I Introduction
We live in an increasingly complicated and “risky” world. We attempt to mitigate these risks by imposing responsibilities on the actors involved in risky activities and by regulating, or prohibiting, the activities themselves. Scientific and technological advancements pose evolving challenges to the regulation of risk, as can be seen in the regulation of new technologies and of complex problems such as climate change.Footnote 1 Risk regulation itself has become a contested activity, raising questions regarding the nature of information, the acceptability of risk,Footnote 2 the distinction between perceived and actual risk,Footnote 3 the timespan during which risks may materialise,Footnote 4 and, perhaps most importantly, choice of risk regulator – a governmental agency, the judiciary, insurance companies.Footnote 5
The recent Urgenda judgment brings many of these questions to the fore.Footnote 6 In Urgenda, the question before the The Hague District Court was whether the Dutch government could be held liable under tort law for exposing the Dutch population to the risk of dangerous anthropogenic climate change.Footnote 7 The Court held that it could and that the existing mitigation policy was insufficient to discharge its duty of care.Footnote 8 While the Court’s judgment was based on Dutch tort law, it relied heavily on international scientific consensus regarding the likelihood of climate change and its associated risks in determining the standard of care, as well as international obligations regarding climate change mitigation;Footnote 9 having identified several sources of “valid” information, the Court found the governmental actions that had been taken to prevent, or at least reduce, these risks to be unacceptable.Footnote 10
The societal and academic impact of this judgment, despite coming from a district court and therefore subject to appeal, has already been profound. This article uses the Urgenda judgment as the backdrop for two analytical points that have thus far been undervalued in the academic debate on judicial risk regulation: firstly, it considers the institutional puzzle of courts as risk regulators from a law and economics (“L&E”) perspective, focusing specifically on the relative institutional strengths of courts to efficiently and effectively regulate risk as compared to governmental agents; second, it distinguishes between different types of judicial risk regulation and shows how Urgenda represents a new “hybrid” form where tort law is used to judicially review governmental (in)action. L&E provides an extra-legal perspective on the value and dangers of this particular type of judicial risk regulation.
The remainder of this article is structured as follows: Section II introduces three types of judicial risk regulation. Section III shows how the extra-legal perspective offered by law and economics can play a particularly valuable role in evaluating the judicial role in risk regulation, as it helps us map the relative institutional strengths and weaknesses of courts vis-à-vis governmental actors. Section IV explores the new “hybrid” form of judicial risk regulation as exemplified by the Urgenda decision and how L&E insights may be used to assess judicial competence and desirability in this type of case.
II Types of judicial risk regulation
Courts act as risk regulators by assigning responsibility for certain actions, and the risks they entail, to specific actors. Judicial risk regulation most commonly takes place through tort law, aimed primarily at the behaviour of private actors, and judicial review, aimed at governmental decisions on the regulation of risk. Urgenda represents a case where these two types are combined: a tort action against the government, which may lead to judicial review of governmental policy.
Judicial risk regulation through tort law regulates risky activities undertaken by – primarily – private actors. In most legal systems, tort law places a duty of care on one party (the injurer), which if breached, makes the injurer liable for damages suffered by another party (the victim) as a result of that breach.Footnote 11 Courts play a determinative role in many steps of this process, as they must establish whether the harm suffered is legally “relevant” (harm), the actions of the injurer led to the harm suffered (causation), and whether the injurer breached her duty of care (tort/liability). The form and function of the latter assessment depends on the type of liability imposed on the injurer; in cases of strict liability, the level of care becomes immaterial – if the injurer’s behaviour caused the harm, she is liable. In cases of negligence, the court has significantly more discretion, as the level of care take by the injurer becomes decisive: the injurer will only be liable if she acted without taking sufficient care. In establishing the latter, the court has two tasks: first, it must determine which party is best placed to avoid or mitigate the potential harm resulting from a risky activity; second, it must assess what is the appropriate level of care given the costs and benefits of the activity and the potential harm.Footnote 12 Aside from liability under strict liability and negligence, a party might also be liable for the breach of a statutory duty. In this case, the legislator has determined the appropriate duty of care and the court is tasked with enforcing this duty of care.
