Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-d8cs5 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T09:47:36.978Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Evolutionary catastrophes and the Goldilocks problem

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 September 2007

Milan M. Ćirković
Affiliation:
Astronomical Observatory of Belgrade, Volgina 7, 11160 Belgrade, Serbia e-mail: mcirkovic@aob.bg.ac.yu
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

One of the mainstays of the controversial ‘rare Earth’ hypothesis is the ‘Goldilocks problem’ regarding various parameters describing a habitable planet, partially involving the role of mass extinctions and other catastrophic processes in biological evolution. Usually, this is construed as support for the uniqueness of the Earth's biosphere and intelligent human life. Here it is argued that this is a misconstrual and that, on the contrary, observation-selection effects when applied to catastrophic processes make it very difficult for us to discern whether the terrestrial biosphere and evolutionary processes which created it are exceptional in the Milky Way or not. This agnosticism, in turn, supports the validity and significance of practical astrobiological and SETI research.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2007

Introduction

One of the mainstays of the controversial ‘rare Earth’ hypothesis in astrobiology is the ‘Goldilocks rule’ regarding various parameters describing a habitable planet. If an arbitrary astrobiological parameter Ω can have various values on different habitable planets (let us neglect for the moment its temporal variation on a single planet), then only a limited range of values of Ω∊[Ωmin, Ωmax] will lead to a complex biosphere such as Earth's. In an instance of this rule, it is often suggested that the extent and rate of catastrophic events in the history of the terrestrial biosphere was both:

  • low enough to prevent the complete extinction of life or its developmental arrest at the microbial level, but

  • high enough to provide sufficient ‘evolution pump’ and enable the fauna (large-scale changes of dominant taxons, e.g. the switch from ediacaran to cambrian fauna) overturns, and to open ecological niches for more complex and advanced evolutionary designs.

The reasoning here is that, on an average, the terrestrial-planet rate of catastrophes is going to be either higher or lower than the rate characterizing Earth's history. Therefore, the conditions necessary for the emergence of complex life and intelligent observers are bound to be quite rare. This has been argued by Ward & Brownlee (Reference Ward and Brownlee2000) in the ‘Bible’ of the ‘rare Earth’ movement, and is essentially accepted by all supporters of this astrobiological view (particularly illustrative for different reasons are Carter (Reference Carter, Bertola and Curi1993), Webb (Reference Webb2002), Conway Morris (Reference Conway2003), and various writings of Frank Tipler, e.g. Tipler (Reference Tipler2003)). The catastrophes we are dealing with here include not only well publicized ones such as the asteroidal/cometary impacts and supervolcanic eruptions, but also those less understood such as a close supernova/γ-ray burst or even those nobody has suggested thus far (Leslie Reference Leslie1996; Bostrom Reference Bostrom2002).

In comparison to some other claims of the ‘rare Earth’ supporters, this one sounds plausible and even appealing. After all, only in the last quarter of a century have we realized the significance of the role mass extinctions play in determining courses of evolution, especially after the study of Alvarez et al. (Reference Alvarez, Alvarez, Asaro and Michel1980); among fine popular reviews are Raup (Reference Raup1991), Courtillot (Reference Courtillot1999) and Erwin (Reference Erwin2006). Symbolically, the reasoning involved can be presented as follows.

  1. (1) The Earth possesses property X.

  2. (2) X seems a priori unlikely among Earth-like planets.

  3. (3) Our emergence is contingent on X.

  4. (4) We are intelligent observers.

The emergence of intelligent observers on other Earth-like planets is unlikely.

X in this particular case can be defined as ‘fine-tuned catastrophism’. This reasoning can be criticized from several different viewpoints. For instance, one could deny premise (3), an approach which is unpopular today due to theistic misuses in the past, although it is denied by some secular philosophers as well (e.g. Wright Reference Wright2000). Often, people question the ceteris paribus clause in (2). Here we shall take a different approach: first, we wish to argue that (3) should be rephrased by emphasizing its temporal nature:

  1. (3)′ Our emergence at the present epoch is contingent on X.

