parties to an investment contract will be able to bargain to an efficient result, given their own needs, than it is that the states parties to an investment treaty will be able to predict the most efficient contract terms, across a range of issues, for all contracts to which the treaty applies.

Of course, there is little reason to assume perfect rationality in transnational government contracting. In practice, the mandatory approach is likely to prove not only inefficient, but quite unjust. It is not safe to assume that state officials and agents of state-owned entities charged with negotiating contracts will be aware of the contents of IIL and ISDS jurisprudence—nor that anything outside the agreed law of the contract will govern whether their chosen contractual terms are effective. This is especially so for developing countries, with smaller legal staffs and less resources available for due diligence.Footnote 130 Given that investment treaty standards will be typically more favorable to investors than either the domestic contract laws or the particular contractual choices that they displace, states will likely find themselves on the wrong end of surprise claims arising out of investment contracts—with unexpected legal exposure measured in millions or billions of dollars. This is not to say that ignorance of the law should be an excuse. The point is rather that a rigid approach to the treaty/contract problem will be more likely to lead to perverse outcomes—and this should be taken into account in thinking through treaty design and interpretation.

The optimal approach for IIL would (usually) be to privilege contractual arrangements over background treaty rules.Footnote 131 The treaty/contract problem is not zero-sum. Although states and investors have different interests and values at stake, both sides usually stand to benefit from the freedom to negotiate around treaty rules. There may be good reason to make specific rules stickier.Footnote 132 But given the costs, this should be justified on a case-by-case basis, in terms of the values, incentives, and risks implicated by the particular treaty rule in question—not on the basis of broad formalisms about the relationships between treaty and contract, or international law and domestic law.Footnote 133 Generally prioritizing party choice is not only optimal from the economic standpoint—it also empowers states to secure their future regulatory autonomy, by controlling for risk through limitations on damages, force majeure clauses, and so on. Though investment treaties protect foreign investors’ contract rights, it makes little sense to bar states and investors from contracting around treaty terms at arm's length. A contract represents a bargain struck by the parties; if the goal of the treaty is to protect the bargain as struck ex ante, then it should not be taken as license to rewrite the deal ex post.

2. Contract Formation and Regulation

Not everything in contract law is about facilitating choice. All laws of contract limit party autonomy in order to make choice itself more meaningful—through laying out rules of the game (basic formalities for formation), policing the bargaining process (e.g. mandatory fraud and duress doctrines), pushing parties to share certain kinds of information, and so on.Footnote 134 National contract law also limits some choices in the service of extrinsic values, typically through mandatory rules—for example, by policing distribution and abuse at the margins through unconscionability and good faith doctrines, invalidating contracts to commit a crime, and imposing limits on government contracting to safeguard public administration and democratic choice.Footnote 135 All this comprises a core regulatory function of contract law—the state must address these matters if it is to make contract law effective, and to safeguard other community values from the market. However, investment treaties diminish the state's capacity to regulate the limits of contractual freedom. Not only do IIL and ISDS inefficiently limit party choice (without good reason); they also constrain how the state uses contract law to limit choice in the service of other national values.

The recent award in Bankswitch v. Ghana amply demonstrates how IIL and ISDS can distort the regulatory functions of contract law in the context of anti-corruption norms. The Ghanaian Constitution provides that any “international business or economic transaction,” including contracts between the government and foreign investors, can only come into effect after parliamentary approval.Footnote 136 The Constitution limits the executive's ability to unilaterally contract with foreigners in order to bolster transparency and accountability in a context where corruption is rife and effects on the public purse can be dramatic. The rule manages agency costs in government (i.e., the risk of executive self-dealing) by putting both Ghanaian officials and foreign investors on notice that government contracts require legislative approval. In Bankswitch, the investor contracted with the government to develop software for Ghanaian customs authorities, and invested heavily in the project over three years. It relied on assurances that the contract was valid by various government officials (including the attorney general) even absent parliamentary approval.Footnote 137 The tribunal agreed with Ghana that the alleged contract was subject to the constitutional formation requirements, which all agreed were not satisfied. Nevertheless, the tribunal found the contract valid under a lenient promissory estoppel rule, which was supposedly grounded in customary international lawFootnote 138—displacing the mandatory Ghanaian formation rule, and eroding the state's ability to regulate government corruption.

Bankswitch did not involve an investment treaty. Rather, it arose out of an investment contract between Bankswitch and Ghana, under Ghanaian law, providing for ISDS through arbitration under UN Commission on International Trade Law (UNCITRAL) rules.Footnote 139 However the tribunal determined that general international law applied to the contract, including aspects of IIL, and that it could rely on ISDS case law in fleshing out both the contract's terms and the conditions for valid contract formation. First, the tribunal implied that customary international law might apply to the contract simply in light of its international nature.Footnote 140 But in any case, it held that custom would enter the picture as a convoluted triple default. The contract was governed only by Ghanaian law, and did not expressly incorporate international law. Nor does Ghanaian law expressly incorporate international law. Amazingly, however, the tribunal found that “Ghana, as a former British Colony, is a common law country, and principles of English common law are generally applied in Ghana as highly persuasive (if not binding) authority,” and that it could apply such English common law principles as were not expressly displaced by Ghanaian statute or binding case law.Footnote 141 Since English common law directly incorporates customary international law into domestic law, and since Ghanaian law says nothing on the subject, the tribunal found the English “doctrine of incorporation” implicitly applicable in Ghana. In this way, the tribunal drew on customary international law and ISDS case law to read an implied doctrine of promissory estoppel into Ghanaian law.Footnote 142 Thus, in the tribunal's view, an international contract governed by Ghanaian law, but invalid under that law, could be given effect under a theory of contract formation by estoppel derived from international law—even if it flatly contradicts constitutional requirements.Footnote 143

Finding the conditions for promissory estoppel satisfied, the tribunal enforced the contract, and ultimately found Ghana in breach.Footnote 144 The problem is that this approach entirely upends the constitutional anti-corruption provision. Article 181(5) is meant to check government action—to mitigate agency costs associated with corruption in the executive branch, by precluding officials from executing large-scale international contracts without parliamentary oversight. Allowing these same officials to vitiate the constraints on their action merely by making representations to the investor makes the intended constitutional constraint effectively optional. The tribunal's approach not only displaces national constraints on contract formation, but further distorts the state's capacity to regulate government corruption at the constitutional level.Footnote 145

3. Distorting the Logic of Contract

Including contracts in the definition of investment effectively transforms IIL into a rudimentary, yet broad, law of contracts—governing agreements between states and foreign investors on pivotal issues, from implied terms to rules on formation. However, this emerging international law of contracts has developed sporadically, irregularly, and inconsistently through ISDS, due in part to a tendency among tribunals to confuse the logics of contract and property.

As a result, it remains uncertain whether contracting parties should understand background treaty norms as defaults, sticky defaults, or mandatory terms—leaving the meaning of their contracts under a cloud of doubt. Such uncertainty is already highly inefficient ex ante, and unfair insofar as it leads to undue (and costly) surprise ex post. Further, to the extent tribunals tend toward viewing treaty provisions as mandatory, the jurisprudence has further undercut states’ and investors’ capacity to bargain. IIL and ISDS thus distort the empowering and gap-filling functions of national contract law for no good reason. At the same time, IIL and ISDS can distort the regulatory function of national contract law, by providing an end run around domestic constraints on bargaining.

Thus, in sum, the investment treaty regime distorts national contract law from both ends. On the one hand, it distorts contract's logic of customization by imposing far-ranging rigid terms on states and investors—constraining their ability to bargain to efficient outcomes, and, in so doing, limiting the state's ability to control the scope of its liability. On the other hand, ISDS also stands in the way of the state's attempts to constrain contracts in the service of extrinsic regulatory values.

C. Corporate Law and the Corporate Form in ISDS

A similarly problematic dynamic arises between investment law and corporate law. As with contracts, IIL and ISDS erect rules of international corporate law, with a surprising and textually non-obvious scope. In certain key instances, they subvert keystone principles of national corporate law, and thereby distort central functions of the corporate form. These distortions undercut efficiency, fairness, and equitable distribution, affecting not only host states, but also all corporate constituencies—including insiders (shareholders and management) and outsiders (creditors and third parties), wherever they reside.

Here again the problem starts with the definition of investment. Investment treaties expressly protect both natural and legal persons. Corporations thus enjoy protection as investors in their own right where their assets qualify as covered investments. But the definition of investment in most BITs and FTAs also includes stocks and shares, meaning that shareholders in a locally incorporated company also qualify as covered investors. This extends beyond controlling stakes, to minority shares and even indirect equity—meaning shares in an enterprise held through intermediary companies.Footnote 146 The rationale seems to be that host states often require (or encourage) foreigners to invest through a local entity, in hopes of generating benefits for local development (jobs, transfer of know-how, etc.). As a national of the host state, that company would not be covered by the typical investment treaty. But by including stocks and shares, the treaties cover foreigners investing in the local entity.Footnote 147 As with contracts, the problem here is that investment treaties tend not to specify how their provisions apply to shareholders, leaving unanswered substantial questions about differentiation and fit. Left to interpret these matters, ISDS tribunals have tended toward positions that distort central principles and functions of domestic corporate law—in both host and home states.Footnote 148

The business corporation (or company) is the most common vehicle for the large scale investment projects at issue in ISDS.Footnote 149 Across all legal systems, the corporate form exhibits the same core characteristics: (1) separate legal personality; (2) limited shareholder liability; (3) transferable shares; (4) centralized management; and (5) shared investor ownership.Footnote 150 Together, these interrelated features provide a streamlined and efficient vehicle for mobilizing capital at scale—one which is “uniquely effective at minimizing coordination costs.”Footnote 151 The primary function of corporate law everywhere is thus to empower private parties to organize their businesses through this uniquely efficient legal form.Footnote 152 Selection of the corporate form, in turn, signals the applicability of well-known basic rules, imparting substantial expectations among corporate insiders (shareholders and management), and outside constituencies (creditors, governments, and publics).Footnote 153

The second key function of corporate law is regulatory. Despite its merits, the corporate form tends to create serious agency problems (or conflicts of interest): between shareholders and managers; between controlling and minority shareholders; and between shareholders and outside constituencies (especially creditors).Footnote 154 These problems largely arise out of the same features that give the corporate form its distinct value. The bulk of corporate law in all jurisdictions is dedicated to mitigating these conflicts to “reduc[e] the ongoing costs of organizing business through the corporate form.”Footnote 155 Importantly, however, there is no single blueprint; national systems of corporate law differ substantially in which legal strategies they adopt to manage the relevant tradeoffs, reflecting substantial differences in values and priorities.Footnote 156

IIL and ISDS tend to upset both the empowering and regulatory functions of corporate law by distorting national legal arrangements in underappreciated ways. To illustrate this problem, I focus on just one of the corporation's hallmark features: separate legal personality. However, it will be clear that IIL affects its other characteristics as well.

Separate legal personality is a sine qua non of the corporate form. It allows the “firm to serve [a] coordinating role by operating as a single contracting party that is distinct from the various individuals who own or manage the firm.”Footnote 157 Personality entails three core capacities: (i) separate ownership; (ii) the firm's capacity to contract in its own name; and (iii) capacity to sue and be sued in its own name.Footnote 158 Each of these components depend on key background legal rules,Footnote 159 which, in each case, are undermined by IIL and ISDS. Some further specificity helps to show why.

Separate ownership (or “separate patrimony” in civil law) is the most technical aspect of personality. The basic idea is that the corporation can own assets in its own right, hived off from its shareholders. Such patrimony includes “rights to use the assets, to sell them, and—of particular importance—to make them available for attachment by [the corporation's] creditors.”Footnote 160 Conversely, the firm's assets are unavailable for attachment by shareholders’ personal creditors. Emphasizing function over form, law and economics literature refers to this aspect as “entity shielding.”Footnote 161 Separate patrimony, or entity shielding, is produced by two distinct background rules: a creditor priority rule, granting the firm's creditors a claim on corporate assets prior to any claims by shareholders or their personal creditors; and a rule of liquidation protection, barring shareholders from withdrawing their share of corporate assets at will.Footnote 162 Together, these rules “protect the going concern value of the firm against destruction by individual shareholders or their creditors.”Footnote 163 Entity shielding is what allows a firm to assure outsiders (such as creditors) that it will be able to carry out its obligations. It facilitates negotiating contracts and, ultimately, shareholder liquidity.Footnote 164

The other two capacities of separate legal personality similarly require dedicated legal rules to make them fully viable. The capacity of a corporation to contract in its own name requires clear rules about who acts for the corporation—who may buy and sell in its name, or otherwise commit its resources. Some can be defaults—corporations are generally free to decide how actual authority is delegated. However, the law must at minimum provide rigid rules on apparent authority to protect third parties.Footnote 165 Similarly, the capacity to sue and be sued requires background legal procedures specifying how the firm can initiate, or be subjected to, litigation. For example, most jurisdictions provide that, in general, management (not shareholders) makes litigation decisions on behalf of the corporation, and all recovery is due to, or from, the firm (not its owners).Footnote 166

As a whole, separate legal personality facilitates efficient contracting, reduces conflicts of interest and associated agency costs, and, ex ante, serves to reduce the costs of capital. However, “[t]he outcomes achieved by each of these three types of rules—entity shielding, authority, and procedure—require dedicated legal doctrines to be effective,” rules which, empirically, all national legal systems provide without major differences.Footnote 167 It is therefore striking that IIL and ISDS have managed to subvert the rules undergirding each component of separate legal personality, in sometimes serious ways, without much in the way of policy justification for doing so. I illustrate such distortions in two contexts: (1) shareholder suits for reflective loss; and (2) apparent authority.

1. Shareholder Claims for Reflective Loss

If the problem with how investment law grapples with contracts stems from the underspecified relationship between contracts-as-investments and substantive treaty protections, the problem with stocks and shares relates more to the procedural right of access to ISDS. While it is clear that stocks and shares are covered investments,Footnote 168 BITs tend to say very little about just how shareholder-investors may bring suit, and whether such procedural rights might differ from rights of suit relating to property, contracts, or intellectual property. Though counterintuitive at first blush, there is no reason to assume that each type of investment is meant to, or should, involve the same kind of access to arbitration. To the contrary, the assumption that investors in stocks or shares possess unqualified access to ISDS substantially distorts national corporate law, upsetting the careful tradeoffs of interests and values established by both home and host state jurisdictions, with perverse consequences for corporate constituencies wherever they reside.