In the context of judicial risk regulation, negligence-based liability is most relevant, as it empowers the court to determine the acceptable risk level of the regulated activity. The need for this independent assessment of risk lies in the possibility of the injurer to externalise her risk on other parties, which would result in inefficiently low levels of care (ie lower than would be socially optimal).Footnote 13 Tort law thus has a risk regulation function – measures are taken to reduce the risk that harm may materialise by forcing parties to take (additional) care – as well as a compensatory function – the victim is compensated for (some of) the harm suffered. As a remedy, tort law tends to be categorised as an ex post solution: the harm needs to have materialised before the court can impose a penalty. This characterisation is insufficiently precise for several reasons,Footnote 14 one example being that courts may also be asked to issue injunctions to prevent certain activities from taking place, or continuing, based on the associated risk and/or expected harm.Footnote 15
Judicial risk regulation can also take place through the judicial review of governmental decisions. In these cases, the question before the court may not be directly related to the assessment of risk; rather, the legality of the governmental measure – broadly understood – will be the focus of the review. Depending on the scope for judicial review in the relevant jurisdiction,Footnote 16 the court may have more or less discretion to critique the risk assessment of the government and any subsequent action or inaction. In situations of judicial review, other constitutional principles become immediately relevant, such as the separation of powers doctrine. This doctrine tends to empower the judiciary to provide a check on the executive and/or legislature but also looks to ensure the judiciary does not take the place of the legislature and/or one of its agencies.Footnote 17
The Urgenda case introduced a third form of judicial risk assessment, which combines, intentionally or unintentionally, these two forms of judicial risk regulation. The Urgenda decision was founded in Dutch tort law and centred on the establishment of a duty of care for the Dutch government regarding the mitigation of the risks associated with anthropogenic climate change. The Court established the existence of such a duty of care and clarified that the current governmental policy was insufficient to discharge of this duty.Footnote 18
However, the injurer in Urgenda differs from a private tortfeasor in important ways. Governments can only “externalise” costs in limited ways: to different societal groups, to actors outside of its jurisdiction or to future generations that do not currently have a vote. The dynamics between the political actors involved and the different parties affected have been studied as part of Public Choice theory,Footnote 19 which demonstrates that political actors are susceptible to pressure by small interest groups which may result in socially sub-optimal outcomes. This undermines the government’s position as regulator.Footnote 20 However, it is very difficult to empirically separate regulations that improve the public interest and those that only serve the interests of certain governmental agents.Footnote 21 Therefore, while the types of choices regarding risk distribution are imperfect and at times controversial, many continue to consider the government best placed to make such an assessment.Footnote 22
In addition, one could argue that in determining the standard of care, a species of judicial review took place; the Court considered evidence on the risk of climate change and its consequences in order to determine the appropriate standard of care. Based on its own assessment of this evidence, it decided that the government’s assessment of similar evidence, and its subsequent policies, were insufficient to fulfil the duty of care. This can be distinguished from a situation where the Court had followed the government’s assessment of the risk and had based the level of care needed on that assessment. In traditional judicial review the courts are not empowered to replace the government’s decision with their own, rather they force the government to retake its decision.Footnote 23
Each of the types of judicial risk regulation set out above draws on different strengths of the courts vis-à-vis other risk regulators, including the government and private actors. Depending on the perspective adopted (eg a legal or L&E perspective) certain strengths will weigh more heavily, and will be measured differently, than others. The L&E perspective – and the types of questions it would pose with respect to each form of judicial risk regulation – will be set out in detail in the next section.
III A law and economics perspective on judicial risk regulation
L&E scholarship provides us with tools for the choice between the government – or another type of social planner – and the court as risk regulator.Footnote 24 This section outlines the L&E lessons as to which institution can set optimal rules, involving lowest total (ie private and social) cost. Before doing so, the first sub-section will briefly discuss how L&E views risk and the aims of risk regulation. As will become clear from our discussion, these aims are not necessarily shared with legal scholars, which may explain for some of the difference between these two approaches. The second and third sub-sections will set out the main lessons of L&E scholarship regarding this issue and the implications of these findings regarding our questions on the judicial competence to act as risk regulators and the desirability for them to do so.