This has multifold advantages, the most important being the possibility of connecting with the well-studied evolutionary processes, both on Earth and in the Milky Way. In addition, it serves to underscore that the argument pertains essentially to us, Homo sapiens, no matter how its authors pretend otherwise (in order to escape the charge of anthropocentrism; e.g. Carter (Reference Carter1983)).

The next question we should ask is: How big does the catastrophe at each point in the history of Earth need to be in order to be consistent with the existence of intelligent observers at t=t 0? Notice that the observers we are asking about here need not be us, humans, in either a morphological, phylogenetical or just chronological way. Without entering the hard and heated topic concerning to what extent our presence today is contingent or convergent (for different views, see Gould (Reference Gould1989), McShea (Reference McShea1998), Conway Morris (Reference Conway1998, Reference Conway2003) and Shanahan (Reference Shanahan1999, Reference Shanahan2001)), we can attempt to draw some preliminary conclusions by investigating first a specific catastrophic event, and subsequently showing that such very destructive episodes in fact undermine the information value of past records. This, we shall try to show, makes the Goldilocks argument misleading, since it does not take into account important observation-selection effects.

Catastrophes and observation selection

Let us consider a case of the catastrophic event which has influenced evolution of Earth's biosphere beyond serious doubt: the Chixhulub impact of ~65 Myr ago. Since Alvarez et al. (Reference Alvarez, Alvarez, Asaro and Michel1980) proposed an impact as the major causal agency of the well-known mass extinction episode at the Cretaceous/Tertiary boundary (the K–T boundary), the scientific case for impact has been strengthened almost continuously. Nowadays, we know that the size of the impactor was between 10 and 20 km, depending on parameters such as the internal composition, the incident angle and the velocity of the impacting body (Hughes Reference Hughes2003). However, impacting bodies can, in principle, be of widely varying sizes; after all, micrometeorites bombard Earth all the time, and larger particles create beautiful meteor showers apparently without threatening the biosphere or in any known way influencing the evolutionary processes. On the other hand, studies of the early history of the Solar System have suggested that collisions with bodies hundreds of kilometres in size remaining at that epoch caused repeated meltdown of the entire planetary crust and perhaps even complete atmosphere blow-off (Maher & Stevenson Reference Maher and Stevenson1988). Thus, only a finite – and quite small – range of impactors at the fixed epoch of the K–T boundary could have caused the evolution of modern humans. A schematic presentation of this effect is shown in Fig. 1, which considers the range of possible impactors at the K–T boundary. Only impactors in the roughly shadowed region of size distribution could lead to the emergence of humans. (Whether some other form of intelligence could emerge without the mass extinction for general biological reasons is highly uncertain; on the other hand, it seems quite unlikely that this would have occurred at about the same time.)

Fig. 1. The Goldilocks problem at the K–T boundary: only impactors in the narrow shaded strip would have led to the ‘right’ mass extinction (leading to the development of humans at the present epoch). Both smaller and larger impacts would have resulted in the non-existence of humans. This remains valid even if we acknowledge the existence of the empirical upper limit on the size of an impactor.

Obviously, the same ‘Goldilocks problem’ reasoning applies to other physical causative agents of catastrophic events. But, what does this mean? Do we have to conclude that only an overwhelming, a priori extremely improbable instance of luck brought about catastrophes fine-tuned for our existence, as the ‘rare Earth’ proponents seemingly suggest? Not really, since (i) it is obviously incorrect to conclude that in the absence of humans no intelligent observers would have arisen by this date (cf. Russell Reference Russell1983; McKay Reference McKay and Doyle1996), and (ii) at least those catastrophes which are stochastic in the epistemic sense are subject to a simple observation-selection effect which we shall now illustrate by a toy model.

