I. Introduction
In recent years, the imaginations of patent lawyers have been captured by the possibility of patents for inventions made by machines. The question of machine inventors has been brought to the fore by a series of patent applications in which DABUS, an artificial intelligence-driven system, was designated as the inventor of the inventions that were the subject of those applications.Footnote 1 Not only was DABUS designated as the inventor, but it was also later reasserted that it indeed had devised the inventions and thus the inventions had no human inventor.Footnote 2
These events have fuelled a debate about whether artificial intelligence (AI) has reached a stage at which AI-driven systems are able to devise inventions. Some argue that the systems are not capable of any such achievements.Footnote 3 Others claim that the systems are indeed capable of producing patentable inventions, and that such inventions should be protected by patents without discrimination.Footnote 4 The disagreement may be due to both divergent perceptions of law and different understandings of technology. The legal differences concern the relevance of an invention's history to its patentability and the meaning of “devising inventions”; the technical differences relate to the capabilities of AI-driven systems.
This article seeks to clarify the legal grounds of debate. More specifically, it argues that in Europe the history of an invention is relevant to its patentability, and that this becomes obvious when European patent law is read holistically and in the light of its factual assumptions and theoretical underpinnings. This article argues that in European patent law human inventorship is implicitly present and requires an invention to be devised through a human creative intervention and intellectual activity of inventive quality. Human inventorship in this sense should be recognised as an implicit requirement as part of the statutory patentability requirements that there be an “invention” and that the subject matter of the application involves an “inventive step”. Although this investigation was prompted by concerns raised in relation to AI, the relevance of this analysis is not limited to the context of AI and its validity thus does not depend on the questioned capabilities of AI-driven systems to invent.
The analysis proceeds in four main stages. First, the article explains why the analysis is significant, and that is, in particular, because of developments in AI (Section II). Second, the article considers current European patent law and shows that human inventorship is both presupposed for an invention to exist and required for a legitimate grant of a European patent (Section III). Third, and perhaps more controversially, the article observes that human inventorship is reflected in the statutory patentability requirements for an invention and inventive step (Section IV). Fourth, the article proposes a modest reform with a view to restricting patent protection to products of human inventorship (Section V). If adopted, the reform would ensure the European patent system's capacity to deal with the growing reliance on AI in the production of inventions.Footnote 5
II. AI-generated Problem
The possibility that AI-driven systems are capable of inventing makes consideration of whether patent law contains a human inventorship requirement both an important and timely topic. More concretely, the question is whether the increasing AI-driven systems’ “autonomy” in the process of devising inventions may preclude human beings who designed those systems, fed them with data, or employed them, from claiming their inventorship in relation to the resulting subject matter.
A. Neural Networks
The AI technique most promising in terms of “autonomous inventing” is a neural network.Footnote 6 The idea of artificial neural networks comes from psychology and dates back to 1958 when Frank Rosenblatt published his work on “perceptron”, a probabilistic model for information storage and organisation in the brain.Footnote 7 In recent years, neural networks have been gaining momentum due to accessibility of vast amounts of data (Big Data), availability of efficient computing hardwareFootnote 8 and a major methodological advancement – implementation of more layers of networks with different structures and different roles in the whole network.Footnote 9
Neural networks are composed of interconnected nodes which carry a mathematical model.Footnote 10 These nodes receive and process inputs from their neighbouring nodes and generate an output if activated. Their activation depends on (1) a weighted sum of all incoming inputs, (2) a so-called activation function and (3) an activation threshold. Advanced neural networks also incorporate a so-called backpropagation function which enables the network to send feedback backwards (to the nodes in the previous level) and compute gradients of error and then optimise the weights accordingly.Footnote 11 Initially, the weights and activation thresholds can be set to random values and they adjust continually during the training.Footnote 12
Mainly thanks to the lack of precise instructions for computation and the continual adjusting of weights and activation thresholds on their own, neural networks seem to be in some sense autonomous. Crucially, the expert knowledge that neural networks embody is “opaque”.Footnote 13 To quote Michael Wooldridge, professor of Computer Science at Oxford who works in AI for few decades, “at present, we have no idea how to interpret the knowledge and representations that neural networks embody”.Footnote 14
Consequently, human beings who employ neural networks in the process of problem-solving may have neither the control over the concrete form of the solutions nor the ability to grasp those solutions intellectually before they are completed. For instance, in 2020, an AI-driven system identified a highly effective antibiotic called halicin. The system learnt representations of molecules “automatically, mapp[ed] molecules into continuous vectors [and designed] molecular representations that are highly attuned to the desired property”.Footnote 15 The approach of the system was analytical (using abstracted information about molecular representation inscrutable and unavailable to human beings). This change of method allowed identifying structurally different antibiotics.Footnote 16 The system was given a task to find a compound with a desired property in relation to E.coli bacterium (in European patent law terms, this was “the technical problem”), it was let to crawl chemical libraries and ranked halicin very high with respect to the desired property (in the same idiom, it offered a “technical solution”) which was a result that no human being involved in the process was able to control or have prior knowledge of.