1 Defining risk and risk regulation
Risk can be viewed in two interrelated ways:Footnote 25 first, risks can be conceptualised as potential harms arising from an activity. Typically, but not necessarily, these harms affect third parties: someone other than the person undertaking the risky activity.Footnote 26 When risk is viewed as the potential for harm, risk regulation, or rather management, then refers to methods aimed at preventing, distributing and/or compensating potential harms. This goes back to tort law as a form of judicial risk regulation: by imposing a duty of care, or strict liability, on the potential injurer, she can no longer externalise potential harms on third parties.Footnote 27
A second way to conceive of risk is as a situation of imperfect information.Footnote 28 Risk analysis, the three-step process used by most leading jurisdictions, tends to be broken down in risk assessment, risk management and risk communication.Footnote 29 Risk assessment involves assessing and quantifying the probabilities and magnitudes of hazards associated with particular behaviours and policies. Risk management, in contrast, involves policy-based decisions about which, and how, risks will be reduced or tolerated. The latter tends to be viewed as more political than the former, even though this position becomes less defensible in situations of scientific uncertainty,Footnote 30 and “politicised science”.Footnote 31 Nevertheless, the division of labour between governmental actors continues to reflect this assumption: risk assessment is typically done by specialist agencies whereas decisions regarding risk management are often in the hands of the legislature.Footnote 32
Information is particularly vital in the risk assessment stage, as our ability to assess the level of risk, and/or the likelihood of harm, varies between activities.Footnote 33 This will also put additional burden on the risk management part of the process as the decision-maker will have to rely more heavily on her discretion. Risk assessment could be seen an exercise in gathering as much valid information as possible so as to take informed decisions.Footnote 34 However, gathering information is costly.Footnote 35 From an L&E perspective, being optimally informed may therefore mean being imperfectly informed.Footnote 36
Our conceptualisation of risk, at least partially, informs which of the institutions we consider best placed to regulated risks. For example, we tend to have more information about the risk once the harm has materialised.Footnote 37 While it can then no longer be prevented, the question of compensation may be answered more accurately than if such an assessment had been made ex ante.Footnote 38 Relatedly, many risky activities result in benefits as well as costs, but not necessarily for the same (group of) people. The distributional consequences of such risks tend to be left to governmental agents, which have a more inclusive view of the situation than a court faced with two parties in one case.Footnote 39
Both legal and L&E scholars recognise these two conceptualisations of risk. However, the emphasis placed on each differs depending on our perspective, as do the strategies connected to them. On questions of distribution, the legal perspective prioritises justice concerns,Footnote 40 although controversial and hard to quantify,Footnote 41 over efficiency or social welfare criteria as prioritised by L&E scholarship.Footnote 42 Similarly, legal reasoning relies heavily on legal principles that can be traced back to specific constitutional and jurisdictional contexts. For example, in the environmental context, the precautionary principle is meant to guide courts and regulators in determining acceptable levels of risk and activity.Footnote 43 This may not always result in the most efficient regulation of risk, which would be prioritised by L&E scholars. Even in situations where both perspectives reach the same conclusions as to the nature of the risk, consequent conclusions regarding the type of regulation or regulator can easily diverge depending on our view on the aim of risk regulation.
L&E scholarship focuses on non-system specific rules that look to optimise rules and institutions in order to achieve efficiency.Footnote 44 In the context of risk regulation, this can be summarised as: adopting those rules that ensure optimal internalisation of potential harm, leading to optimal levels of precaution and/or activity.Footnote 45 In order to achieve this aim, the parties involved in risky behaviour – the “injurer” and the “victim” – have to be incentivised to “optimise” their behaviour.Footnote 46 This optimisation aims to ensure that social costs of the activity are minimised and that the costs of reducing risks are incurred by the person best placed to affect them – typically the potential injurer.Footnote 47
The aim of risk regulation can also be tailored to the informational conceptualisation of risk. From an L&E perspective, information can play a number of roles in risk regulation: (lack of) information can create transaction costs, especially if information is asymmetric between parties.Footnote 48 The locus of information is vital, both with respect to the information (made) available to the regulator and the information that actors have regarding their own behaviour. Increased levels of information lead to more accurate risk assessment and an increased ability to optimise behaviour. When information is imperfect or asymmetrical, optimal risk regulation is less likely. Risk regulation can therefore also aim at optimising information as a precursor to optimising behaviour, distribution or compensation decisions. Conversely, the type of regulation or regulator can also influence the amount of information available. Information can thus be considered as endogenous or exogenous to the type of risk regulator/regulation.Footnote 49
2 Judicial versus governmental risk regulation
L&E scholarship typically portrays the choice between governmental and judicial risk regulation as a choice between an ex ante regulatory regime or ex post liability regime.Footnote 50 A judicially-enforced liability regime is characterised as “ex post” as it imposes liability for manifested harms and thereby ensures compensation of parties that have suffered harm due to materialised risks.Footnote 51 Conversely, governmental regulation is aimed at minimising the costs related to risky activities through the ex ante regulation of risks,Footnote 52 for example through the imposition of standards or requirements on those involved in risky activities. The relative strengths of courts and governmental actors in administrating these systems depend on the type of risk and harm being regulated, and the characteristics of the regulators. We will start by focusing on the former.