Consider the simplest case of a single very destructive global catastrophe, for instance, a Toba-like supervolcanic eruption.Footnote 1 The evidence we take into account in a Bayesian manner is the fact of our existence at the present epoch (not necessarily including the influence of the perturbation on the evolutionary pathways; this is just a binary toy model). We can schematically represent the situation in Fig. 2: the a priori probability of catastrophe is P and the probability of human survival (or an insufficiently strong perturbation leaving the evolutionary pathway within the morphological subspace containing humans) of the catastrophic event is Q. We shall suppose that the two probabilities are (i) constant, (ii) adequately normalized and (iii) applicable to a particular well-defined interval of past time. Event B 2 is the occurrence of the catastrophe, and by E we denote the evidence of our present existence.

Fig. 2. A schematic presentation of the single-event toy model. The evidence E consists of our present-day existence.

Direct application of the Bayes formula in the form

(1)
P\lpar B_{\setnum{2}} \vert E\rpar \equals {{P\lpar B_{\setnum{2}} \rpar \,P\lpar E\vert B_{\setnum{2}} \rpar } \over {P\lpar B_{\setnum{1}} \rpar \,P\lpar E\vert B_{\setnum{1}} \rpar \plus P\lpar B_{\setnum{2}} \rpar \,P\lpar E\vert B_{\setnum{2}} \rpar }}\comma

using our notation, gives the a posteriori probability as

(2)
P\lpar B_{\setnum{2}} \vert E\rpar \equals {{PQ} \over {\lpar 1 \minus P\rpar \cdot 1 \plus PQ}} \equals {{PQ} \over {1 \minus P \plus PQ}}.

Only a rather straightforward algebraic manipulation shows that

(3)
P \lpar {B_{\setnum{2}} \vert E} \rpar\les P\comma

i.e. we tend to underestimate the true catastrophic risk. It is intuitively clear why: the symmetry between past and future is broken by the existence of an evolutionary process leading to our emergence as observers at this particular epoch in time. We can expect a large catastrophe tomorrow, but we cannot – even without any empirical knowledge – expect to find traces of a large catastrophe which occurred yesterday, since it would have preempted our existence today.

We can define the overconfidence parameter as

(4)
{\rmeta} \equiv {{P\lpar a{\rm \ }priori\rpar } \over {P\lpar a{\rm \ }posteriori\rpar }}\comma

illuminating the magnitude of this bias in a quantitative way; obviously, our inferences from the past become unreliable if η>1 and rather useless for η≫1. In the special case of our toy model, the overconfidence parameter becomes

(5)
{\rmeta} \equals {P \over {P\lpar B_{\setnum{2}} \vert E\rpar }} \equals {{1 \minus P \plus PQ} \over Q}.

All values larger than η~1 indicate that we are seriously underestimating the extinction risk. However, even quite conservative numerical values give rather depressing results here. If, for instance, we take Q=0.1, P=0.5 (corresponding to a fair-coin-toss chance that an event similar or slightly larger than the Toba supereruption occurs once per ~1 Myr of human evolution), the resulting value of the overconfidence parameter is η=5.5, indicating a gross error in the risk estimates! Values of overconfidence as a function of severity (as measured by the extinction probability 1 – Q) are shown in Fig. 3.

Fig. 3. Overconfidence parameter as a function of the extinction probability 1 – Q in our single-event toy model. Different values of the real event probability density P (appropriately averaged) are colour-coded. We notice that the anthropic overconfidence bias is strongest for low-probability density (‘rare’) events.

Note that

(6)
\mathop {{\rm lim}}\limits_{Q \rightarrow \setnum{0}} {\rmeta} \equals \infty.