The example of the discovery of halicin demonstrates that technical solutions can be produced without any human being originating those solutions in the sense of solving the problem themselves or determining the inventive features of the solution. Hence, these changes in the process of inventing raise important questions for patent law.
B. Framing the Problem
A high-profile policy initiative on the patentability of AI-driven systems’ outputs invites formulations of new definitions dependent on the notion of AI and on (generating vs assisting) capabilities of AI-driven systems.Footnote 17 The downside of such an approach is that there is no universally accepted definition of “AI” even in the AI field itself. Most definitions of AI are concerned either with thought processes and reasoning implying that the goal is to design machines that think like humans, or with behaviour aiming at machines that perform tasks that normally require intelligence when performed by humans.Footnote 18 This uncertainty will naturally impede the efforts towards defining AI and its capabilities for regulatory purposes.
In contrast, there are advantages to framing the debate on the patentability of AI-driven systems’ outputs by focussing on the relevant human activity.Footnote 19 The answer would then primarily depend on the legal definition of human activity or human intervention that makes the resulting invention merit patent protection. If a human activity corresponding to the legal definition is found to having been involved in the process of devising a particular subject matter, then the subject matter will constitute a product of human inventorship. As such it can qualify for patent protection regardless of the nature of AI intervention in the process (provided the AI intervention does not break the chain of causation between the relevant activity and the resulting object). The article adopts this framing and considers the role of human inventors and their activities in European patent law.
III. Origin of an Invention Matters
This part argues that European (and international) patent law presupposes that an invention has a human origin. This is so, even though no statutory provision explicitly states that patents must only be granted for products of human inventorship. The current European legislative framework is founded on factual assumptions about inventions and inventing which stem from contemporary experience of how technical solutions come to being.
A. The Role of Inventors
Patents as proprietary rights in intangible objects “emerged from the very tangible world of artisanship and crafts”Footnote 20 and hence the first inventors were artisans and craftsmen. The first patent statute which was enacted in Venice derived inventor's rights from “the very fact of his invention”Footnote 21 rather than from a privilege granted by a state. Individual rebellions against Renaissance guilds underscored the role of individual inventors and their ingenuity, such as a patent for the architect Brunelleschi was justified by “his own ingenuity and invention”.Footnote 22
In Elizabethan England patents also served to attract the importation of new technologies through welcoming their carriers and embodiments, namely foreign craftsmen and artisans.Footnote 23 Following public objections to royal prerogatives, the Statute of Monopolies 1623 prohibited them with few exceptions, including patents for “the true and first inventor”.Footnote 24 In Edgeberry v Stephens this piece of legislation was interpreted as encouraging the inflow of inventions “whether learned and acquired by study or travel”.Footnote 25
On the other side of the Atlantic, in 1788, one of the federalists, James Madison advocated that Congress be given the power
to promote the progress of science and useful arts, by securing, for a limited time, to authors and inventors, the exclusive right to their respective writings and discoveries. … The copyright of authors has been solemnly adjudged, in Great Britain, to be a right of common law. The right to useful inventions seems with equal reason to belong to the inventors.Footnote 26
The US Patent Act 1836 expressly referred to labour and desert policy when justifying the duration of patent rights which it was said ought to secure “for inventors the fruits of their inventive labors”.Footnote 27