Generally speaking, ex post compensation will only be effective in cases where we can be certain that the threat of ex post liability will result in preventative action, ie deterrence.Footnote 53 In situations of complex, geographically and/or temporally dispersed harm, ex ante regulation of the risk may be preferable over the imposition of ex post liability for several reasons:Footnote 54 firstly, there can be procedural difficulties, such as having to prove causation – a key requirement in most legal systems for establishing liability.Footnote 55 This may be impossible for certain (groups of) victims, precluding compensation and any specific or general deterrent effect created by the imposition of liability. Dispersed harm similarly tests the limits of ex post regimes, as it may be difficult to identify victims and/or injurers to which to award compensation/ assign liability. Secondly, ex ante regulation may be more effective for injurers with certain characteristics – particularly so-called “litigation proof” injurers.Footnote 56 The imposition of ex post liability is aimed at providing incentives to potential injurers to take (optimal levels of) care, as failure to do so would result in the payment of compensation. However, if the injurer is insensitive to such penalties (is “litigation proof”), these incentives will not be effective and ex ante regulation may be preferable.Footnote 57 Finally, the overall cost of using the court system in terms of time and resources needed to achieve compensation (as compared to a governmental default rate, or better, prevention of the harm) continues to weigh against the judicial risk regulator in terms of cost-effectiveness. This cost is, however, difficult to quantify and given the compliance and enforcement costs involved in ex ante regulation, which tend to increase with complexity of the regulated activity, the respective costs of ex ante and ex post regulation is hard to quantify.Footnote 58
There are also strengths to ex post judicial risk regulation; firstly, at the moment that the court is asked to impose liability for harm, the risk will have materialised. Courts thus tend to have more information than the social planner might have had before the risk has materialised.Footnote 59 This allows for greater accuracy in assessing damages, particularly for uncertain risks, and correspondingly provides more information regarding the optimal level of care by the injurer and/or victim.Footnote 60 It also allows for a greater level of initial flexibility and experimentation regarding risks, which can be particularly valuable for “new” risks associated with activities that may prove to be valuable for society.Footnote 61 This dynamic is also a closer reflection of the purpose and effect of a duty of care, which is not limited to compensation; rather, the duty of care and related compensation also aim to change future behaviour when engaging in risky activities. Second, one must consider the speed with which regulators and courts can respond to changes in information. Court-based injunctions may be used to, at least temporarily, halt activities, which prove to be more harmful than anticipated, while changing regulation may take much longer as a new regulatory standard must be set. This is not to say that the judicial process is not subject to its own limitations regarding speed of process and trial, but the ability of the judiciary to respond to changed circumstances in its rulings often allows for more dynamic changes than the legislative route.
Thus far we have focused on the type of rules that certain regulators tend to adopt and how well they may be suited for certain risks and/or parties affected by the risk. However, the choice of regulator has also been found to affect the behaviour of the regulatee, as distinct from the choice of rule.Footnote 62 One explanation for this is the (perceived) imperfect assessment of care by the courts. A key determinant in assessing liability is the level of care taken by the injurer; under negligence, the injurer is only liable if her level of care falls short of the duty of care imposed by the court.Footnote 63 The ability of courts to observe the care taken by the injurer is typically imperfect, which can lead injurers to take excessive care, rather than optimal care, in order to avoid liability.Footnote 64 This can be true even when the liability rule itself is set at the optimal level.Footnote 65
These respective strengths and weaknesses are based on stereotypes of ex ante and ex post regulation. In reality, the dividing line drawn between ex ante and ex post regulation is rather blurred. The traditional juxtapositioning of judicial and governmental risk regulation assumes that the two function primarily, or even exclusively, as substitutes: one either imposes a regulatory regime or a liability regime.Footnote 66 In practice, we tend to see a combination of these two regimes. For example, regulatory compliance does not necessarily provide a (full) defence against the ex post imposition of liability.Footnote 67 Early explanations given for situations where ex post and ex ante regimes act as complements rather than substitutes focus on the failings of liability as a regulatory mechanism, such as those mentioned previously: inefficiencies caused by uncertainty about the court’s behaviour,Footnote 68 the presence of litigation proof injurers, and enforcement errors.Footnote 69
Ex ante regulation is presumed to be equally inefficient for different reasons: the presumption of a single regulator standard applied to all injurers;Footnote 70 the “capture” of regulatory agencies by regulatees, where asymmetries in information or other power dynamics are abused so as to shape regulation in the interest of the regulated parties rather than the societal interest;Footnote 71 or is assumed to work perfectly.Footnote 72 Neither of these stereotypes accurately reflect the complex dynamic within and between these types of regulatory regimes. Specifically the role of interest groups – including regulated groups as well as groups of voters that may prefer (de)regulation – is complex and insufficiently clear in models that treats regulation and liability as alternatives; the courts can, and are, used by these interest groups in very similar ways as governmental actors, for example through strategic litigation.Footnote 73 The specifics of the legal system under examination determine whether the courts are more or less protected than governmental actors against such pressures.Footnote 74
Depending on the identified drivers for the complementarity of judicial and governmental risk regulation, different conclusions can be drawn regarding the impact of this complementarity on the respective mechanisms. For example, Kolstad et al found that it may be inefficient to set the ex ante regulatory standards at the socially optimal level if there is also an ex post liability scheme in place.Footnote 75 Later work, which has relaxed the assumption that enforcement under liability schemes is subject to persistent errors, found that regulation and liability can only be optimally combined when faced with injurers that have varying levels of wealth.Footnote 76 Rather than providing conclusive answers to the best combined use of ex post and ex ante regulation, this body of literature highlights which factors may be considered when deciding between (stylised) types of regulatory regimes.