Overconfidence becomes very large for very destructive events! An obvious consequence is that the possibility of absolutely destructive events, which humanity has no chance of surviving at all (Q=0), completely destroys our confidence in predicting from past occurrences. This almost trivial conclusion is not, however, widely appreciated. On the contrary, a rather well-known argument of Hut & Rees (Reference Hut and Rees1983) on the vacuum phase transition contains the not-so-trivial error of not taking observation selection into account. Of course, a more sophisticated model involving a series of random catastrophic events with various causes needs to be developed, but the main philosophical point is clear: we cannot reason as if our past evolution is truly typical for a terrestrial planet without taking into account our present existence.

This has important consequences for our study of the role of catastrophic events in the general astrobiological context, i.e. in the evolution of an average biosphere in the Galaxy. Is evolution on the other habitable planets in the Milky Way influenced more or less by catastrophes? We cannot say, because the stronger the catastrophic stress is (the larger the analogue of our probability 1−Q is on average), the less useful information we can extract about the proximity – or else – of our particular historical experience to what is generally to be expected. Only serious astrobiological studies can give a useful answer to this conundrum. Some data already exist. For instance, one well-studied case is the system of the famous nearby Sun-like star Tau Ceti, which contains both planets and a massive debris disk, analogous to the Solar System Kuiper belt. Modelling of Tau Ceti's dust disk observations indicate, however, that the mass of the colliding bodies up to 10 km in size may total around 1.2 Earth-masses, compared with 0.1 Earth-masses estimated to be in the Solar System's Edgeworth–Kuiper Belt (Greaves et al. Reference Greaves, Wyatt, Holland and Dent2004). Thus, Tau Ceti's dust disk may have around 10 times more cometary and asteroidal material than is currently found in the Solar System – in spite of the fact that Tau Ceti seems to be about twice as old as the Sun. Why the Tau Ceti system would have a more massive cometary disk than the Solar System is not fully understood, but it is reasonable to conjecture that any hypothetical terrestrial planet of this extrasolar planetary system would be subjected to much more severe impact stress than Earth has been during the course of its geological and biological history.Footnote 2

Discussion

We have considered the influence of observation selection on our thinking about the role of catastrophes in the evolutionary history of Earth and, by analogy, other habitable terrestrial planets in the Galaxy. Two points are of particular importance for future discussions:

  1. (1) We cannot hope to realistically assess the general importance of catastrophic events in shaping the evolution on habitable planets as long as we are limited to the past local records.

  2. (2) Invoking fine-tuning of catastrophes to support the ‘rare Earth’ hypothesis is misguided, since any information one infers from the past records is either erased or heavily skewed by the observation-selection effects.

It is significant to note that, in principle, it is quite possible that we need to revise our views on the general frequency of catastrophes upwards, and thus the universe might be more hostile to life throughout and the probability of escaping catastrophic extinction is very small.Footnote 3 This is still consistent with the conclusion (1) above. This possibility should always be kept in mind, at least as a cautioning note for the overwhelming enthusiasm similar to that reigning about SETI in the 1960s and 1970s. However, there is a host of different reasons for taking a more moderate position, somewhere between the extremes of naive contact optimism and anthropocentric skepticism of ‘rare-Earthers’ (Dyson Reference Dyson and Marshak1966; Gould Reference Gould1987; Dick Reference Dick2003; Ćirković & Bradbury Reference Ćirković and Bradbury2006).

There are several practical consequences of conclusions (1) and (2). One is certainly that only astrobiology, currently undergoing explosive development, will be able to tell us whether there are other biospheres and other intelligent communities in the Milky Way. No amount of armchair theorizing can escape the observation-selection effects related to the evolutionary development of intelligent observers on Earth. In contrast, fruitful studies like those of Greaves et al. (Reference Greaves, Wyatt, Holland and Dent2004) on Tau Ceti and other exoplanetary systems offer us a glimpse of the ‘true’ underlying physical background of the astrobiological evolution in the Milky Way. Besides, important philosophical questions related to the foundations of astrobiology need to be addressed. In particular, the observation-selection effects, often demeaned under the heading of anthropic principle(s), need to be re-evaluated, especially in view of their potentially important impact on all studies of future catastrophic risk facing an Earth-confined humanity (Bostrom & Ćirković Reference Bostrom and Ćirković2008).