Investment treaties typically say very little about shareholder standing. The 2017 Japan-Israel BIT is typical.Footnote 169 Article 1 provides:

(a) the term ‘investment’ means every kind of asset … owned or controlled, directly or indirectly, by an investor, including … (ii) shares, stocks or other forms of equity participation in an enterprise.”

Beyond that, Article 24(2) provides very generally that an investor

… may submit to arbitration under this Article a claim: (a) that the respondent [state] has breached an obligation under Section I …; and (b) that the claimant has incurred loss or damage by reason of, or arising out of, that breach.

The connection between these provisions seems facially straightforward: shareholders-qua-investors appear empowered to sue the state directly for treaty breaches causing diminution in share value. From a corporate law perspective, however, things become immediately murky.

With real property, the relationship between the investment and the right to invoke ISDS is perfectly clear. In case of a dispute, the investor-in-property may compel the host state into arbitration. If she wins, she is clearly entitled to the winnings. She is thereby made whole. The same holds for investors with covered contract or intellectual property rights. By contrast, where the investment in question is a pool of stock or shares in a corporation, drawing such a straight line between investment and ISDS proves quite problematic.

At least from the perspective of corporate law, basic questions about just what kind of suit an investor-shareholder is entitled to bring are left totally unaddressed. Evidently, she is entitled to some kind of access to ISDS. But what kind of claim(s) can she bring? Can she bring suit on her own behalf, for injuries to the company diminishing the value of her shares? Or may she only bring suit on the company's behalf? And who is entitled to recover damages—the shareholder or the firm? The answers determine the relative strength of separate ownership, as well as the contours of managerial authority over litigation. Separate personality thus turns on these questions, making them fundamental to any system of corporate law. Yet they are rarely addressed directly in treaty text, leaving their resolution to arbitral interpretation. What is striking is that advanced national legal systems almost always answer these questions in one way, for clear policy reasons, while ISDS tribunals invariably go in the opposite direction—with little policy justification.

Because shareholder standing cuts to the core of separate legal personality, corporate law everywhere sharply distinguishes two kinds of shareholder claims. On the one hand, shareholders may bring “direct claims,” for injury to their shares (if, say, the government improperly forces an investor to sell her shares in a company). On the other hand, shareholders are typically not permitted to bring claims for “shareholder reflective loss,” meaning claims based on injury to the corporation causing incidental diminution in share value.Footnote 170 In general, all claims arising out of injury to the corporation must be vindicated by the corporation itself (in management's discretion). The only significant exception is the shareholder derivative suit, where shareholders can sometimes bring claims on behalf of the corporation against management's wishes (typically requiring managerial conflict of interest), with any recovery going to the firm.Footnote 171

All advanced domestic systems of corporate law categorically reject shareholder reflective loss suits,Footnote 172 as do most international jurisdictions, including the International Court of JusticeFootnote 173 and the European Court of Human Rights.Footnote 174 However, as Gaukrodger explains, the restriction of shareholder claims is rarely codified in statute or treaty.Footnote 175 The doctrine is instead usually judge-made, even in civil law countries. The main policy concern driving this common judicial practice is that allowing direct shareholder recovery for reflective loss undermines entity shielding, and thus separate legal personality. Allowing reflective loss claims enables shareholders to siphon off recovery rightly belonging to the injured company (eroding liquidation protection), and thereby jump ahead of creditors and other shareholders (circumventing creditor priority). It also enables shareholders to undermine centralized managerial decision-making about litigation or settlement, and creates unfair risks of multiple claims and double recovery.Footnote 176

ISDS tribunals, by contrast, invariably interpret investment treaties as permitting shareholder reflective loss claims, with little explanation or analysis of why this follows from the underlying treaties.Footnote 177 They instead tend to assume that vague treaty text speaks for itself. In Impregilo, for example, the Italian claimant-shareholder complained of Argentina's actions toward a local entity in which it had a controlling interest (AGBA). For the tribunal, it was enough that the definition of investment in the Argentina—Italy BIT included stocks and shares: “[If] AGBA was subjected to expropriation or unfair treatment with respect to its concession … such action must also be considered to have affected Impregilo's rights as an investor, rights that were protected under the BIT.”Footnote 178

Such a focus on the definition of investment apparently leads tribunals to assume that shareholder claims are independent from the firm's claims. This creates two further problematic corollaries. First, tribunals allow shareholders to recover directly in such suits, in proportion to their stake in the company. This effectively reverses the rule across national jurisdictions that all recovery should go to the corporation itself. Second, this assumption of independence opens the door to multiple parallel and/or sequential claims—by the company, by controlling shareholders, and/or by various minority shareholders.Footnote 179 The effect is exponentially compounded where the treaty also covers indirect equity.Footnote 180

Although ISDS case law is remarkably well-settled on each of these points, it is not clear that these conclusions necessarily follow from how investment treaties are drafted. Rather, ISDS openness to claims of shareholder reflective loss reflects an interpretive choice. Certainly, BIT coverage of stocks and shares is meant to have some effect. But most investment treaties do not address the scope of shareholder claims.Footnote 181 That covering stocks and shares as investments, without more, implies allowing shareholder reflective loss claims is certainly one possibility. But other less distortive interpretations are also reasonable. One approach would require that such claims be brought on behalf of the firm, with any recovery going to company coffers. Another would be to limit shareholder claims to residual actions where the corporation itself (i.e. management) is unable or unwilling to bring its own claim for some inequitable reason. While the pro-shareholder reflective loss rule may fit (relatively) neatly with the text of most investment treaties, these texts do not unambiguously close off a more calibrated approach. Nor is text everything. Indeed, even as a matter of formal treaty interpretation, it is not clear why tribunals have given such short shrift to the position in general international law,Footnote 182 or the uniformity across domestic jurisdictions.Footnote 183 As in domestic law, the scope and limits of shareholder suits reflect judicial choices. The difference is that, in ISDS, tribunals have placed little emphasis on policy, relying more on (assumed) textual mandate and arbitral precedent.

A small handful of treaties seem designed to limit shareholder claims, yet even here the pull of ISDS precedents on reflective loss is apparent. The NAFTA, for example, includes stocks and shares in the definition of investment,Footnote 184 but distinguishes between two types of shareholder ISDS claims. Article 1116 covers claims by an investor “on its own behalf.” Article 1117, by contrast, permits an investor to bring a claim “on behalf of” a locally incorporated enterprise that it “owns or controls, directly or indirectly”—essentially a form of derivative action, where recovery goes to the company.Footnote 185 Further, Article 1117(3) provides for presumptive joinder of 1116 and 1117 claims arising out of the same events. The NAFTA parties have consistently argued that these provisions mirror the classic separation between direct and derivative claims in domestic corporate law, with the intent of precluding shareholder reflective loss claims.Footnote 186 But these provisions are not paragons of clarity. While some tribunals have viewed them as barring shareholder claims for reflective loss,Footnote 187 others have permitted reflective loss claims under Article 1116.Footnote 188

From his extensive review of the cases, Gaukrodger concludes that tribunals “have apparently considered it unnecessary to consider policy consequences in any detail because they consider that the issue is resolved by the inclusion of shares in the investment definition … [and by force of] arbitral precedent”—although the precedents themselves “rarely if ever addressed the policy issues or consequences.”Footnote 189 Yet it is worth considering whether there might nevertheless be some policy justification for allowing shareholder reflective loss claims in ISDS that may be absent in domestic law. One seemingly compelling reason might be to protect foreigners who invest through local entities, as discussed above. This does not, however, require anything so radical as reversing the national rule against shareholder reflective loss claims. Various treaties incorporate provisions that would solve this problem more directly, without contorting domestic corporate law. The NAFTA avoids this problem by providing for derivative suits.Footnote 190 And many U.S. BITs resolve the issue by providing that a local company can invoke ISDS as a constructive foreign investor if it would itself qualify as a covered investment under the treaty (by dint of foreign ownership).Footnote 191 These treaties still cover stocks and shares, and tribunals thus usually view them as permitting local company claims in addition to claims for shareholder reflective loss.Footnote 192 But these alternatives would suffice, on their own, to protect investors operating through local companies without sacrificing major features of corporate law, undercutting this possible rationale for allowing shareholder reflective loss claims.

Although neither necessitated by text, nor supported by any clear policy justification, ISDS openness to shareholder reflective loss has a strong distortive effect on national private law. By allowing such shareholder claims, IIL displaces a keystone presumption of corporate law wherever the relevant company is incorporated (home or host state), undermining foundational principles of the corporate form on which all constituencies rely. The ISDS approach further contorts domestic corporate law by allowing such shareholders to recover directly, bypassing the firm's coffers; and by allowing the firm and its shareholders to bring multiple independent, and even sequential, claims. Each of these moves reverses the position of the firm under the domestic law of incorporation. IIL thereby tends to upset how that state's national law calibrates the rights, interests, and expectations of key corporate constituencies—shareholders, creditors, and management. Each of these distortions also strongly affects the expectations of the host state more generally, in its interactions with the firm—both adversarial (e.g. as a defendant) and cooperative (e.g. in trying to salvage an ongoing relationship, or settle a lawsuit).

The obvious surface problem with ISDS openness to reflective loss claims concerns the fairness of admitting multiple shareholder and/or corporate claims. Tribunals’ tendency to view corporate claims and claims by discrete shareholders as completely independent raises two specters: double recovery and multiple bites at the apple. Tribunals have proven sensitive to the former, generally striving to limit shareholder recovery on a pro rata basis if and when the arbitration reaches the damages phase. However, the latter concern has mostly fallen on deaf ears.Footnote 193 The problem is most vividly illustrated by the widely criticized awards in CME and Lauder v. Czech Republic. These cases involved separate claims arising out of the same injury to a local Czech company—by its 99 percent shareholder (CME) and by an indirect minority shareholder (Lauder, who controlled CME).Footnote 194 The two tribunals substantially agreed on the admissibility of multiple separate shareholder suits. The respondent argued that Lauder should be dismissed, because, to the extent that any damages were due, recovery by CME would make all of its shareholders whole—including Mr. Lauder—while recovery by the latter would leave the other shareholders in CME empty-handed.Footnote 195 Both tribunals disagreed, insisting that the claims were independent precisely because Lauder could not be completely identified with CME.Footnote 196 They then famously disagreed on the merits of essentially identical disputes: Lauder lost, while CME won an award in excess of $270 million.

The treatment of shareholder reflective loss in CME and Lauder is typical. This approach gives investors little reason to forego successive bites at the apple beyond (substantial) cost—especially in close cases. Beyond the manifest unfairness of allowing one party to “play ‘till you win,” the ISDS approach also distorts incentives on all sides at the settlement stage, and facilitates opportunistic hold ups.

There have, however, been some recent signs that tribunals are becoming more sensitive to these concerns—at least on the surface. A few have recognized that, in principle, it would be abusive to allow an aggrieved investor to bring suit after failed suit, ad infinitum. A handful have drawn an outer limit based on complete identity of shares—barring separate claims by shareholders and their wholly owned entities,Footnote 197 or separate indirect and direct shareholder claims over the exact same tranche of shares.Footnote 198 However, this rule is not difficult to work around and does little to ward off opportunism.

The very recent award in Orascom v. Algeria goes further, explicitly questioning the continued relevance of Lauder/CME.Footnote 199 In Orascom, the ultimate controlling shareholder had both brought its own shareholder claim, and caused several subsidiary entities in the chain to bring separate parallel claims under different BITs (including the local entity itself, the direct shareholder, and several other intermediaries). Uncomfortable with permitting the claimant so many shots, the tribunal invoked the equitable doctrine of “abuse of right”—holding that “an investor who controls several entities in a vertical chain of companies may commit an abuse if it seeks to impugn the same host state measures and claims for the same harm at various levels of the chain.”Footnote 200 The investor may opt to take his bite through any affected vehicle he controls, but he may not take more than one.Footnote 201 Still, the tribunal refused to foreclose the possibility of additional reflective loss claims by other non-controlling shareholders (direct or indirect), viewing these as essentially independent.Footnote 202 Thus, while Orascom is a step in the right direction, it addresses only the surface problems of multiple claims and double recovery, and these only partially.

The deeper structural harm in ISDS openness to shareholder reflective loss is that it hollows the core tenets of entity-shielding: creditor priority and liquidation protection. Where the corporation alone is entitled to bring suit to vindicate its interests, all recovery goes to the company—to be distributed according to normal priority rules, and without abnormal risk of liquidation by individual shareholders. But because ISDS entitles individual shareholders to sue host states for reflective loss and recover directly, the covered shareholder-investor is empowered to jump the line (undermining priority rules), and to siphon off assets rightfully belonging to the corporation as a whole (undermining liquidation protection). This move undermines the signal feature of separate legal personality, with consequences ex post (e.g., for the insulation and/or equitable distribution of corporate assets) and ex ante (e.g., for the availability and price of credit).Footnote 203

The extent to which ISDS distorts national law on entity shielding is especially stark where the firm is in distress—in the zone of bankruptcy, or in actual bankruptcy proceedings. As Gaukrodger puts it, usually “[shareholder reflective loss] intervenes at a moment when the company is already weakened. What is at issue is the company's capacity to reconstitute its assets and expectations about that capacity.”Footnote 204

Assume, for simplicity, that a foreign-owned firm's value as a going concern is destroyed due to host state mistreatment. The business may need to be wound down, irrespective of any potential recovery from the state. In such circumstances, there may not be enough assets to satisfy the firm's creditors and shareholders. National corporate law guarantees creditors priority on these assets. If the business gets wound down, all funds (including any recovery in pending litigation) get paid out to the firm's creditors first, and distributed pro rata among shareholders only thereafter.Footnote 205 Creditors depend on this priority rule, and it is a key factor in the availability (and price) of credit ex ante.Footnote 206 ISDS, however, allows particular (treaty-protected) shareholders to recover immediately, reducing the total asset pool available for distribution to all other corporate constituencies. Even if the tribunal reduces the investor's recovery in proportion to her shares, there may not be enough left to satisfy the firm's creditors (who normally expect priority), or appropriately compensate other shareholders (who expect parity). Moreover, allowing a shareholder to recover directly enables her to siphon value from the firm, potentially undercutting its capacity to reconstitute itself as a going concern. Thus, the ISDS rule distorts both aspects of entity shielding (creditor priority and liquidation protection), with the effect of subverting the normal expectations of creditors and shareholders (as a class) set by the domestic law of the corporation (be that host state law or home state law).