***
The implications of L&E research regarding the strengths and weaknesses of judicial risk regulation can be summarised across three dimensions: First, the institutional comparison between courts and governmental agencies as risk regulators depends on the characteristics of: the risk that is regulated; the parties engaged in, or affected by, the risky activity; the type of harm; and, the availability of certain information. Second, using the judicial system for risk regulation can impose costs on the parties involved and the system as a whole, but these costs are not necessarily higher than the costs involved in setting, monitoring and complying with regulatory standards – much will depend on the efficiency of the rule set by either the judicial or governmental risk regulator. Third and finally, as may be expected, people’s behaviour is affected by the choice of regulator as well as the type of rule. Through these tripartite insights, L&E scholarship outlines the factors that influence the relative strengths of judicial versus governmental risk regulation (as summarised in Table 1).
Table 1 Strengths of judicial and/or governmental risk regulation

However, these lessons are limited in several ways. Firstly, first generation L&E scholarship was based on highly formalised assumptions regarding the characteristics of the legal system and the behaviour of the actors involved. One of these assumptions is that all actors would behave rationally – ie that they would pursue their goals in the most efficient way consistent with the information available to them.Footnote 77 This assumption has been taken to task by inter alia behavioural law and economics scholarship, which is starting to move past this rationality assumption in search of alternative theories. That said, a complete alternative to rational choice is yet to be provided. This research has provided important lessons on the motivators of individuals and institutional actors alike, which forces us to nuance many of the findings found in the more formalistic models of first generation L&E.Footnote 78 Similarly, early models paid limited attention to the institutional specifics of different legal systems. New institutional work – influenced by law and society literatures – is moving beyond the generic “court” and “government” models that were used to model these scenarios, making findings both more accurate and less easily generalisable.Footnote 79
Second, the dichotomy between judicial and governmental risk regulation as set out above, does not take account of the fuller range of risk regulation types that courts can engage in.Footnote 80 Instead, a generic ex post liability regime is used as a default. When we consider the role of courts in judicial review and/or the hybrid form of risk regulation as exemplified by the Urgenda case, the distinction between governmental and judicial risk regulation becomes immediately less pronounced; not least because the focus of L&E research as described above is geared towards regulating the behaviour of private actors. When we consider the courts’ ability to regulate governmental behaviour, many considerations remain constant, including the nature of the regulated risk. This would suggest that we can continue to use the insights provided by L&E based on the benchmark of relative efficiency and effectiveness, and to assess the competence and desirability of judicial risk regulation based on these two normative criteria. The next section offers some initial thoughts on how the lessons of L&E scholarship may be applied to the “hybrid” forms of judicial risk regulation as exemplified by Urgenda.
IV L&E insights for “hybrid” judicial risk regulation
This contribution categorises the approach of the Court in Urgenda as a hybrid form of judicial risk regulation. In Urgenda, the Court established tortious liability for the Dutch government,Footnote 81 and went on to prescribe what level of mitigation efforts would allow the government to discharge its duty of care.Footnote 82 In doing so, the Court replaces the government’s risk assessment with its own, thereby stretching the limits of tort law (as to the type of injurer) as well as judicial review (as to the invasiveness of review).Footnote 83 Whereas few have taken issue with the substantive outcome of the case – stronger measures for climate mitigation have been widely welcomed by public interest groups and even the Dutch ParliamentFootnote 84 – many legal scholars have expressed an unease with the Court’s willingness to “correct” the government’s risk assessment regarding the desirable level of climate change mitigation efforts.Footnote 85
Part of this unease may be explained by the potentially far-reaching constitutional implications of a new species of judicial risk regulation that combines tort law and judicial review functions and modalities. In most democracies, the separation of powers doctrine formalises the distinct functions of the executive, legislature and judiciary,Footnote 86 and determines the scope of judicial review.Footnote 87 With respect to risk regulation, the policy discretion enjoyed by the executive in implementing the aims set out by the legislature may be tested by the judiciary against constitutional and legal principles but is not supposed to be curtailed by the courts, or much less, be replaced by court-based policy assessment.Footnote 88 The Court in Urgenda was acutely aware of this issue but summarily dismisses the claim that its order could amount to a breach of the separation of powers doctrine.Footnote 89
This penultimate section complements these critiques with an extra-legal perspective on the Urgenda judgment that focuses on the relative strengths and weaknesses of the judiciary to engage in this specific type of risk regulation.Footnote 90 It does so by identifying how, if at all, the five factors identified in the previous section – the type of risk, the type of harm, information, the type of injurer, and the type of victim – were considered by the District Court, and by evaluating the Court’s evaluation of its institutional competence vis-à-vis these factors.