Acknowledgements

The author uses this opportunity to thank the Future of Humanity Institute, Oxford, UK, for their kind hospitality during the period this paper was conceived. This work has been partially supported by the Ministry of Science of the Republic of Serbia through the project ON146012. Useful discussions with Anders Sandberg, Nick Bostrom, Robert Bradbury, George Dvorsky Slobodan Popović and Robin Hanson are also hereby acknowledged. Two referees have provided helpful comments on a previous version of the manuscript. Aleksandar Zorkić kindly helped in drawing Figure 2. Invaluable technical help and the kind encouragement of Irena Diklić have been instrumental in the completion of this project.

Footnotes

1 Supervolcanism gives us an example of an almost-too-strong environmental stress: Toba supereruption (Sumatra, Indonesia, 74 kyr BP) may have, according to at least one speculative hypothesis, reduced the human population to ~1000 individuals, nearly causing the extinction of humanity (Rampino & Self Reference Rampino and Self1992; Ambrose Reference Ambrose1998). Even if that is shown to be wrong by subsequent research, it seems clear that the high correlation of supervolcanic eruptions with the mass extinction episodes testifies to their evolutionary importance.

2 Earth-like planets have not been discovered yet around Tau Ceti, but in view of the crude observational techniques employed so far, it has not been expected; the new generation of planet-searching instruments currently in preparation (DARWIN, Gaia, TPF, etc.) will settle this problem.

3 On the other hand, one should not underrate the constructive aspect of global catastrophes, such as the oft-mentioned ‘evolution pump’ enabling faunal overturns and opening hitherto inaccessible parts of the evolutionary morphospace. This effect is, of course, extraordinarily hard to quantify (e.g. Kitchell & Pena Reference Kitchell and Pena1984; Benton Reference Benton1995). The reasoning similar to that above applies here too: any observer is bound to find – upon their developing evolutionary biology and paleontology in sufficient detail – that the evolutionary pump was sufficiently strong in their past. This is valid even if the a priori rate of catastrophic events is on average significantly lower than that commonly inferred from Earth's past record.