Although less glaring, the ISDS rule also undermines core features of the corporate form even for firms not in distress. It allows shareholders to second-guess fundamental managerial decisions on whether to initiate litigation, how to pursue lawsuits, and whether to settle.Footnote 207 Investment disputes can (and often should) be resolved through consultation and compromise, rather than litigation. But the specter of separate shareholder claims substantially weakens the company's hand, and should diminish a rational state's confidence that any agreement with management will ultimately stick. This further undermines the foundations of separate legal personality (weakening the firm's ability to serve as a single contracting party, and to sue in its own name) as well as the principle of delegated management.Footnote 208

In perforating separate legal personality, ISDS creates substantial inefficiencies. Ex post, the rule creates incentives for covered shareholders to act opportunistically, especially where firms are in distress. This harms creditors, other shareholders, and the firm itself. Even among treaty-covered shareholders, it creates perverse first-mover incentives, with obvious harm for states stuck defending multiple claims. And it weakens the hand of management in its interaction with the state at critical moments. All these effects are further likely to produce ex ante problems over the long term. IIL, as interpreted, forces creditors to account for the dearth of typical priority and liquidation protections when considering whether to fund foreign direct investment projects—a problem drastically exacerbated by the possibility of reflective loss claims by indirect investors. By imposing additional risks and costs, this rule pushes creditors to either reduce the availability of credit, or increase its price—affecting the overall cost of capital either way.Footnote 209

In sum, based solely on the fact that investment treaties cover stocks and shares as investments, without clarifying the scope of investor standing vis-à-vis such investments, ISDS tribunals have inferred that shareholder-investors enjoy the same procedural rights as any other investors. They have thus allowed shareholder claims for reflective loss without much considering the vast policy considerations at stake.Footnote 210 This position deviates from, and displaces, the rule universally adopted by advanced national corporate laws, as well as general international law. More fundamentally, IIL here affirmatively distorts the domestic corporate laws of all parties to the investment treaty, undermining key features of the corporate form for any firm involved in foreign direct investment. These distortions have harmful spillover effects for the firm itself, as well as inside and outside constituencies, both ex post (incentivizing multiple bites at the apple and shareholder opportunism), and ex ante (diminishing managerial authority and the availability of credit).Footnote 211

2. Agency and Apparent Authority

IIL and ISDS also distort the firm's capacity to contract as a single entity—another hallmark of separate legal personality—by creating unnecessary questions about apparent authority. This capacity turns on dedicated background rules articulating the authority of agents to tie the firm's hands. “Rules governing the allocation of authority are needed to establish common expectations as to who has authority to transfer rights relating to corporate assets prior to entering into a contract for their transfer.”Footnote 212 For most matters, mere default rules suffice. Corporate law generally leaves firms significant leeway to decide internally how actual authority is delegated—in its articles of incorporation, or bylaws. However, the law must provide firmer guidance regarding apparent authority, upon which third parties can rely. Otherwise, parties wishing to deal with the firm would face oppressive and wasteful costs to discover whether officers indeed possess the authority to transact in the firm's name.Footnote 213 This, in turn, would open the door to undue opportunism on the part of the firm and its agents. Corporate law everywhere thus provides minimal rules delineating apparent authority, or some functional equivalent, and generally makes them mandatory.Footnote 214

ISDS muddies the apparent authority analysis.Footnote 215 Questions of authority come up frequently in ISDS—sometimes regarding agents of the host stateFootnote 216 or state-owned entities, and sometimes regarding the investor's corporate agents.Footnote 217 Investment treaties generally say nothing on the subject, leaving it to tribunals to resolve such issues. Here, as with contracts, the absence of clear rules creates substantial uncertainty: Is the question of authority governed by national law? If so, which national law? And, if not, on what basis will tribunals decide such questions?

Given the strong policy rationale favoring clear rules of apparent authority, one would expect a tribunal to simply rely on national law to resolve the issue, following conflict of laws principles—or at least articulate its own “crystalline” rules-based approach upon which states and putative investors could theoretically rely ex ante.Footnote 218 The case law on point is still sparse. Yet at least one tribunal eschewed a rules-based approach to apparent authority entirely, instead resolving the issue through muddy ex post equitable balancing—creating significant uncertainty and revealing yet another way in which ISDS can distort the corporate form.

In Getma v. Guinea, four related claimant companies brought an ICSID claim over the state's termination of a concession contract to develop and operate a container terminal in the Port of Conkary.Footnote 219 One entity (NCT Necotrans) wholly owned the other three subsidiaries (including Getma). The preliminary issue was whether the claimants had waived ICSID jurisdiction. The concession agreement, formally executed between Getma and Guinea, contained an arbitration clause that selected the Common Court of Justice (CCJA) of the Organization for the Harmonization of Business Law in Africa (OHADA). In the tribunal's view, this clause served to waive ICSID jurisdiction under the Guinean Investment Law, which provided standing consent to arbitrate at ICSID absent a “contrary agreement” to arbitrate elsewhere.Footnote 220 Since Getma had actually signed the contract, its access to ICSID was foreclosed. The key issue was whether the other three claimants, not parties to the contract, were nevertheless constructively bound by the waiver.Footnote 221

Guinea claimed that the non-signatories should be bound on a “group of companies” theory, allowing extending an arbitration agreement with a subsidiary to its non-signatory parent (and other related companies) under certain conditions.Footnote 222 Functionally, this doctrine should be understood under the rubric of apparent authority—as a means of protecting third parties who believe they are negotiating with the broader group.Footnote 223 Guinea argued that the doctrine applied as a substantive principle of international arbitration applicable in OHADA law.Footnote 224 The claimants denied that any such doctrine applied, being neither clearly established in many domestic legal orders, nor in ICSID case law,Footnote 225 and being in any event inapposite on the facts.Footnote 226

Given the parties’ views on the matter, one might have expected the tribunal to deal with three questions to determine the applicable rules of apparent authority here: Does the group of companies theory apply? If so, does it bind the non-signatory claimants to Getma's contractual waiver of ICSID jurisdiction? And if not, might some other rules of apparent authority bind the non-signatories?Footnote 227 Yet, with no explanation, the tribunal skated past any rules-based analysis, opting instead to resolve the issue through impressionistic balancing.

The tribunal first carefully examined whether Getma might have had actual authority to bind the other members of the group. Confusingly, the same individuals who served as executives of the subsidiaries also served as executives or board members of the parent—meaning that the same individuals might have authority to speak for each entity.Footnote 228 The tribunal rightly held that actual authority would turn on whether those officers were acting on behalf of Getma or the other entities in negotiating and signing the concession agreement—and found that they were indeed only acting as Getma's agents.Footnote 229

The more difficult question was whether these companies could be bound to the concession under a theory of apparent authority. Obviously, the investors’ group structure could create confusion in the negotiating process. So the question was whether some rule of apparent authority entitled Guinea to understand that it was negotiating with the corporate group as a whole. Here the tribunal opted to resolve things on its own, through muddy ex post equitable review. It rejected Guinea's proposed theory of corporate groups out of hand—without reference to any particular applicable law or policy.Footnote 230 Instead, the tribunal declared that “[t]hird parties are obliged to recognize the proper identity of each company, unless the companies themselves do not respect it and create confusion about the subject.”Footnote 231 However, the tribunal emphasized that these companies each had a defined, constitutive role in the investment project, and that Getma was negotiating through individuals who also served as officers of the other companies. In the tribunal's view, the claimants should have known that Guinea might derive reasonable assurances from these facts.Footnote 232 Thus it held the non-signatories to the concession agreement's waiver of ICSID jurisdiction.Footnote 233

Viewed in isolation, the tribunal's analysis seems reasonable enough. It seemed to reject a broad group of companies doctrine, in favor of a more stringent theory of apparent authority, wherein one member of a corporate group might bind the others without actual authority if the companies were all active participants in the investment, and their conduct was likely to create substantial confusion about the distinctions among them. This would be a perfectly reasonable approach, closer to the U.S. alter ego approach than the French doctrine of groupes des sociétés,Footnote 234 and this is not the place to debate which would be normatively preferable. The distortion arises from the fact that the tribunal did not inquire into the applicable law at all—in a context where crystalline clarity serves a crucial function of protecting third parties. The tribunal rather engaged in a wholly de novo analysis, neither grounded in any national or international law, nor adequately specified in its contours.

The corporate form requires clear and immutable rules on apparent authority. Their absence engenders perverse incentives for firms to behave opportunistically and forces third parties to engage in excessive due diligence. Even mere confusion about the rules drives up the cost of doing business. Though the Getma tribunal came to a reasonable enough ex post result, its rough justice analysis does little to foster confidence in the content of apparent authority ex ante. Under this muddy approach, ISDS displaces otherwise applicable national law solutions without offering a reasonably secure alternative. This further distorts the capacity of the firm to serve as a single contracting party, which depends on outsiders having confidence in the rules of engagement. What the tribunal should have done instead—and future tribunals ought to do—is rely on national apparent authority rules, determined on the basis of conflict of laws analysis.Footnote 235 Failing that, the Getma tribunal should have at least articulated a rules-based approach on which future arbitrators might rely—even given the perennial institutional deficiencies of ISDS.

3. Distorting the Corporate Form

In extending their coverage to enterprises, as well as stocks and shares, investment treaties materially create international corporate law. However, they do so only implicitly and vaguely. ISDS has tended to interpret the treaties in ways that displace keystone principles of domestic corporate law, and distort the corporate form. In particular, the patterns of interpretation undercut the corporation's separate legal personality, undermining each of its three core features. By upending the domestic bar on shareholder reflective loss suits, ISDS provides an end run around separate ownership (by weakening entity shielding and liquidation protection). It further allows shareholders to second-guess managerial authority over litigation, watering down the firm's capacity to sue on its own behalf (not to mention delegated management) with efficiency costs for insiders and third parties. And finally, by muddying the waters on apparent authority, ISDS erodes the firm's capacity to contract in its own name, creating unnecessary due diligence costs for all who engage with firms involved in foreign direct investment.

These problems adequately illustrate the distortive potential of ISDS vis-à-vis national corporate law. Yet other instances abound. Another example, which I explore in greater detail elsewhere, regularly arises when tribunals have to decide under what circumstances it would be appropriate to “look through” a corporation (“veil piercing”)—for such different questions as determining corporate nationality, or attributing acts of a state-owned corporation to the host state.Footnote 236 Here the reverse problem arises. Rather than ignoring domestic law, tribunals have typically overemphasized domestic analogies—leaning on an inapposite presumption against veil piercing derived from the very different context of limited shareholder liability, without considering the different interests and values at stake across these varied situations.Footnote 237

Lastly, it is worth noting that the distortions of contract and corporate law compound one another. One extreme result has been to render the terms of a bargained-for state contract effectively optional for a foreign investor operating through a business corporation.Footnote 238 This perverse result arises because IIL and ISDS simultaneously (1) make treaty rules mandatory, and (2) allow firms to shop for treaty protection after executing their contracts (by granting rights of standing to indirect shareholders).Footnote 239 As a result, a firm can contract with a state in the absence of any investment treaty, and unilaterally alter the terms of the deal in its favor by restructuring for BIT protection ex post, without even notifying the host state.Footnote 240 This situation creates excessive due diligence costs for states party to even a single investment treaty, as well as significant risks of unfair, surprise constraints on their freedom of action.

At the same time, the mandatory approach to contracts might undercut potential private ordering solutions to ISDS’ distortions of the corporate form. Korzun has suggested, for example, that firms might restrict shareholder access to ISDS in corporate charters or bylaws.Footnote 241 Firms should be able to do this. But the current contracts jurisprudence leaves open to serious doubt whether an ISDS tribunal would give this innovative solution any effect.

D. Intellectual Property as a Limited Case for Optimism

Tribunals have tended to fare better in the few decided cases involving intellectual property claims, with greater sensitivity to the discrete functions of patent and trademark protection. Intellectual property refers to a group of loosely related bundles of intangible rights to control the products of human innovation and creativity.Footnote 242 The major forms involve ownership rights over inventions (patent), expressions (copyright), and brand names or signs (trademark). This is not the place to delve deeply into these categories. Suffice it to say that each reflects a bargain between society and innovators: under certain circumstances, the state protects knowledge-based goods with the goal of encouraging socially beneficial innovation. Such protections are always limited in scope, and often in duration. They are typically framed around exclusive rights—private monopolies that allow owners to challenge infringing conduct by other private actors. And intellectual property rights typically involve only limited protection against the state as regulator.

The various intellectual property categories each involve different values and tradeoffs. For example, patent seeks to incentivize costly research and development by limiting third party free-riding after the utility (and value) of an invention is established. One glaring tradeoff is that such private monopolies may keep prices high for important consumer goods like medicines. Trademark, by contrast, enables a business to protect the goodwill it generates by preventing others from trading off its name—but might make it difficult for new, potentially innovative firms to dislodge established market players. Different types of intellectual property protection pursue different interests and values, and in no case is there a perfect balance among the relevant tradeoffs. Nations unsurprisingly differ in what priorities they pursue in their intellectual property regimes.

However, unlike with property and contract, there is a broad field of international intellectual property law, comprised of major multilateral treaties and institutions,Footnote 243 and regional agreements. Indeed, most national legal systems have committed internationally to harmonize a common core of patent, copyright, and trademark rights. Still, countries exhibit considerable variation in how far they go beyond these minimums and how they interpret them. And some still refrain from signing on to particular intellectual property treaties in the first place.Footnote 244

The ISDS cases decided thus far have not upended this ecology—neither distorting national nor international intellectual property law, nor, mostly, the balance between them.Footnote 245 This does not mean that the investment treaty regime has had no distortive effects. It is difficult to know how far the mere threat of ISDS has pushed states to preemptively distort the regulatory balance in favor of foreign intellectual property owners. And some large investors have pursued strategies of intense pressure under the shadow of litigation—sometimes successfully.Footnote 246 Still, from a private law perspective, the few merits awards in intellectual property cases light the path toward a better approach.

1. The State of the Field: Trademark and Patent

Of the handful of ISDS merits-awards based on intellectual property investments, the most prominent are Philip Morris v. Uruguay and Eli Lilly v. Canada.Footnote 247 In each case, the tribunal proved sensitive to the particularities of the intellectual property rights comprising the investment—trademarks and patents, respectively.Footnote 248 Rather than treat all covered investments as an undifferentiated pool, both tribunals started from the sensible assumption that any expropriation or fair and equitable treatment analysis would have to begin with an appreciation of the scope and meaning of those rights alleged to have been taken.