1 Judicial self-assessment: competence in hybrid judicial risk regulation
a Type of risk and harm
In Urgenda, the District Court was asked to determine “whether the existing mitigation policies [of the Dutch government] are acceptable in light of the need to prevent dangerous anthropologic climate change, given the government’s discretion in adopting said policies”?Footnote 91 If not, Urgenda’s claim that the Dutch government’s policies were negligently endangering the Dutch people in breach of its duty of care would have to be upheld.Footnote 92 The Court agreed with Urgenda finding the following: “[I]n view of risk management and from scientific considerations, there is a strong preference for the 450 scenario, as the risks [of hazardous climate change]Footnote 93 are much higher with a 500 scenario.”Footnote 94 Put differently, the Court agreed with Urgenda that the government’s efforts were insufficient in light of existing scientific information.Footnote 95 The potential harm that the Court identified was that of “hazardous” or “dangerous” climate change. The harm associated with climate change has posed challenges for tort litigation in other jurisdictions,Footnote 96 as the scale, scope, timeline and nature of the harms related to climate change are disputed,Footnote 97 and these global harms are likely to affect people beyond the jurisdiction of one specific court. The Dutch District Court did not consider these characteristics to impede its ability to judge the case.Footnote 98
b Information
The plaintiffs had initially requested a declaratory judgment from the Court on the veracity and validity of specific facts surrounding climate change.Footnote 99 The Court refused to give this declaration but did use international and national legal principles and scientific information on the risk of dangerous anthropogenic climate change to inform the duty and standard of care under Dutch tort law provisions on tortious acts.Footnote 100 In so doing, the Court converted some of these disputed scientific facts into “legal fact”,Footnote 101 even without the declaratory judgment.
c Type of injurer and victim
Perhaps the starkest contrast between the three forms of judicial risk regulation lies in the type of injurer targeted. As discussed previously, tort law is primarily considered a vehicle for regulating private behaviour. This is underlined by the fact that the legislature and executive are often immune to tort liability.Footnote 102 This is not the case in the Netherlands. Nevertheless, the government is treated differently from a private actor;Footnote 103 the Court underlined this by stressing that review of “individual cases” with wide societal impacts is possible, but only if the government’s ability to balance societal interests is treated with sufficient deference.Footnote 104 The government accordingly challenged the Court’s authority to award the mandatory order based on the Court’s lack of democratic legitimacy, and the impact of the judgment on the position of the Netherlands in international negotiations.Footnote 105 The Court did not find these arguments persuasive and held that the mandatory order was firmly within its competence;Footnote 106 since it did not detail the method of mitigation in its order, the Court considered the government’s discretion to be intact.Footnote 107
The type of victim in the three species of judicial risk regulation does not necessarily vary: an individual could bring a tort case as well as a judicial review case. That said, the requirements for standing do differ between these types of cases and even between, for example, tort cases. It has been notoriously difficult for parties to get standing in cases concerning climate change due to questions of harm and causation.Footnote 108 Due to the Dutch laws regarding standing for NGOs, Urgenda’s standing and ability to represent itself and the 886 co-plaintiffs was easily confirmed by the Court, and not challenged by the Dutch government, although its claim to also represent future generations outside of the Netherlands was rejected.Footnote 109
2 An L&E perspective on judicial competence in hybrid cases
The Court’s assessment of its ability to hear the case brought by Urgenda and its assessment of the substantive elements outlined above is based on legal reasoning. This reasoning has been critically discussed in legal scholarship, including contributions to this special issue,Footnote 110 raising important questions that go beyond the scope of the current inquiry, for instance regarding the interplay of European and national competence regarding climate mitigation.Footnote 111 This section will consider the Court’s analysis regarding the factors outlined above from a law and economics perspective so as to add an extra-legal perspective and see whether different conclusions may be reached regarding the Court’s competence.