References

Alvarez, L., Alvarez, W., Asaro, F. & Michel, H.V. (1980). Extraterrestrial cause for the Cretaceous–Tertiary extinction. Science 208, 10951108.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ambrose, S.H. (1998). Late Pleistocene human population bottlenecks, volcanic winter, and differentiation of modern humans. J. Human Evolution 34, 623651.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barrow, J.D. & Tipler, F.J. (1986). The Anthropic Cosmological Principle. Oxford University Press, New York.Google Scholar
Benton, M.J. (1995). Diversification and extinction in the history of life. Science 268, 5258.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bostrom, N. (2002). Existential risks. J. Evolution Technol. 9 (http://www.jetpress.org/volume9/risks.html). 130.Google Scholar
Bostrom, N. & Ćirković, M.M. (eds) (2008). Global Catastrophic Risks. Oxford University Press, Oxford. In press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carter, B. (1983). The anthropic principle and its implications for biological evolution. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. London A 310, 347363.Google Scholar
Carter, B. (1993). The anthropic selection principle and the ultra-Darwinian synthesis. In The Anthropic Principle, Proceedings of the Second Venice Conference on Cosmology and Philosophy, eds Bertola, F. & Curi, U., pp. 3366. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Conway, Morris S. (1998). The Crucible of Creation: The Burgess Shale and the Rise of Animals. Oxford University Press, Oxford.Google Scholar
Conway, Morris S. (2003). Life's Solution: Inevitable Humans in a Lonely Universe. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Courtillot, V. (1999). Evolutionary Catastrophes. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Ćirković, M.M. & Bradbury, R.J. (2006). Galactic gradients, postbiological evolution and the apparent failure of SETI. New Ast. 11, 628639.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dick, S.J. (2003). Cultural evolution, the postbiological universe and SETI. Int. J. Astrobiology 2, 6574.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dyson, F.J. (1966). The search for extraterrestrial technology. In Perspectives in Modern Physics, ed. Marshak, R.E., pp. 641655. Interscience Publishers, New York.Google Scholar
Erwin, D.H. (2006). Extinction. Princeton University Press, Princeton.Google Scholar
Gould, S.J. (1987). SETI and the wisdom of Casey Stengel. In The Flamingo's Smile: Reflections in Natural History, pp. 403413. W. W. Norton, New York.Google Scholar
Gould, S.J. (1989). Wonderful Life. W. W. Norton, New York.Google Scholar
Greaves, J.S., Wyatt, M.C., Holland, W.S. & Dent, W.R.F. (2004). The debris disc around τ Ceti: a massive analogue to the Kuiper Belt. Mon. Not. R. Astron. Soc. 351, L54L58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hughes, D.W. (2003). The approximate ratios between the diameters of terrestrial impact craters and the causative incident asteroids. Mon. Not. R. Astron. Soc. 338, 9991003.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hut, P. & Rees, M.J. (1983). How stable is our vacuum? Nature 302, 508509.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitchell, J.A. & Pena, D. (1984). Periodicity of extinctions in the geologic past: deterministic versus stochastic explanations. Science 226, 689692.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Leslie, J. (1996). The End of the World: The Ethics and Science of Human Extinction. Routledge, London.Google Scholar
Maher, K.A. & Stevenson, D.J. (1988). Impact frustration of the origin of life. Nature 331, 612614.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McKay, C.P. (1996). Time for intelligence on other planets. In Circumstellar Habitable Zones, Proceedings of The First International Conference, ed. Doyle, L.R., pp. 405419. Travis House Publications, Menlo Park, CA.Google Scholar
McShea, D.W. (1998). Possible largest-scale trends in organismal evolution: eight ‘Live Hypotheses’. Annu. Rev. Ecol. Syst. 29, 293318.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rampino, M.R. & Self, S. (1992). Volcanic winter and accelerated glaciation following the Toba super-eruption. Nature 359, 5052.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raup, D.M. (1991). Extinction: Bad Genes or Bad Luck? W. W. Norton, New York.Google ScholarPubMed
Russell, D.A. (1983). Exponential evolution: implications for extraterrestrial intelligent life. Adv. Space Res. 3, 95103.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shanahan, T. (1999). Evolutionary progress from Darwin to Dawkins. Endeavour 23, 171174.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Shanahan, T. (2001). Methodological and contextual factors in the Dawkins/Gould dispute over evolutionary progress. Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. & Biomed. Sci. 32, 127151.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tipler, F.J. (2003). Intelligent life in cosmology. Int. J. Astrobiology 2, 141148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ward, P.D. & Brownlee, D. (2000). Rare Earth: Why Complex Life is Uncommon in the Universe. Springer, New York.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Webb, S. (2002). Where is Everybody? Fifty Solutions to the Fermi's Paradox. Copernicus, New York.Google Scholar
Wright, R. (2000). Nonzero: The Logic of Human Destiny. Pantheon Books, New York.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Fig. 1. The Goldilocks problem at the K–T boundary: only impactors in the narrow shaded strip would have led to the ‘right’ mass extinction (leading to the development of humans at the present epoch). Both smaller and larger impacts would have resulted in the non-existence of humans. This remains valid even if we acknowledge the existence of the empirical upper limit on the size of an impactor.

Figure 1

Fig. 2. A schematic presentation of the single-event toy model. The evidence E consists of our present-day existence.

Figure 2

Fig. 3. Overconfidence parameter as a function of the extinction probability 1 – Q in our single-event toy model. Different values of the real event probability density P (appropriately averaged) are colour-coded. We notice that the anthropic overconfidence bias is strongest for low-probability density (‘rare’) events.