Philip Morris v. Uruguay involved a dispute over restrictions on cigarette packaging, which the investor alleged to have vitiated the value of several of its brands—in violation of treaty provisions on expropriation and fair and equitable treatment (among others). The investor had registered several trademarks in Uruguay, grouped into several brands (e.g., Marlboro, Casino, and Fiesta), each including several “variants” (e.g., Marlboro Red, Marlboro Gold, and Marlboro Fresh Mint). The dispute arose out of two Uruguayan measures designed to limit tobacco consumption. One limited brand presentation to 20 percent of any cigarette package (the 80/80 regulation). The other barred companies from subdividing brands to prevent misleading consumers into thinking that some variants posed lower health risks (the Single Presentation Regulation)—effectively forcing the investor to choose one variant and refrain from marketing the others.Footnote 249 The clear goal of both measures was to mitigate consumer misinformation about the serious health risks associated with smoking. There was no dispute that trademarks were covered as investments under the BIT. The case turned on whether Uruguay had violated the treaty in regulating how the investor used its marks (the 80/80 regulation), and by completely restricting the use of several of its variant marks (Single Presentation).

The tribunal rightly began by inquiring into the exact nature of trademark rights under Uruguayan law. Acknowledging that the governing law of the dispute was the BIT (and other applicable international law), the tribunal nevertheless explained that the treaty could not be applied in the abstract. Any expropriation or fair and equitable treatment claim must start with that which was alleged to have been taken—an investment, the scope and contents of which are determined, in the first cut, by national law.Footnote 250 Thus “[t]he central issue over the trademarks is what rights a registered trademark accords its owner under Uruguayan law.”Footnote 251 Specifically, the case turned on whether Uruguayan trademarks entailed absolute use rights or merely exclusive rights. The first would entail an affirmative right to use the trademarks in any way the investor wished, free from restriction by government or encroachment by others. The latter would entail more limited rights to exclude others from using the marks, or confusingly similar ones, without guaranteeing that the owner would be free to use the mark herself.

The claimant attempted to muddy the waters by arguing that “trademarks are a form of property” like any other, “and that all property owners have the right to use their property” under the Uruguayan Constitution.Footnote 252 However, the tribunal rightly agreed with the respondent that Uruguayan law distinguishes between tangible and intellectual property, and that the scope of the investor's rights could only be determined in light of Uruguayan trademark law.Footnote 253 Reviewing Uruguay's intellectual property statutes and international intellectual property commitments, the tribunal held that the Uruguayan trademarks entailed merely exclusive rights, with no “absolute right to use that can be asserted against the state qua regulator.”Footnote 254

The question, then, was whether Uruguay's regulatory measures expropriated, or otherwise interfered with, the investor's exclusive rights. The tribunal found that neither constituted an expropriation, which would require a substantial deprivation of the asset. The 80/80 regulation did not deprive the investor of its marks at all, merely limiting the size of their presentation. The Single Presentation Requirement was more difficult, because it prevented Philip Morris from using some of its trademarks entirely, forcing it to pick one variant per brand and let other trademarked variants lie fallow. However, the tribunal refused to examine the trademarks one by one, instead finding that they comprised a single investment for purposes of an expropriation analysis, and that there had been no substantial deprivation of that investment as a whole.Footnote 255 And in any case, neither measure in any way impaired the investor's right to exclude third parties from using its marks.

The tribunal also found that there was no violation of fair and equitable treatment. In its view, the state was entitled to “great deference” in fair and equitable treatment claims when regulating matters like public health in good faith. Again emphasizing that the investors’ rights were limited to exclusion, not use, it found that the measures were not sufficiently egregious as to breach the treaty.Footnote 256

[C]hanges to general legislation (at least in the absence of a stabilization clause) are not prevented by the fair and equitable treatment standard if they do not exceed the exercise of the host State's normal regulatory power in the pursuance of a public interest and do not modify the regulatory framework relied upon by the investor at the time of its investment “outside of the acceptable margin of change.”Footnote 257

In the tribunal's view, the investor could not draw from general Uruguayan law a legitimate expectation that its trademarks would not be subject to future regulation (though, notably, as in Parkerings, it could have ratcheted up the level of treaty protection by contract).Footnote 258

From a private law perspective, Philip Morris v. Uruguay admirably keeps property, intellectual property, and contract separate—despite their undifferentiated inclusion under the treaty definition of investment. For the tribunal, the extension of treaty standards to intellectual property rights turns on the content of those rights under national law, and must not be confused with other forms of property. And should an investor wish for heightened protections, she is free to bargain with the state for a contractual stabilization clause.

The award in Eli Lilly v. Canada is similarly encouraging. At issue there was the Canadian courts’ invalidation of two of the claimant's patents for medications. The courts voided the patents on the basis of a common law “promise utility doctrine.”Footnote 259 Canadian patent law, like that of other jurisdictions, requires that a patent be both novel and useful. The promise utility doctrine represented a relatively restrictive version of the usefulness prong, requiring that any invention actually turn out to have the utility that the filer claimed it would. The doctrine also foreclosed owners from developing post-filing evidence of utility or finding new potential uses for the invention to justify the original patent. The claimant alleged that the promise utility doctrine was a new creation by the courts—one that radically departed from the much more lenient regime in force when the patents were actually filed. Eli Lilly thus claimed that the retroactive application of this doctrine to invalidate its patents constituted an expropriation and a breach of legitimate expectations.Footnote 260

The tribunal sided with Canada on most fronts, mostly limiting its discussion to dismissing the “factual predicate” of the investor's case: that the promise utility doctrine represented a radical transformation of Canadian common law.Footnote 261 Most importantly for present purposes, the tribunal focused on the meaning of the claimant's rights under national law, and considered any expectations to which these patents might give rise only in the context of the intellectual property regime under which they were actually granted. Noting that Canada is a common law system, the tribunal emphasized that “evolution of the law through court decisions is natural, and departures from precedent are to be expected,”Footnote 262 and that “although [the] Claimant may not have been able to predict the precise trajectory of the law on utility, it should have, and could have, anticipated that the law would change over time as a function of judicial decision-making.”Footnote 263 The tribunal also found that the promise utility doctrine emerged incrementally, with roots predating Eli Lilly's patents, thus upending the factual premise on which the claimant hung its hat.Footnote 264

Finally, timing aside, the tribunal examined whether the Canadian patent doctrine could be described as arbitrary on its face. Stressing that the measures in question were judicial rulings, the tribunal deferred mightily to both the courts’ interpretations of their own domestic law and their policy considerations, applying a highly deferential “rational connection” test.Footnote 265 It found that Canada had a “legitimate public policy justification” for the promise utility doctrine, in that it “helps ensure that ‘the public receives its end of the patent bargain’ … and that it ‘encourages accuracy while discouraging overstatement in patent disclosures.’”Footnote 266 The tribunal found that it “need not opine on whether the promise doctrine is the only, or the best, means of achieving these objectives.”Footnote 267 It sufficed that the “doctrine is rationally connected to these legitimate policy goals … [and] it is not the role of a NAFTA Chapter Eleven tribunal to question the policy choices of a NAFTA Party.”Footnote 268

In both of the major intellectual property cases decided thus far, the tribunals proved uncommonly sensitive to domestic private law. From a private law perspective, these cases provide a model for engaging with the varied rights and assets covered by investment treaties. The analyses in both Philip Morris and Eli Lilly started from an appreciation of the rights comprising the investment, in their proper national legal context. Both tribunals proved highly sensitive to the discrete functions and logic of intellectual property protection, as against other kinds of assets. And each proved admirably deferential to the states’ own policy choices undergirding their intellectual property regimes. In both instances, then, IIL and ISDS served as an additional layer of protection for the investor's intellectual property rights, without meaningfully distorting national (or international) intellectual property law.

2. Intellectual Property Is Not Inoculated

There is nothing about intellectual property law that insulates it from the distortive effects marking ISDS jurisprudence on contracts or corporate law. One can only speculate about the greater sensitivity to national private law in Philip Morris and Eli Lilly. On the one hand, intellectual property may be a special case. The existence of a robust field of international intellectual property law may have played an important role, allowing the tribunals to “check” domestic intellectual property solutions against what might have appeared more neutral international comparators. It is certainly plausible that these tribunals were more comfortable relying on domestic law to determine the scope of the rights involved because the domestic laws in question comport, more or less closely, with international standards. It may also be that tribunals are more comfortable with the rigid logic of standardization pervading both intellectual property and classical property—the world of forms, by contrast to contract and corporate law, which belong, to varying degrees, to the world of choice.

On the other hand, one might explain the cases by reference to contingent factors: their recent vintage, their exceptionally high profile, or the particular arbitrators involved.Footnote 269 Also potentially relevant is the longstanding political salience of disputes over the scope of intellectual property protection in international law and politics.Footnote 270 Or even more simply, the difference here may just be that the litigants framed these cases around the contours of the domestic intellectual property rights in question.

Whatever the explanation, what is important is that the greater sensitivity of ISDS to the logic and functions of intellectual property cannot be taken as a guarantee. The intellectual property cases do give some cause for cautious optimism. More importantly, they provide a roadmap for how tribunals ought to approach all kinds of private legal rights. But given the diffuse nature of the ISDS regime, the structural risk of distortion remains—both in future cases, and informally, through investor pressure under the shadow of litigation.Footnote 271 Though a handful of cases have come out the right way, it behooves states to consider addressing the specificity of intellectual property at the treaty level.

IV. Conclusion: Private Law and Reform

From a private law perspective, IIL and ISDS have become unjustifiable and increasingly unsustainable. I have argued that investment treaties have quietly established broad fields of international private law—including discrete laws of property, contract, corporations, and intellectual property. This metamorphosis has taken place through a troubling dynamic in the interpretation of thousands of similarly drafted BITs and FTA investment chapters. The treaties typically cover all kinds of private commercial rights as “assets,” without differentiating as to how their substantive and procedural guarantees interact with such varied legal arrangements. Called to interpret the relationship between treaty rights and these myriad commercial assets, ISDS tribunals have mostly followed a one-size-fits-all model, reflecting an assumed real property logic—even though this logic makes little sense as applied to non-property assets. As a result, IIL and ISDS have together generated rudimentary, but surprisingly broad, swathes of international private law—disciplining domestic policy space in underappreciated ways, and distorting the logic and functions of whole fields of domestic private law in relation to foreign investors. Not only do these distortions create unfair ex post constraints and surprise costs for states seeking to regulate in the public interest (the typical public law complaint), they also make investment more difficult, costly, and unappealing for all parties ex ante.

The most significant distortions have thus far arisen in the world of choice—especially in the context of contracts and corporate law. ISDS tribunals have tended to blur the logics of contract and property—limiting states’ and investors’ capacity to bargain for terms they prefer, and instead mandating highly investor-friendly terms which are unlikely to prove efficient under all circumstances. At the same time, tribunals have prevented states from regulating choice where they deem it appropriate in the interest of extrinsic values (like policing public corruption). In so doing, ISDS has turned contract law on its head, undercutting its empowering, gap-filling, and regulatory functions. True, a few tribunals have exhibited a greater appreciation for the logic of contract. But given the institutional fragmentation of the investment treaty regime, even uncertainty over the prospective effects of contractual choices creates substantial inefficiencies for bargaining ex ante.

Similarly the case law has tended to distort the logic and functions of corporate law. By permitting shareholders to directly sue host states for reflective loss, ISDS perforates the firm's separate legal personality, undercutting the expectations of all corporate constituencies (management, shareholders, creditors, and governments). All this affects the cost and availability of credit for foreign direct investment projects, and creates more long-term uncertainty than it cures. It further diminishes managerial authority over fundamental questions of litigation and settlement. IIL and ISDS have also proven capable of muddying rules of agency and authority, creating substantial uncertainty over who speaks for the firm in a cross-border context, and undermining the firm's ability to transact in its own name. This generates uncertainty for states contracting with foreign firms, as well as investors contracting with state-owned entities. All these distortions undercut core features of the corporate form, diminishing the corporation's signal value as an efficient vehicle for coordinating capital in the context of foreign direct investment. And similar concerns arise for other forms of business organization.

Happily, the cases have not tended to distort real property or intellectual property. Thus far tribunals have proven more comfortable with the world of forms than the world of choice. Yet there is little reason to assume these regimes will remain insulated from the kinds of problems of differentiation and fit marking the jurisprudence on contracts and corporations. Particularly in the case of intellectual property, the few landmark cases decided thus far may prove to be outliers, akin to the handful of better reasoned decisions grappling with contracts or corporations. And even now, investors can and do exploit the vagaries of the limited intellectual property jurisprudence to informally inflate their intellectual property rights beyond what is purportedly afforded in national law. The shadow of ISDS litigation is long indeed.

From a private law perspective, then, it appears that ISDS case law has tended to undermine the very values of predictability, stability, and investment promotion that investment treaties are designed to secure—ballooning transaction costs for all parties for no good reason. Even given the most optimistic assumptions about market rationality and information available to states and investors, the tradeoffs posed by prevailing interpretations of investment treaties produce perverse results. If adequately understood and priced in by all concerned parties, these distortions are likely to raise the cost of doing business for states and investors ex ante—particularly to the extent that they cannot be bargained around. And on more realistic assumptions about the (bounded) rationality of these actors, the regime is all the more likely to impose one-sided surprise costs on host states ex post.

The private law critique thus calls attention to myriad problems with the investment treaty regime that the public law approach has generally missed, and even tends to obscure. Moreover, this frame further shows that many of these problems are lose-lose—affecting not only host states (the primary locus of concern for the public lawyers), but also investors, home states, and third parties (including corporate creditors, and non-litigious shareholders). From this vantage point, IIL and ISDS not only undercut equitable distribution and fairness for states. Counterintuitively, they also undercut IIL's own primary values—legal predictability and stability, in the service of promoting efficient foreign direct investment.

Given these pathologies, it remains to consider whether states are doing anything to reform the private dimensions of the regime, and, if not, to begin thinking about what might be done. As noted at the outset, IIL is at an inflection point, with states of all stripes invested in a wide range of reform projects. Yet, while important, the major ongoing reform projects have mostly missed the kinds of private law pathologies identified here. A good part of the problem appears to be that these programs are typically framed in public law terms by both scholars and key reform-minded government actorsFootnote 272—something this Article seeks to redress.