a Type of risk and harm
The Court’s assessment of the risk highlights several issues. First, the dispute concerns the level of acceptable risk. This would typically be categorised as a political question best left to the executive or legislator.Footnote 112 The L&E insights summarised above also suggest that this assessment should be left to the government and its agents based on, inter alia, the government’s ability to consider distributional effects of policy choices and trade-offs between the restriction of different activities.Footnote 113 Second, the Court replaces the government’s assessment of acceptable risk level with its own,Footnote 114 and issues a mandatory order for the reduction of Dutch GHG emissions by at least 25% compared to 1990 by 2020 – a more ambitious goal than the existing 17–20% reduction commitment.Footnote 115 This raises a further question as to whether there is something about the institutional position of the court that makes it better placed than the government to digest the scientific information used to set these goals; is there something about the type of risk, and relatedly the type of information related to this risk, that suggests that the Court has more or better information than the government? This will be discussed further below in the section on Information.
Prima facie, L&E research suggests that courts are not comparatively better placed to deal with the types of harm associated with climate change: geographically and temporally dispersed, catastrophic harm. However, some of these characteristics also undermine the ability of governments to regulate these harms successfully. Specifically, the fact that the time horizons related to climate change are so distant as to not correspond with election cycles reduces the public’s ability to “penalise” political actors for “bad” climate decisions.Footnote 116 Similarly, the fact that many climate harms materialise outside the jurisdictions causing the harm, ie affect non-voters, reduces the responsiveness of governments.Footnote 117 The judiciary is more insulated from these kinds of pressures, which reduces its comparative disadvantage in dealing with these types of harms.Footnote 118
Some have argued that the result of this has been the expansion of the scope of the “public life” of tort law;Footnote 119 allowing tort law to add to “problem articulation, norm amplification and intergovernmental signalling”.Footnote 120 If one accepts the potential role that courts can play in providing a forum for interests that have been ignored or underrepresented during the legislative process, then courts should embrace tort cases that call for a questioning of governmental (in)action, specifically for cases involving complex, or politically sensitive risks.Footnote 121 Kysar stresses that “[d]eference to the representativeness of legislatures and the expertise of agencies need not be seen as a reason for withdrawing tort law as a traditional avenue for the pursuit of civil redress. The tracks are neither ‘parallel’ nor redundant. They are different”.Footnote 122 From an L&E perspective, however, the question remains whether this hybrid form of judicial risk regulation (in contrast with a pure tort law approach) is best suited for harnessing these potential public choice advantages (see below in the section Type of injurer).
b Information
Some of the commentary on Urgenda has been extremely critical as to the Court’s ability to digest and assess scientific information, particularly information that is itself disputed or controversial.Footnote 123 From an L&E perspective, the institution that has access to the “best” information would have the relative advantage. Specifically, this means that regulation is the best form of risk regulation if the government has better information than the injurer (assuming for now that all other factors are constant). Conversely, if the injurer has better information, judicial risk regulation in the form of tort law is preferable (through strict liability or negligence), as this would provide incentives to the injurer to take socially optimal care based on the information that she has regarding the activity. With respect to Urgenda, this raises two questions: first, which actor has better information? Second, how does the fact that the government is the defendant affect this comparison?Footnote 124
As to the first question, the District Court and the Dutch government have access to much the same information – in fact, the Court takes care to reference only sources already in the public sphere and referenced by the Dutch government in its decision-making. The real issue, therefore, is the way in which this information is processed and which conclusions are drawn. There is nothing to indicate that the Court is better placed to do this, except for the fact that they may be more insulated from political pressures as highlighted above. It has been suggested that this position of relative objectivity has led judicial fact checking to become an indispensable part of judicial review, even if this replicates some of the work undertaken by the governmental actor,Footnote 125 and/or if the court does not have the same specialised knowledge that the government agent may have.Footnote 126 In addition, it has been suggested that this position may be harnessed by differentiating between the review of different types of administrative decisions, eg legal, scientific and political decisions (assuming such a distinction can indeed be drawn).Footnote 127 In this case, especially since the harm is yet to materialise, ie the risk is yet to become a reality, it cannot be maintained that the Court has “better” information than the government – only that its ability to digest this information is different, and in the view of some, better. However, in this context “better” does not (necessarily) mean “more efficiently”.