This one-sided public law approach is particularly evident in the unilateral and bilateral efforts toward reforming substantive investment treaty norms since 2010, where the focus has been on including general exceptions clauses or limiting the ambit of particular substantive treaty standards. Although such reforms can alleviate ISDS’ sting, they do little to differentiate between the various species of covered rights and assets, or to cure IIL's distortion of national private law.

Still, there have been some small-scale signs for optimism in recent treaty practice, indicating that some states are beginning to recognize the private law dimensions and pathologies of IIL—at least on a piecemeal basis. A few recently adopted treaties contain differentiated rules for how substantive treaty standards apply to particular types of investment. For example, the Japanese and Canadian BITs generally set special rules for intellectual property claims, clarifying, inter alia, that they do not expand substantive intellectual property protection beyond the bargain reached in the World Trade Organization (WTO) Trade-Related Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPS) Agreement.Footnote 273 Similarly, a handful of treaties incorporate special rules for some state contracts under the rubric of “investment agreements,” adding greater clarity about the relationship between national and international law.Footnote 274 And a few treaties have hesitantly sought to limit the scope of indirect shareholder claims, by introducing minimal equity requirements.Footnote 275 The 2018 amendments to the Korea-U.S. Free Trade Agreement (KORUS) are a rare example where states have gone further to address the reflective loss problem, by mostly closing off the possibility of multiple claims by parents and subsidiaries.Footnote 276 Although these reforms rarely go far toward redressing the problems identified here, they at least hint at their growing salience.

States could go much further, however, by adopting relatively simple treaty design solutions. For example, with respect to the logic of contract, treaties could explicitly indicate that investors and states are free to contract around substantive or procedural treaty terms. As noted above, the CISG does exactly this for sales contracts with a single concise sentence.Footnote 277 Not only would this promote efficient bargaining for both states and investors, it would also empower states to control risks posed by IIL and ISDS to their regulatory autonomy directly, within their contractual relationships. States might also demarcate certain norms as expressly mandatory, or even as sticky defaults with specific rules on how to make opt-out effective. Any express language in this regard would be a substantial boon from the perspective of predictability and efficiency, for both states and investors. Similarly, treaties might include relatively simple provisions to eliminate or defang the perverse consequences of shareholder reflective loss claims—for example by requiring that all recovery go presumptively to the firm (not the shareholder). And with respect to intellectual property and classical property, drafters might take a page from the intellectual property cases to clarify that the scope of such rights turns, primarily, on national law. These examples are just illustrative of the range of drafting possibilities available.

Treaty reform of this sort is difficult to accomplish, due to the sheer number of treaties involved. But given the structural weakness of ISDS as a jurisprudential system, treaty design is likely to be a more fruitful and lasting strategy than waiting for tribunals to start getting it right. Given adequate substantive treaty reforms, IIL might serve as a complement to domestic private law, rather than a distortive interloper.

Although a heavier political lift, the broader multilateral efforts at reforming ISDS also give cause for optimism, and provide a rare window of opportunity. Here too, the efforts at UNCITRAL and elsewhere have tended to be cast in public law terms, with nary a mention of the tradeoffs between ISDS and domestic private law. Yet some of these projects may nevertheless ameliorate the latter concerns. For example, a systematic multilateral investment court (or appellate mechanism) could mitigate the scourge of uncertainty over the treaty/contract relationship. Depending on design choices, it might also remove incentives for investors to bring parallel shareholder claims (through strong provisions on res judicata, lis pendens, and mandatory joinder).Footnote 278 In this sense, the investment court project might prove highly desirable from a private law perspective, even though it is rarely justified in those terms.Footnote 279 However, institutional reform is not a panacea, and could perversely lead to entrenching the distortions of the current jurisprudence instead of removing them—for example, by adopting an inefficiently rigid approach to the treaty/contract question, or endorsing shareholder reflective loss claims. Important as they are, institutional and procedural reforms must be accompanied by substantive treaty reform, whether bilateral or multilateral.

The private law frame reveals substantial pathologies in the investment treaty jurisprudence. IIL distorts domestic private law policy space, as much or more than it undercuts the state's general regulatory autonomy. These problems need to be addressed—not just by litigants and arbitrators, but, much more importantly, by states themselves in designing the next wave of investment treaties. This does not mean that the solutions are necessarily to be found in analogies to domestic private law as opposed to public law, as a magic key to unlocking IIL's optimal tradeoffs. The point is rather that these heuristics are most useful in what they reveal, not in what they prescribe. What is needed, then, is a project of treaty reform sensitive to the pathologies of IIL vis-à-vis both public and private law—a project for which this critique simply lays the groundwork.

Footnotes

I am grateful to José Alvarez, Simon Batifort, Chris Beauchamp, Eyal Benvenisti, Chris Borgen, Jonathan Bonnitcha, Rich Chen, Kathleen Claussen, Hanoch Dagan, Tsilly Dagan, Kevin Davis, Steven Dean, Katharina Pistor, Sergio Puig, Jean Galbraith, James Thuo Gathii, Andrew Gold, Ben Heath, Michael Heller, Rob Howse, Ted Janger, Brian Lee, Lucas Lixinski, Paul Mertenskötter; Christina Mulligan, Julianne Marley, Peggy McGuiness, Sabeel Rahman, Dana Brakman Reiser, Shalev Roisman, Darren Rosenblum, Brandon Ruben, Stephan Schill, Yahli Shereshevsky, Jocelyn Simonson, Alex Stein, Thomas Streinz, and Joseph Weiler for many comments and discussions on earlier drafts. I also thank the anonymous reviewers, from whose comments this piece has greatly benefited. Thanks are also due to Rebecca Meyer and Viola Lee, who provided excellent research assistance.

References

1 I avoid the phrase “private international law”—a term of art mainly encompassing rules regulating conflicts of law and jurisdiction. While not technically inapposite, it does not usually refer to substantive private law (which is largely left to domestic law). To avoid confusion, I use the anodyne expression “international private law” to connote those international legal rules imposing primary substantive and procedural rules of private law on states (and others), regulating property rights, contracts, intellectual property, corporate governance, and so forth. This Article takes no hard stance on whether these rules are better understood as “private international law” or “public international law.”

2 James Crawford, Brownlie's Principles of International Law, 611–14 (8th ed. 2012).

3 See GA Res. 1803 (XVII), “Permanent Sovereignty Over Natural Resources,” Art. 8 (Dec. 14, 1962) (“Foreign investment agreements freely entered into by or between sovereign states shall be observed in good faith.”).

4 Arato, Julian, Corporations as Lawmakers, 56 Harv. J. Int'l L. 229, 260 (2015)Google Scholar.

5 See Arato, Julian, The Logic of Contract in the World of Investment Treaties, 58 Wm. & Mary L. Rev 351 (2016)Google Scholar.

6 See, e.g., Bankswitch v. Ghana, UNCITRAL Award (except for costs) (2014) [hereinafter Bankswitch].

7 See, e.g., CMS Gas v. Argentine Republic, ICSID Case No. ARB/01/8, Jurisdiction, para. 65 (July 17, 2003).

8 See David Gaukrodger, Investment Treaties and Shareholder Claims for Reflective Loss: Insights from Advanced Systems of Corporate Law (OECD Working Papers on International Investment, 2014/02, July 23, 2014), available at http://dx.doi.org/10.1787/5jz0xvgngmr3-en; Vera Korzun, Shareholder Claims for Reflective Loss: How International Investment Law Changes Corporate Law and Governance, 40 U. Penn. J. Int'l L. (forthcoming 2018).

9 See Getma v. Guinea, ICSID Case No. ARB/11/29, Décision sur la Compétence, para. 17 (Dec. 29, 2012) (Fr.) [hereinafter Getma].

10 Dreyfuss, Rochelle & Frankel, Susy, From Incentive to Commodity to Asset: How International Law Is Reconceptualizing Intellectual Property, 36 Mich. J. Int'l L. 557 (2015)Google Scholar; Gathii, James & Ho, Cynthia, Regime Shift of IP Law Making and Enforcement from the WTO to the International Investment Regime, 18 Minn. J. L. Sci. & Tech. 427 (2017)Google Scholar; Yu, Peter K., Cross Fertilizing ISDS with TRIPS, 49 Loy. U. Chi. L.J. 321 (2017)Google Scholar; Liddell, Kathleen & Waibel, Michael, Fair and Equitable Treatment and Judicial Patent Decisions, 19 J. Int'l Econ. L. 145 (2016)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

11 Lauge Poulsen, Bounded Rationality and Economic Diplomacy: The Politics of Investment Treaties in Developing Countries, ch. 2 (2016); Vandevelde, Kenneth, The Bilateral Investment Treaty Program of the United States, 21 Cornell Int'l L.J. 201, 211–13 (1988)Google Scholar.

12 Dani Rodrik, Straight Talk on Trade (2017). A parallel, though less thoroughgoing, development has occurred in human rights law with respect to the right to property. See Alvarez, José, The Human Right of Property, 72 Miami L. Rev. 580 (2018)Google Scholar; Arato, supra note 4.

13 See, e.g., Thomas Picketty, Capital in the Twenty-First Century (Arthur Goldhammer trans., 2017); Dani Rodrik, The Globalization Paradox (2012); Joseph Stiglitz, Globalization and Its Discontents Revisited (2017); See also Howse, Robert, Economics for Progressive International Lawyers, 5 London Rev. Int'l L. 187 (2017)Google Scholar.

14 See, e.g., Kingsbury, Benedict & Schill, Stephan, Public Law Concepts to Balance Investors’ Rights with State Regulatory Actions in the Public Interest: The Concept of Proportionality, in International Investment Law and Comparative Public Law 75 (Schill, Stephan ed., 2010)Google Scholar; Burke-White, William & von Staden, Andreas, Private Litigation in a Public Law Sphere: The Standards of Review in Investor-State Arbitrations, 35 Yale J. Int'l L. 283 (2010)Google Scholar; Gus Van Harten, Investment Treaty Arbitration and Public Law (2007); but see Alvarez, José, Is Investor-State Arbitration Public?, 7 J. Int'l Disp. Settlement 534 (2016)Google Scholar.

15 Not all proponents of the “public law” school of thought deploy the frame in such a totalizing manner. See, for example, the more even-handed work of Stephan Schill and Robert Howse.

16 For example, clarifying and/or limiting the scope of treaty protections, or incorporating general exceptions provisions.

17 For example, via mechanisms for greater control over interpretation, or reworking ISDS. See Puig, Sergio & Shaffer, Gregory, Imperfect Alternatives: Institutional Choice and the Reform of Investment Law, 112 AJIL 361 (2018)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Roberts, Anthea, Incremental, Systemic, and Paradigmatic Reform of Investor-State Arbitration, 112 AJIL 410 (2018)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Howse, Robert, International Investment Law and Arbitration: A Conceptual Framework, in International Law and Litigation (Fabri, H.R. ed., 2017)Google Scholar.

18 See van Aaken, Anne, International Investment Law Between Commitment and Flexibility: A Contract Theory Analysis, 12 J. Int'l Econ. L. 507 (2009)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Jonathan Bonnitcha, Lauge Poulsen & Michael Waibel, The Political Economy of the International Investment Regime (2017).

19 See, e.g., Michael Waibel, Asha Kaushal, Kyo-Hwa Chung & Claire Balchin, The Backlash Against Investment Arbitration: Perceptions and Reality (2010); Bonnitcha, Poulsen & Waibel, supra note 18; UNCITRAL, Report of Working Group III (Reform of Investor-State Dispute Settlement), Thirty-Fifth Sess., UN Doc A/CN.9/935 (April 23–27, 2018) [hereinafter UNCITRAL WGIII Report, 35th Sess.] (compiling government concerns about procedural and structural problems with ISDS).

20 UNCITRAL WGIII Report, 35th Sess., supra note 19, at paras. 20–38.

21 Puig & Shaffer, supra note 17, at n. 31 (discussing withdrawals from ICSID by Bolivia, Ecuador, and Venezuela, and attempts by the latter two to exit numerous BITs). South Africa has also suspended negotiation of new investment treaties. See, e.g., Republic of South Africa, Bilateral Investment Treaty Policy Framework Review: Government Position Paper 12, 12 (2009), available at http://www.pmg.org.za/files/docs/090626trade-bi-lateralpolicy.pdf.

23 See, e.g., EU-Canada Comprehensive and Economic Trade Agreement (CETA), available at http://ec.europa.eu/trade/policy/in-focus/ceta/ceta-chapter-by-chapter; Comprehensive and Progressive Agreement for Trans-Pacific Partnership (CPTPP), available at http://international.gc.ca/trade-commerce/trade-agreements-accords-commerciaux/agr-acc/tpp-ptp/text-texte/09.aspx?lang=eng.

24 UNCITRAL WGIII Report, 35th Sess., supra note 19 (on reforming ISDS multilaterally).

25 See, e.g., Van Harten, supra note 14; Burke-White & von Staden, supra note 14; Kingsbury & Schill supra note 14; Howse, supra note 17.

26 Alvarez, supra note 14.

27 See, e.g., UNCITRAL, Possible Reform of ISDS, Submission from the EU, at 2–3, UN Doc. A/CN.9/WG.III/WP.145 (Dec. 12, 2017), available at https://documents-dds-ny.un.org/doc/UNDOC/LTD/V17/088/32/PDF/V1708832.pdf?OpenElement.

28 See, e.g., Rudolph Dolzer & Christoph Schreuer, Principles of International Investment Law (2d ed. 2012); Zachary Douglas, The International Law of Investment Claims (2009).

29 Max Weber, Economy and Society, Vol. II, at 641 (Guenther Roth & Claus Wittich eds., 1968). This does not mean that public and private law are necessarily completely interchangeable categories. On the specificity of private law, see Hanoch Dagan & Avihay Dorfman, Just Relationships, 116 Colum. L. Rev. 1395 (2016) (conceiving of private law as the law of relationships, establishing frameworks for interactions between free and equal persons).

30 See, e.g., Shubha Ghosh, Patents and the Regulatory State: Rethinking the Patent Bargain Metaphor After Eldred, 19 Berkeley Tech. L.J. 1315 (2004).

31 A few scholars have similarly characterized the regime as a hybrid between public and private law. See Alvarez, supra note 14; Anthea Roberts, Clash of the Paradigms: Actors and Analogies Shaping the Investment Treaty System, 107 AJIL 45, 45 (2013).

32 See, mutatis mutandis, Max Weber, The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism 125 (Talcott Parsons trans., 2005)

33 Weber, supra note 29, at 3–24 (on ideal types) and 641–44 (on public and private law as ideal types). Each type may have some elective affinity toward certain legal doctrines or institutions, but merely affixing one label or the other to a borderline case should not lead mechanically to conclusions about how that case should be resolved. As Dewey notes, abstract descriptions of what a legal entity is tells us nothing about how it ought to be regulated, and may indeed mask the key tradeoffs. John Dewey, The Historical Background of Corporate Legal Personality, 35 Yale L.J. 655, 670–73 (1926).

34 Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, Art. 27, May 23, 1969, 1155 UNTS 331 [hereinafter VCLT]; GA Res. 56/83, Art. 3, Articles on Responsibility of States for Internationally Wrongful Acts (Dec. 12, 2001) (corrected by A/56/49(Vol I)/Corr.4) [hereinafter ARSIWA].

35 On “direct effect” in EU law, see J.H.H. Weiler, The Constitution of Europe 19 (1999).

36 See Convention on the Settlement of Disputes Between States and Nationals of Other States, Mar. 18, 1965, 17 UST 1270, 575 UNTS 159 [hereinafter ICSID Convention]; Convention on the Recognition and Enforcement of Foreign Arbitral Awards, June 10, 1958, 21 UST 2517, 330 UNTS 3 [hereinafter New York Convention].

37 See VCLT, supra note 34, Art. 27; ARSIWA, supra note 34, Art. 3.

38 For example, express contract terms would not properly “conflict” with diverging defaults. See Richard Craswell, Freedom of Contract, at 1–2 (Coase-Sandor Inst. for Law & Econ., Working Paper No. 33, 1995).

39 See, e.g., U.S.-Turkey BIT, Art. 1(c)(i) (“tangible and intangible property, including rights, such as mortgages, liens, and pledges”); UK-Argentina BIT, Art. 1(a)(i) (“movable and immovable property and any other property rights”).

40 Of course, the degree to which the law protects property from state action is of high interest to domestic property theory. Every society must draw this balance, and it touches upon the full range of societal values. See Joseph Singer, Property as the Law of Democracy, 61 Duke L.J. 1287 (2014). Evidently BITs regulate the balance between property protection and regulatory autonomy. Yet the important question of the appropriate level of protection can be settled in myriad ways without denaturing the logic and functions of property law.

41 See Thomas Merrill & Henry Smith, Optimal Standardization in the Law of Property: The Numerus Clausus Principle, 110 Yale L.J. 1 (2000); Henry Hansmann & Reinier Kraakman, Property, Contract, and Verification: The Numerus Clausus Problem and the Divisibility of Rights, 31 J. Legal Stud. S373 (2002); Nestor Davidson, Standardization and Pluralism in Property Law, 61 Vand. L. Rev 1597 (2008).

42 Merrill & Smith, supra note 41, at 3; Davidson, supra note 41, at 1598; Robert Scott & Alan Schwartz, Contract Theory and the Limits of Contract Law, 113 Yale L.J. 541 (2003); Arato, supra note 5, at 399.

43 Merrill & Smith, supra note 41, at 8.

44 Hansmann & Kraakman, supra note 41, at S374.

45 Merrill & Smith, supra note 41, at 8.

46 Excessive individual freedom to dissect and synthesize property forms can also create significant societal costs. See Michael Heller, The Tragedy of the Anticommons: Property in the Transition from Marx to Markets, 111 Harv. L. Rev. 621–88 (1998).

47 Merrill & Smith, supra note 41, at 24.

48 Hansmann & Kraakman, supra note 41, at S374.

49 Davidson, supra note 41, at 1600–01.

50 Id. at 1600.

51 Id. at 1601 (“standardization is a near-universal feature of property systems because the phenomenon facilitates the use of property law to define, control, and regulate the public aspects of private legal relations with respect to things … any given form represents the resolution of the competition between the multiple and often clashing ends that property serves”); Hanoch Dagan, Property: Institutions and Values (2011). See also Singer, supra note 40, at 1303.

52 Douglas, supra note 28, at 52.

53 See, e.g., Emmis v. Hungary, ICSID Case No. ARB/12/2, Award, para.162 (Apr. 16, 2014) (“Public international law does not create property rights. Rather it accords certain protections to property rights created according to municipal law.”); Douglas, supra note 28, at 52.

54 Arguably, however, the uncertainty inherent in IIL and ISDS increases the cost of coordination and verification substantially for states in determining whose property is entitled to international protection. Such concerns are likely to become significant in view of various methods of treaty shopping. See Arato, supra note 4, at 275; Simon Batifort & J. Benton Heath, The New Debate on the Interpretation of MFN Clauses in Investment Treaties: Putting the Brakes on Multilateralization, 111 AJIL 873 (2018).

55 Dolzer & Schreuer, supra note 28; Crawford, supra note 2, at 614. But see Poulsen, supra note 11 (demonstrating that, in practice, officials responsible for executing BITs in developing countries often lack adequate information about these treaties’ tradeoffs).

56 Davidson, supra note 41, at 1601; Singer, supra note 40, at 1303.

57 Arato, supra note 4, at 260; Dagan, Hanoch & Dorfmann, Avihay, The Human Right to Private Property, 18 Theoretical Inquiries L. 391, 393 (2017)Google Scholar; Douglas, Zachary, Property, Investment, and the Scope of Investment Protection Obligations, in The Foundations of International Investment Law: Bringing Theory into Practice 363 (Douglas, Zachary, Pauwelyn, Joost & Viñuales, Jorge E. eds., 2014)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; see also Perrone, Nicolás, The Emerging Global Right to Investment: Understanding the Reasoning Behind Foreign Investor Rights, 8 J. Int'l Disp. Settlement 673 (2017)Google Scholar. See generally Dagan, supra note 51.

58 See, e.g., Philip Morris v. Uruguay, ICSID Case No. ARB/10/7, Award, para. 423 (July 8, 2016) [hereinafter Philip Morris v. Uruguay]; Mesa Power Grp., LLC v. Gov't of Can., PCA Case No. 2012-17, Award, para. 502 (Mar. 24, 2016) [hereinafter Mesa Power v. Canada] (limiting the scope of “legitimate expectations” protection). Recent treaties and model BITs have also set heavy presumptions against recovery for regulatory takings. See Howse, supra note 17.

59 Merrill & Smith, supra note 41, at 8.

60 Dagan, supra note 51, at xvii–xviii.

61 See, e.g., Been, Vicki & Beauvais, Joel, The Global Fifth Amendment? NAFTA’s Investment Protections and the Misguided Quest for an International ‘Regulatory Takings’ Doctrine, 78 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 30, 6364 (2003)Google Scholar.

62 See Merrill & Smith, supra note 41; Hansmann & Kraakman, supra note 41.

63 As Hale notes, American law protects a property holder's vested rights and legitimate expectations “from some vicissitudes” but “leaves them exposed to many others—such as competition, the constitutional exercise of the police power, [and] the increase in the cost of operation.” Hale, Robert, Coercion and Distribution in a Supposedly Non-coercive State, 38 Pol. Sci. Q. 470, 489 (1923)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. National systems vary widely in how far such protection goes. One purpose of investment treaties is to set certain minimums, and this is not necessarily distortive. But a difference of degree could eventually become a difference in kind. Pushed far enough, an absolutist approach to protecting expectations would arguably erode the nature of property law, for example by insuring foreign property against any diminution of value caused by regulatory change. See Been & Beauvais, supra note 61. Still, with the arguable exception of a handful of early awards (like Metalclad v. Mexico and Tecmed v. Mexico), ISDS rarely goes so far—and indeed seems to be going in the opposite direction.

64 See, e.g., Japan-Israel BIT, Art. 1(a) (“The term ‘investment’ means every kind of asset … including (v) rights under contracts, including turnkey, construction, management, production, or revenue-sharing contracts; [and] (vi) claims to money and to any performance under contract having a financial value.”); US-Turkey BIT, Art. 1(c) (“every kind of investment … [including] service and investment contracts … (iii) a claim to money or a claim to performance having economic value, and associated with an investment … [and] (v) any right conferred by law or contract”).

65 Hanoch Dagan & Michael Heller, The Choice Theory of Contracts (2017); Scott & Schwartz, supra note 42; Merrill & Smith, supra note 41, at 8.

66 Dagan & Heller supra note 65, at 109; Mariana Pargendler, The Role of the State in Contract Law: The Common-Civil Law Divide, 43 Yale J. Int'l L. 143, 146 (2018).

67 Robert Scott & Jody Kraus, Contract Law and Theory 2–4 (2013); Robin Bradley Kar, Contract as Empowerment, 83 U. Chi. L. Rev. 759 (2016).

68 Charles Goetz & Robert Scott, The Mitigation Principle: Toward a General Theory of Contractual Obligation, 69 Va. L. Rev. 967, 971 (1983).

69 Ayres, Ian & Gertner, Robert, Filling Gaps in Incomplete Contracts: An Economic Theory of Default Rules, 99 Yale L.J. 87, 91 (1989)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

70 Goetz & Scott, supra note 68, at 971.

71 See, e.g., UCC 2-305.

72 Arato, supra note 5, at 400–01. See Dagan & Heller supra note 65, at 5, 49–65; Scott & Schwartz, supra note 42; Craswell, Richard, Contract Law, Default Rules, and the Philosophy of Promising, 88 Mich. L. Rev. 489, 490 (1989)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

73 Goetz & Scott, supra note 68, at 971.

74 See Ayres & Gertner, supra note 69, at 91.

75 For example, U.S. jurisdictions prefer defaults, while European jurisdictions make broader use of mandatory rules, reflecting different mixes of social values and priorities. See Aditi Bagchi, The Political Economy of Regulating Contract, 62 Am. J. Comp. L. 687 (2014); Pargendler, supra note 66, at 146 (explaining that in civil law countries, “the State … goes further in providing and policing the substantive terms of the agreement to ensure compliance with broader social values and objectives”).

76 See Pargendler, supra note 66, at 155.

77 Id. at 155; Scott & Schwartz, supra note 42, at 569.

78 Pargendler, supra note 66, at 154–55; Ian Ayres, Regulating Opt-Out: An Economic Theory of Altering Rules, 121 Yale L.J. 2032, 2045.

79 See, e.g., Dagan & Heller, supra note 65 at 4, 111–13; Ayres, supra note 78, 2045, 2095–96.

80 See Ayres, supra note 78, at 2098.

81 Arato, supra note 5, at 372–92.

82 Campbell McLachlan, Laurence Shore & Matthew Weiniger, International Investment Arbitration: Substantive Principles, para. 7.04 (2d ed. 2017).

83 Compare Enron v. Argentine Republic, ICSID Case No. ARB/01/3, Award, paras. 260–61 (May 22, 2007) [hereinafter Enron Award] (fair and equitable treatment entails a strong obligation of legal stabilization), with Philip Morris v. Uruguay, para. 423 (fair and equitable treatment entails only a weak stabilization protection against general legislation), and Mesa Power v. Canada, para. 502 (“failure to respect an investor's legitimate expectations in and of itself does not constitute a breach of [fair and equitable treatment under the NAFTA], but is an element to take into account when assessing whether other components of the standard are breached”). See also Dolzer & Schreuer, supra note 28, at 82–85.

84 See Rudolf Dolzer, Fair and Equitable Treatment: Today's Contours, 12 Santa Clara J. Int'l L. 7, 25–26 (2013); Moshe Hirsch, Between Fair and Equitable Treatment and Stabilization Clause: Stable Legal Environment and Regulatory Change in International Law, 12 J. World Inv. & Trade 783, 805–06 (2011).

85 Sempra Energy v. Argentine Republic, ICSID Case No. ARB/02/16, Award (Sept. 28, 2007) [hereinafter Sempra Award]; Enron Award; CMS Gas v. Argentine Republic, ICSID Case No. ARB/01/8, Award (May 12, 2005) [hereinafter CMS Gas Award]. See generally José E. Alvarez & Kathryn Khamsi, The Argentine Crisis and Foreign Investors: A Glimpse into the Heart of the Investment Regime, in Yearbook on International Investment Law & Policy 2008–2009, at 379 (Karl P. Sauvant ed., 2009).

86 Each tribunal noted that the state might not be under a total stabilization requirement, but none clarified how far the requirement goes. See CMS Gas Award, para. 277; Sempra Award, para. 300; Enron Award, para. 261.

87 See Sempra Award, para. 310.

88 Arato, supra note 5, at 383–84, 394; James Crawford, Treaty and Contract in Investment Treaty Arbitration, 24 Arb. Int'l 351, 373 (2008) (“treaties and contracts are different things. But they are not clean different things”).

89 Arato, supra note 5, at 394; Crawford, supra note 88, at 373 (“The relevance of legitimate expectations is not a license to arbitral tribunals to rewrite the freely negotiated terms of investment contracts.”).

90 Parkerings-Compagniet AS v. Lithuania, ICSID Case No. ARB/05/8, Award, para. 332 (Sept. 11, 2007) (finding that fair and equitable treatment does not impose broad stabilization requirements, but merely amorphously obliges the state to not use its legislative power “unfairly, unreasonably or inequitably”).

91 Id.

92 Parkerings leaves unsaid whether fair and equitable treatment can be ratcheted down. See also EDF Servs. Ltd. v. Romania, ICSID Case No. ARB/05/13, Award, para. 217 (Oct. 8, 2009); Philip Morris v. Uruguay, para. 423.

93 MNSS v. Montenegro, ICSID Case No. ARB(AF)/12/8, Award (May 4, 2016).

94 Id., para. 149

95 Id., para. 163.

96 Id., para. 159 (accepting waiver of fair and equitable treatment claims over matters covered by the contract, but not of those involving interference with the investment not envisioned by the contract).

97 Id., paras. 163–64.

98 See SGS v. Paraguay, ICSID Case No. ARB/07/29, Decision on Jurisdiction, paras. 131, 138–42 (Feb. 12, 2010) [hereinafter SGS v. Paraguay, Jurisdiction].

99 Id., paras. 177–84.

100 See, e.g., Vivendi I, ICSID Case No. ARB/97/3, Decision on Annulment, paras. 101–03 (2002).

101 SGS v. Philippines, ICSID Case No. ARB/02/6, Decision of the Tribunal on Objections to Jurisdiction, para. 128 (Jan. 29, 2004) [hereinafter SGS v. Philippines]; BIVAC v. Paraguay, ICSID Case No. ARB/07/9, Jurisdiction, para. 142 (May 29, 2009).