The second, perhaps more important, question relates to the position of the government as the defendant/injurer. This is an issue in both judicial review cases and hybrid cases and highlights the somewhat narrow view of judicial risk regulation in traditional L&E scholarship, as will be discussed in more detail in the following sub-section.
c Type of injurer
By putting the government in the position of the defendant, judicial review and hybrid cases of judicial risk regulation do not follow the established dichotomy between regulation and tort law on which most L&E scholarship in this area is based. From a legal perspective, the key issue is a constitutional one, linked to the separation of powers.Footnote 128 L&E is agnostic as to these constitutional parameters, although the institutional setting in which the legislature, executive and judiciary function naturally impact on their comparative advantage regarding risk regulation. The narrower question here is: does the government represent a distinct type of injurer, and if so, what are the implications?
The L&E approach to judicial review is remarkably similar to tort cases: the assumption is that the injurer (private or governmental) is optimally informed regarding the correct level of care, and the court corrects for potentially self-serving actions and/or compensates victims. The fundamental L&E distinction between governmental and judicial risk regulation does not change. In hybrid cases, the fact that the defendant is the government similarly does not change the comparison between governmental and judicial risk regulation. However, several related circumstances in Urgenda should be considered: first, while the government has taken the position of the defendant, this does not automatically place her in the position of injurer. In Urgenda, the government became the defendant due to its ability to control the behaviour of injurers.Footnote 129 This is not to say that the government is vicariously liable for the actions of these injurers; the question in Urgenda is whether the government set the correct regulatory standards, not whether it had enforced them.Footnote 130 This distance between the defendant and the injurer changes the incentives given by the judicial intervention. Second, and relatedly, one may question whether the government is more or less likely to be judgment proof, as compared to a private defendant. Formally, the government could be argued to be financially judgment proof due to its powers of taxation and budgeting that could allow it to absorb any penalty imposed. However, the political impact of court rulings is considerable and much harder to set aside.Footnote 131 As envisaged by the checks and balances function of the separation of powers, the judiciary thus plays a vital role in reviewing decisions by the government through judicial review; a role from which the court is not disqualified based on the change in defendant.
V Concluding observations
Judicial risk regulation can take place through tort law, judicial review and a new “hybrid” form of regulation that uses tort principles to review governmental (in)action. While the latter type may be restricted to the Urgenda case referenced in this piece, which is moreover subject to appeal, the theoretical questions it raises are too important to be ignored. Depending on the scholarly perspective adopted, and the specificities of the risk being regulated and the system regulating it, judicial risk regulation can be considered comparatively “better” or “worse” than governmental risk regulation. Legal and L&E scholarship adopt different normative approaches in assessing the relative competence and desirability of risk regulation by the courts. The key strength of L&E scholarship, as compared to legal work on this issue, is its ability to provide generalisable lessons that are not bound to specific jurisdictions. This strength is often presented as L&E’s key weakness: legal scholars, as well as courts and regulators, are quick to emphasise their specific jurisdictional roles, which are ignored in certain theoretical models. However, comparative L&E scholarship has found that not all differences are in fact relevant differences, ie not all jurisdictional differences result in different outcomes.Footnote 132 This suggests that L&E scholarship may also contribute to dispelling the perceived “particularism” that many legal scholars invoke with respect to their respective jurisdictions.Footnote 133
However, as we are faced with increasingly complex risks and correspondingly complex relationships between judicial and governmental risk regulation, legal doctrines are stretched beyond their envisaged limits. L&E scholarship may provide additional positive and normative insights to fill the resulting gaps. Most importantly, the analytical approach adopted by L&E scholars forces us to explicate questions regarding types of risk, harm, information, regulatees, regulators and victims, that are often treated as secondary in constitutional discussions regarding the appropriate role of the courts and government agents in risk regulation.
The distinction made in this article between different types of judicial risk regulation nuances the L&E dichotomy between governmental and judicial risk regulation. It further erodes the credibility of these types of risk regulation acting as substitutes; in most situations, they are more accurate represented as incomplete compliments. Many of the findings regarding the type of risk, harm and information remain constant across these types (depending of course on particulars of a given case). From a legal perspective, the most significant difference – a governmental rather than private defendant – proves to be of limited relevance in an L&E analysis. While the distance between defendant and injurer may complicate enforcement and information issues, there is nothing that suggests that governmental actors are more judgment proof than private defendants. The ways in which they are judgment proof are different but this does not disqualify the complementary function of judicial risk regulation. Judicial risk regulation may therefore supplement governmental risk regulation, also regarding risks related to climate change, which have been viewed as ill-suited for judicial deliberation. The main caveat is that this process is also not immune to abuse by interest groups that may have “lost” during the political process proceeding the case. Conversely, the same may be seen as a positive, as this allows a chance for marginalised groups to be heard.