102 Oxus Gold v. Uzbekistan, UNCITRAL, Final Award, para. 958(ii) (Dec. 17, 2015) (recognizing contractual waiver of ISDS jurisdiction over counterclaims); Getma, para. 17 (permitting waiver of ISDS in an expropriation case under the Guinean investment law, which incorporated IIL by reference).

103 Aguas del Tunari v. Bolivia, ICSID Case No. ARB/02/3, Decision on Jurisdiction, paras. 119, 122 (Oct. 21, 2005) [hereinafter Aguas del Tunari, Jurisdiction]; see also Occidental v. Ecuador, ICSID Case No. ARB/06/11, Decision on Jurisdiction, paras. 71–74 (Sept. 9, 2008).

104 Crystallex v. Venezuela, ICSID Case No. ARB(AF)/11/2, Award, para. 481 (Apr. 4, 2016) [hereinafter Crystallex].

105 Id. (The tribunal did not explain why it considered the quite ordinary practice of opt-out to be “unusual in economic transactions.”).

106 Id., para. 482.

107 Id.

108 See Arato, supra note 5, at 377–78; Ayres & Gertner, supra note 69, at 91.

109 See Christopher Serkin, Public Entrenchment Through Private Law: Binding Local Governments, 78 U. Chi. L. Rev. 879, 916 (2011); Daniel Fischel & Alan Sykes, Government Liability for Breach of Contract, 1 Am. L. & Econ. Rev. 313, 316 (1999).

110 See Dagan & Heller supra note 65, at 100.

111 See Serkin, supra note 109, at 894–96; Arato, supra note 5, at 388.

112 See Pierre-Yves Tschanz & Jorge Viñuales, Compensation for Non-expropriatory Breaches of International Investment Law: The Contribution of the Argentine Awards, 26 J. Int'l Arb. 729, 729–30 (2009). Expropriation provisions often provide for fair market value compensation, but fair and equitable treatment and other provisions typically say nothing about damages. See Sergey Ripinsky & Kevin Williams, Damages In International Investment Law 78–79 (2008).

113 See Factory at Chorzów (Ger. v. Pol.), Merits, 1928 PCIJ (ser. A) No. 17, at 47 (Sept. 13).

114 Id.

115 Arato, supra note 5, at 388.

116 I owe this neat phrase to a helpful discussion with Gregory Klass and Carlos Vasquez.

117 Venezuela Holdings v. Venezuela, ICSID Case No. ARB/07/27, Award (Oct. 9, 2014) [hereinafter ExxonMobil Award].

118 See also Argentine Gas cases, discussed infra; Arato, supra note 5, at 389–90.

119 ExxonMobil Award, para. 225.

120 See CISG, Art. 6. (Private parties to a covered sales contract “may exclude the application of this Convention or, subject to article 12, derogate from or vary the effect of any of its provisions.”).

121 ConocoPhillips v. Venezuela, ICSID Case No. ARB/07/30, Dissenting Opinion of Georges Abi-Saab to Decision on Jurisdiction and Merits, paras. 34–37 (Feb. 19, 2015) (concerning similar compensation clauses in a related concession).

122 Venezuela Holdings v. Venezuela, ICSID Case No. ARB/07/27, Decision on Annulment, paras. 181–83 (2017) [hereinafter ExxonMobil Annulment].

123 Id., para. 184 (“at no stage does the Tribunal give any consideration to what relevance the limitations on the investors’ rights embodied in the Price Cap might actually have to the application of the mandatory criteria laid down in the BIT for compensation”).

124 Id., para. 187.

125 See Siag v. Egypt, ICSID Case No. ARB/05/15, Award, paras. 577–84 (June 1, 2009).

126 Kardassopoulos v. Georgia, ICSID Case Nos. ARB/05/18 and ARB/07/15, Award, paras. 480–81 (Mar. 3, 2010).

127 But see SGS v. Philippines; ExxonMobil, Annulment; ConocoPhillips, Dissenting Opinion of Georges Abi-Saab. Some scholars have suggested that the matter turns on the broader debate on whether investment treaties are better understood as conferring direct rights or derivative rights on foreign investors. See Douglas, supra note 28, at 17–19; Bart Duijzentkunst, Treaty Rights as Tradeable Assets: Can Investors Waive Investment Treaty Protection?, 25 ICSID Rev. 409 (2010); see also Roberts, Anthea, Triangular Treaties: The Extent and Limits of Investment Treaty Rights, 56 Harv. Int'l L.J. 353, 355 (2015)Google Scholar; Paparinskis, Martins, Investment Arbitration and the Law of Countermeasures, 79 Brit. Y.B. Int'l L. 264 (2008)Google Scholar. However, the question of opt-out cannot be neatly settled by appeal to first principles in this way. Either direct or derivative rights could be structured in default or mandatory form—to allow, encourage, or bar opt-out by investors and states. The treaties are simply silent on this matter, and the cases are highly ambiguous.

128 UNCITRAL WGIII Report, 35th Sess., supra note 19; Franck, Susan, The Legitimacy Crisis in Investment Treaty Arbitration: Privatizing Public International Law Through Inconsistent Decisions, 73 Fordham L. Rev. 1521 (2005)Google Scholar.

129 See Coase, Ronald, The Problem of Social Cost, 3 J. L. & Econ. 1, 15 (1960)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

130 Though the empirical work remains to be done, one can cautiously extrapolate from Poulsen's study of treaty negotiation by developing countries that similar problems of bounded rationality are likely to arise in the context of government contracting. See Poulsen, supra note 11.

131 See Arato, supra note 5, at 397.

132 Id.

133 Sticky defaults may also be ineffective under current institutional arrangements, because they require jurisprudential coherence. It is easy enough for an ISDS tribunal to declare ex post that, were the parties serious about opt-out, they would have used special words to indicate their intent. But parties must have some way of knowing the magic words ex ante. Absent a system of precedent, or clear (and excessively intricate) treaty drafting, it will be difficult for states and investors to predict which words and phrases will make opt out effective.

134 Dagan & Heller supra note 65, at 110; Ayres, supra note 78, at 2098.

135 Nations vary widely in how far they interfere with choice in this respect. Pargendler, supra note 66, at 155.

136 Ghana Const. Art. 181(5).

137 Banskwitch, para. 11.83.

138 Id., paras. 11.73–.75.

139 Id., paras. 2.2–.3.

140 Id., paras. 11.62–.64.

141 Id., n. 346.

142 Id., para. 11.78.

143 Id., paras. 11.59, 11.70.

144 Id., para. 11.81.

145 Bankswitch was a hard case. Both parties had real grievances. The company was induced, and given assurances that its contract was valid without parliamentary approval by the highest officials of the government. But this was bad advice, given by those exact officials Article 181(5) was meant to constrain. In fact, it was the same executive branch that induced the contract, assured its validity, and ultimately proclaimed its invalidity after coming to regret the arrangement. Enforcing the constitutional provision strictly would not be entirely fair to Bankswitch, ex post. But it was still the better option. Enforcing the contract meant vitiating the constitutional provision, and constraining the state's ability to manage corruption at the constitutional level. Nor is the tribunal persuasive in suggesting that expecting foreign investors to review express constitutional requirements for contracts would demand overly burdensome due diligence. Ultimately Bankswitch embodies Holmes's adage, that “hard cases make bad law.” Northern Securities Co v. United States, 193 U.S. 197, 400 (1904) (Holmes, J., dissenting).

146 See, e.g., Japan-Israel BIT, Art. 1(a) (“the term ‘investment’ means every kind of asset … owned or controlled, directly or indirectly, by an investor, including: (i) an enterprise and a branch of an enterprise; [and] (ii) shares, stocks, and other forms of equity participation in an investment …”); US-Turkey BIT, Art. 1(c) (“‘investment’ means every kind of investment owned or controlled directly or indirectly, including equity, debt … (ii) a company or shares, stock or other interests in a company or interests in the assets thereof”). Because most treaties cover indirect shares, their coverage potentially extends to long parent-subsidiary chains.

147 Where the firm is foreign, both it and its shareholders arguably enjoy separate treaty coverage. See infra, II.C.1.

148 For brevity, I limit the discussion to corporations—but analogous problems arise for other organizational forms.

149 Gaukrodger, supra note 8. See generally John Armour, Henry Hansmann, Reinier Kraakman & Mariana Pargendler, What Is Corporate Law?, in John Armour, et al., The Anatomy of Corporate Law: A Comparative and Functional Approach 1, 1 (3d ed. 2017).

150 Armour et al., supra note 149, at 5.

151 Id. at 1–2.

152 Id. at 1.

153 Gaukrodger, supra note 8, at 10.

154 Armour et al., supra note 149, at 2.

155 Id.

156 National corporate laws also vary in how far they enshrine values external to firm efficiency, “such as reducing systemic risk, mitigating gender inequity, or protecting the environment.” Armour, et. al, supra note 149, at 24. See also Aaron Dhir, Challenging Boardroom Homogeneity: Corporate Law, Governance, and Diversity, chs. 4–5 (2015).

157 Armour et al., supra note 149, at 5.

158 Id. at 5–7.

159 See Armour, et al., supra note 149, at 8.

160 Id. at 5–6.

161 See Hansmann, Henry, Kraakman, Reinier & Squire, Richard, Law and the Rise of the Firm, 119 Harv. L. Rev. 1335 (2006)Google Scholar.

162 Exit must rather be accomplished by sale of shares. See Armour, et al., supra note 149, at 6.

163 Id. at 6.

164 Id. at 7.

165 Id.

166 Gaukrodger, supra note 8, at 23.

167 Armour, et al., supra note 149, at 7–8.

168 Only a very small handful of treaties limit coverage for shareholdings. See, e.g., Turkey-Azerbaijan BIT, Art. 1 (2011) (excluding shareholdings below 10%).

169 Japan-Israel BIT, Arts. 1(a), 24(2).

170 Gaukrodger, supra note 8, at 7.

171 David Gaukrodger, Investment Treaties as Corporate Law: Shareholder Claims and Issues of Consistency, at 19–20 (OECD Working Papers on International Investment, 2013/03, 2013), available at http://www.oecd.org/investment/investment-policy/WP-2013_3.pdf.

172 Id. at 14–17 (finding that U.S., UK, Australian, German, French, and Japanese corporate laws all bar shareholder reflective loss claims).

173 See Barcelona Traction, 1970 ICJ Rep. 3, 38, 44 (Feb. 5) (finding that diplomatic protection does not generally extend to claims for shareholder reflective loss, though remaining open to equitable exceptions, or exceptions in lex specialis); Ahmadou Sadio Diallo (Guinea v. Dem. Rep. Congo), Preliminary Objections, 2007 ICJ Rep. 582, 605–06 (May 24).

174 See, e.g., Olczak v. Poland, ECtHR App. No. 30417/96, paras. 57–58 (Nov. 7, 2002).

175 Gaukrodger, supra note 171, at 24.

176 Id. at 33.

177 See, e.g., CMS Gas, Jurisdiction, para. 65; Enron v. Argentine Republic, ICSID Case No. ARB/01/3, Decision on Jurisdiction, para. 49 (Jan. 14, 2004); Christoph Schreuer, Shareholder Protection in International Investment Law, 3 Transnat'l Disp. Mgmt. 4 (2005); Douglas, supra note 28, at 455.

178 Impregilo v. Argentina, ICSID Case No. ARB/07/17, Award, para. 138 (June 21, 2011); See also Campbell McLachlan, Laurence Shore & Matthew Weiniger, International Investment Arbitration: Substantive Principles, §§ 6.77, 6.79 (1st ed. 2007) (“Given the wide definition of investment … there is no conceptual reason to prevent an investor recovering for damage caused to those shares which has resulted in a diminution in their value.”).

179 See, e.g., Enron, Jurisdiction, para. 49.

180 Indirect equity refers to an ownership stake in a firm held through a (potentially limitless) chain of companies. The “indirect” owner herself holds no formal shares in the local corporation actually engaged in the investment, but has an indirect stake in it through ownership of shares in an intermediary company that itself holds shares in the local entity. Most tribunals read BITs as allowing any entity in the chain to bring claims against the host state as indirect shareholders, in parallel to any direct shareholder claims and the local firm's own claim (if any)—all over the same alleged harm. See Ampal-American Israel Corp. v. Egypt, ICSID Case No. ARB/12/11, Decision on Jurisdiction, para. 343 (Feb. 1, 2016) [hereinafter Ampal] (refusing to “read into the Treaty restrictions … [on] ‘passive, indirect and very small’ holdings).”

181 Gaukrodger, supra note 8, at 25.

182 VCLT, Art. 31(3)(c) requires tribunals to take into account “other relevant rules of international law applicable in the relations among the parties,” which includes customary international law and general principles of law. See Campbell McLachlan, The Principle of Systemic Integration and Article 31(3)(c) of the Vienna Convention, 54 Int'l & Comp. L. Q. 279 (2005); Julian Arato, Constitutional Transformation in the ECtHR: Strasbourg's Expansive Recourse to External Rules of International Law, 37 Brook. J. Int'l L. 349 (2012). Where tribunals have recognized that general international law bars shareholder reflective loss claims, they have insisted that BITs are lex specialis. See CMS Gas, Jurisdiction, para. 48; and Enron, Jurisdiction, para. 34. However, this argument still rests on an unstable assumption that BITs clearly authorize shareholder reflective loss as a matter of text, object and purpose, etc.

183 Such uniformity arguably indicates a general principle of international law. But see Teinver S.A. v. Argentine Republic, ICSID Case No. ARB/09/1, Jurisdiction, para. 212 (Dec. 21, 2012) (“refus[ing] to take their cues from domestic corporate law”).

184 North American Free Trade Agreement, Art. 1139, entered into force Jan. 1, 1994, Pub. L. No. 103-182, 107 Stat. 2057 (1993) [hereinafter NAFTA].

185 See also CPTPP, Arts. 9.19 (separating types of shareholder claims), 9.28 (incorporating joinder procedures); CETA, Arts. 8.22 (extending waiver rules to cover both the foreign shareholder and a locally incorporated enterprise), and 8.43 (incorporating joinder procedures).

186 The NAFTA parties have also argued that permitting minority shareholders to bring shareholder reflective loss claims under 1116 would render 1117 largely superfluous. See Bilcon v. Canada, PCA Case No. 2009-04, Canadian Counter-Memorial on Damages, para. 26 (June 9, 2017) (allowing shareholder reflective loss “undermines one of the most fundamental rules of corporate law in all three NAFTA Parties… . [This] will weaken the corporation's separate legal personality, create unpredictability for investors, creditors, banks, and others who participate in the foreign direct investment market, create unfair conditions of competition among these different sorts of investors, and hence, inevitably decrease the opportunities for investment in the NAFTA Parties.”); GAMI v. Mexico, Submission of the United States, para. 17 (June 20, 2003); GAMI v. Mexico, Escrito de Contestación of Mexico, para. 167 (Nov. 24, 2003).

187 See, e.g., Mondev Int'l v. United States, ICSID Case No. ARB(AF)/99/2, Award, paras. 84–86 (Oct. 11, 2002) (highlighting the interests of creditors).

188 GAMI v. Mexico, Award, paras. 120–21 (Nov. 15, 2004) (acknowledging the policy tradeoffs); Pope & Talbot v. Canada, Award in Respect of Damages, paras. 75–76 (May 31, 2002).

189 Gaukrodger, supra note 171, at 30.

190 NAFTA, Art. 1117.

191 See, e.g. US-Argentina BIT, Art. VII(8); US-Turkey BIT, Art. VI(6). See also Energy Charter Treaty, Art. 26(7) (taking a narrower approach, including only local companies controlled by nationals of another party).

192 See Eskosol S.p.A. in Liquidazione v. Italian Republic, ICSID Case No. ARB/15/50, Decision on Respondent's Application Under Rule 41(5) (Mar. 20, 2017) (allowing both a local company claim (Eskosol), and a separate shareholder reflective loss claim (Blusun v. Italy)).

193 Enron, Jurisdiction, para. 49; Eskosol, para. 170; but see Orascom, discussed below.

194 CME v. Czech Republic, UNCITRAL, Final Award, para. 436 (Mar. 14, 2003).

195 Though the cases are much vilified, the respondent notably refused the investor's request to join the proceedings, which both tribunals held against it in allowing parallel claims. Ronald Lauder v. Czech Republic, UNCITRAL, Final Award, para. 178 (Sept. 3, 2001) [hereinafter Lauder]; CME, paras. 428–29; see also Ampal, Jurisdiction, para. 329.

196 CME, para. 436; Lauder, para. 172.

197 Grynberg v. Grenada, ICSID Case No. ARB/05/14, Award, para. 7.1.6 (Mar. 13, 2009).

198 Ampal, Jurisdiction, para. 331; Ampal, Liability, paras. 11–12.

199 Orascom TMT Investments. v. Algeria, ICSID Case No. ARB/12/35, Award, para. 547 (May 31, 2017).

200 Orascom, para. 542 (my emphasis).

201 In the tribunal's view, the first suit, by the direct shareholder in the local company, “crystalized” the dispute, blocking the controlling shareholder from making further claims. Orascom, paras. 496, 523–24, 543. This “crystallization” theory is troubling, since, for reasons discussed below, the local entity's claim should be superior to that of its direct controlling shareholder's—irrespective of timing—especially given that the local entity enjoyed BIT protection in its own right.

202 Orascom, para. 543 n. 836.

203 Gaukrodger, supra note 8, at 20.

204 Id.; Korzun, supra note 8, at 6.

205 Saul Levmore & Hideki Kanda, Explaining Creditor Priorities, 80 Va. L. Rev. 2103, 2123 (1994).

206 Armour et al., supra note 149, at 6–7.

207 Douglas, supra note 28, at 456.

208 Gaukrodger, supra note 8, at 23–25.

209 Id. at 20; Douglas, supra note 28, at 455.

210 Douglas, supra note 28, at 455.

211 See Eskosol, para. 170; GAMI v. Mexico, paras. 120–21; but see Mondev, paras. 84–86

212 Armour et al., supra note 149, at 8.

213 See Armour, John and Whincop, Michael, The Proprietary Foundations of Corporate Law, 27 Oxford J. Legal Stud. 429, 444–47 (2007)CrossRefGoogle Scholar (arguing that authority rules necessarily trade off due diligence costs against preserving owners’ flexibility to delineate authority as they see fit).

214 Armour et al., supra note 149, 8, 11; Otto Sandrock, Arbitration Agreements and Groups of Companies, in Festschrift Pierre Lalive, 625, 640 et seq. (1993).

215 See Rose, Carol, Crystals and Mud in Property Law, 40 Stan. L. Rev. 577, 578 (1988)CrossRefGoogle Scholar (distinguishing between crystalline and muddy rules—the former being bright, clear, and rigid, and the latter leaving judges substantial ex post discretion).

216 See, e.g., CCL v. Kazakhstan, SCC Case 122/2001, Award (Jan. 1, 2004).

217 Getma, para. 17 (Fr.) (translations by author); Standard Charter Bank v. Tanzania, ICSID Case No. ARB/10/12, Award paras. 92–96, 160–61 (Nov. 2, 2012) (examining whether the agents of a local power company—the investment—had proper authority to restructure its debt); Philip Morris v. Uruguay, paras. 62–64, 92–95.

218 Rose, supra note 215, at 578.

219 Getma, para. 17. This claim was brought under Guinea's foreign investment law, which provided for ISDS. However, Getma and cases like it tend to conflate foreign investment law claims with treaty claims. On the relationship of national investment laws to IIL and ISDS, see Hepburn, Jarrod, Domestic Investment Statutes in International Law, 112 AJIL 658 (2018)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

220 Id., para. 97.

221 NCT Necotrans, the parent, wholly owned the other three, including Getma International (the concessionaire). Id., para. 26. NCT Necotrans was a société anonyme (i.e. a corporation), while the other three were sociétés par actions simplifiée (similar to the American LLC). Id., paras. 1–4.

222 The group of companies doctrine is not universally accepted. See Sandrock, supra note 214, at 629 (noting its acceptance in France and Germany, but not Switzerland or the UK). In its most famous formulation in Dow Chemical, the theory turned on: (1) a high degree of central control within the group (here absolute control by the parent); (2) the non-signatories playing some significant role “in the conclusion, performance, or termination of the contract”; and (3) the “mutual intention of all parties.” Dow Chemical, ICC Award No. 4131, Interim Award of Sept. 23, 1982, YCA 1984, at 131, 136; confirmed by the Paris Court of Appeal in CA Paris, Oct. 21, 1983, Société Isover-Saint-Gobain v. Société Dow Chemical France, [1984] Rev. Arb. 98, at 100–01.

223 See Sandrock, supra note 214, at 639–45. This doctrine is not always formally housed under the rubric of apparent authority, even if that is the best way to understand its function. Notably, U.S. law deals with the problem of corporate groups under the rubric of alter ego or veil piercing, rather than apparent authority. See Fisser v. Int'l Bank, 282 F.2d 231, 235 (2d Cir. 1960).

224 Getma, para. 58. Selection of the CCJA means that OHADA law governs the arbitration agreement. OHADA is a West African international organization, which enacts supranational commercial law with direct effect in its seventeen member states. The CCJA is OHADA’s apex court. See generally Claire Moore Dickinson, The OHADA Common Court of Justice and Arbitration: Exogenous Forces Contributing to Its Influence, 79 L. & Contemp. Probs. 63, 65 (2016). Thus, unlike most arbitral institutions, the CCJA is itself an arbitral seat, with its own system of substantive law, including rules on apparent authority.

225 Getma, paras. 82–83, citing CME, para. 436 (“a ‘company group’ theory is not generally accepted in international arbitration”).

226 Getma, paras. 82–83.

227 One would expect this analysis to follow normal conflict of laws rules. See, e.g., Dicey, Morris & Collins on the Conflict of Laws, Vol. II, 33R-432, 33-436 (Lord Collins of Mapesbury ed., 15th ed. 2012) (while actual authority is determined by the law of incorporation, the applicable national law for determining apparent authority is the law of the contract (or, if severable, the law of the arbitration agreement)); Sandrock, supra note 214, at 633.

228 Getma, para. 154.

229 Id., para. 169.

230 Id., para. 153 (“it is not enough to note that the … applicants all belong to the same corporate group and have common management”).

231 Id., para. 159.

232 Id., para. 174.

233 Id., para. 177.

234 Compare Fisser (2d Cir.) with Dow Chemicals (Paris CA).

235 See, e.g., Dicey, Morris & Collins, supra note 227 (apparent authority is normally determined under the law of the contract); Sandrock supra note 214, at 633.

236 Arato, supra note 4.

237 Id., at 279–83. See Tokios Tekeles v. Ukraine, ICSID Case No. ARB/02/18, Dissenting Opinion of President Prosper Weil, para. 21 (Apr. 29, 2004) (challenging the majority's unexplained presumption against veil-piercing in the context of nationality shopping, which led the tribunal to permit Ukrainian nationals to indirectly invoke ISDS against their own state of nationality under the Lithuania-Ukraine BIT, via a 99% owned Lithuanian holding company).

238 Arato, supra note 4, at 279–83.

239 See, e.g., Philip Morris v. Australia, PCA Case No. 2012-12, Award on Jurisdiction and Admissibility (Dec. 17, 2015) (the investor must, however, secure the requisite nationality before a dispute arises).

240 See Aguas del Tunari, Jurisdiction; ConocoPhillips, Jurisdiction.

241 Korzun, supra note 8.

242 See Ghosh, supra note 30.

243 Including the WTO-TRIPS, Paris, and Berne Conventions.

244 For example, Iran is not a party to the WTO, and thus not party to the TRIPS Agreement.

245 One major exception is that BITs have allowed investors to bootstrap non-justiciable guarantees under various intellectual property treaties into ISDS, as part of the expropriation and fair and equitable treatment analysis. See Gathii & Ho, supra note 10; Henning Grosse Ruse-Khan, Challenging Compliance with International Intellectual Property Norms in Investor-State Arbitration, 19 J. Int'l Econ. L. 241 (2016).

246 For example, tobacco companies have deployed the threat of ISDS to pressure states to water down tobacco control regulations, often succeeding without embarking on litigation. Sarah Boseley, Threats, Bullying, Lawsuits: Tobacco Industry's Dirty War for the African Market, Guardian (July 12, 2017), at https://www.theguardian.com/world/2017/jul/12/big-tobacco-dirty-war-africa-market. As Puig notes, Big Tobacco's ability to wield IIL and ISDS in this way turns at least in part on ambiguity over how far ISDS will inflate (and distort) national intellectual property protection. Puig, Sergio, Tobacco Litigation in International Courts, 57 Harv. J. Int'l L. 383, 412 (2016)Google Scholar; see generally Galanter, Marc The Radiating Effects of Courts, in Empirical Theories about Courts, 121 (Boyum, Keith O. & Mater, Lynn eds., 1983)Google Scholar; Mnookin, Robert & Kornhauser, Lewis, Bargaining in the Shadow of the Law: The Case of Divorce, 88 Yale L.J. 950 (1979)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

247 Philip Morris v. Uruguay; Eli Lilly v. Canada, ICSID Case No. UNCT/14/2, Final Award (Mar. 16, 2017). A few other trademark claims have yet to be resolved. See, e.g., Bridgestone v. Panama, ICSID Case No. ARB/16/34, Request for Arbitration (Oct. 7, 2016) (claiming denial of justice and discrimination over a ruling by the Supreme Court of Panama ordering Bridgestone to pay damages for allegedly “reckless” challenges to a locally registered trademark).

248 The same can be said for other cases which have cursorily considered more tangential intellectual property claims. See, e.g., AHS v. Niger, para. 154 (Fr.) (dismissing an ancillary trademarks claim for lack of evidence of consumer confusion). See generally Ruse-Khan, supra note 245.

249 Philip Morris v. Uruguay, paras. 108–32.

250 Id., para. 177.

251 Id., para. 255.

252 Id., para. 208.

253 Id., para. 266.

254 Id., paras. 267, 271.

255 Id., paras. 280–84.

256 Id., paras. 409–10.

257 Id., para. 423.

258 Id., para. 481.

259 Eli Lilly v. Canada, para. 5.

260 Id.

261 Id., para. 351.

262 Id., para. 310.

263 Id., para. 384.

264 Id., para. 386.

265 Id., para. 423.

266 Id.

267 Id.

268 Id., paras. 423–26 (“All patent regimes must determine the line between speculation and invention … there is no perfect place to draw this line.”).

269 For example, James Crawford, one of the very few nuanced voices on the treaty/contract problem, also served on the tribunal in Philip Morris.

270 See, e.g., Stiglitz, supra note 13, at 40–43.

271 See Galanter, supra note 246, at 124 (“The principal contribution of courts to dispute resolution is the provision of a background of norms and procedures, against which negotiations and regulation in both private and governmental settings takes place … [including] communication to prospective litigants of what might transpire if one of them sought a judicial resolution”); Puig supra note 246, at 412 (hinting at how tobacco companies use ISDS in this way).

272 See, e.g., EU ISDS Proposal, supra note 27.

273 See, e.g., Japan-Kazakhstan BIT, Art. 21(1) (“Nothing in this Agreement shall be construed so as to derogate from the rights and obligations under multilateral agreements in respect of protection of intellectual property rights to which the Contracting Parties are parties.”); Canada-China BIT, Art. 8(4) (2014), and Canada-Cote D'Ivoire BIT, Art. 16(5) (2015) (carving out most-favored nation, national treatment, and performance requirement claims for actions permitted by the TRIPS or other international intellectual property agreements).

274 Draft TPP, Art. 9.25.2(b)(i) & n. 35, available at http://international.gc.ca/trade-commerce/trade-agreements-accords-commerciaux/agr-acc/tpp-ptp/text-texte/toc-tdm.aspx?lang=eng (providing that investment agreements are governed by the law of the contract, or, by default, the law of the respondent, including in relation to damages, mitigation, interest, and estoppel, supplemented by any applicable international law) (suspended by the supervening CPTPP).

275 See, e.g., Turkey-Azerbaijan BIT, Art. 1 (2011) (excluding coverage for shareholdings under 10%).

276 See, e.g., Protocol Between the Government of the United States of America and the Government of Korea Amending the Free Trade Agreement Between the United States of America and the Republic of Korea (KORUS), Art. 4(i), available at https://ustr.gov/sites/default/files/files/agreements/FTA/KORUS/KORUS%20Protocol%20Amending%20Agreement%20-%20Signed.pdf (inserting a new KORUS Article 11.18(4)) (closing off multiple claims by parents and subsidiaries that they own or control, directly or indirectly, but leaving open the possibility of independent claims by non-controlling shareholders of any entity in the chain).

277 See CISG, Art. 6.

278 See Puig & Shaffer, supra note 17.

279 See Alvarez, supra note 14.