By the time of the drafting of the first international patent law instrument, the Paris Convention (adopted in 1883), the common understanding was that only human beings were capable of coming up with solutions to technical problems or, put in other words, to invent.Footnote 28 This was reflected in Article 4ter of the Paris Convention which article guarantees a moral right of an inventor to be named as such in the patent.Footnote 29 In intellectual property law, moral rights are non-economic rights whose objective is to protect the dignity and personality of authors and inventors. As such they are associated with human beings only and hence the assumption embodied in that provision was that the inventor is a human being. Recognising and providing for the moral right of the inventor caused no noteworthy controversies among the drafters of the Paris Convention.Footnote 30
B. The Right to Be Named as the Inventor
Under the European Patent Convention 2000 (EPC), the inventor has the right, vis-à-vis the applicant for or proprietor of a European patent, to be mentioned as the inventor before the European Patent Office (EPO).Footnote 31 This provision gives effect to the inventor's moral right.Footnote 32 Correspondingly, Article 81 EPC requires the applicant to designate the inventor and “if the applicant is not the inventor or is not the sole inventor, the designation shall contain a statement indicating the origin of the right to the European patent”,Footnote 33 namely the way the title was transferred to the applicant.Footnote 34 Pursuant to Article 60 EPC, the right to the European patent originally belongs to the inventor and through them their successor in title or employer.
Although the EPO does not verify the identity of the inventor designated in the patent application, it notifies the designated inventor where the applicant is a different person.Footnote 35 Moreover, the EPO checks the formal requirements of the patent application.Footnote 36 This includes checking whether the inventor was designated in a request for grant of a European patent where the applicant is the sole inventor,Footnote 37 or whether the inventor was designated in a separate document where the applicant is not the inventor or the sole inventor.Footnote 38 In case the formal requirements are not met, the patent application shall be refused under Article 90(5) EPC.
The European patent applications which designated the AI-driven system, DABUS, as the inventor, met just this fate. They were refused by the EPO on the ground that they did not designate the inventor.Footnote 39 From this verdict it follows that an AI-driven system cannot serve as a designated inventor in the patent grant proceedings before the EPO. Presumably, this is because the EPC system presupposes that each invention has an individualised human inventor. The EPO's verdict also makes clear that the failure to designate a human being as the inventor raises a formal obstacle to the substantive examination of the patent application and thus grant of a European patent. Thereby, at least formally and implicitly, it is required that the invention the subject of a patent application has a human inventor.
The trouble is that in practice, in the event of a de facto absence of human inventor, the provision of Article 62 EPC securing the right of the inventor to be named becomes irrelevant. Moreover, it seems that the above-mentioned formal obstacle to the grant of a European patent can be (pragmatically rather than legally) overcome by merely naming a natural person as the inventor in the European patent application since the identity of the inventor is not verified by the EPO. The possibility of such a manoeuvre exposes a shortcoming with the examination system as set out by the EPC and its Implementing Regulations. Consequently, subject matter that have a human inventor on paper only (and do not in fact have one) could proceed to a substantive examination as if they were products of human inventorship.
C. The Right to a Patent
Even if the problem of missing human inventor may seem of little practical consequence in the patent grant proceedings before the EPO (provided applicants put a name of a human being forward as a matter of formality), it becomes more intriguing when it comes to entitlement to a European patent.
To reiterate, pursuant to Article 60(1) EPC, the right to a European patent shall belong to the inventor or his successor in title. This right comprises the “inventor's personal right [that has as its object] the relationship of the inventor to their creation and a personal position and acknowledgment resulting therefrom”Footnote 40 on one hand and the material right to grant of a patent derived therefrom on the other hand.Footnote 41 The right to a European patent is an expression of a “fundamental principle of almost all European patent systems”Footnote 42 and arises upon completion of the invention.Footnote 43 Thus, the right to patent exists by virtue of the act of invention and it precedes the grant of the patent by an act of state administration.
The EPC does not specify what one must do to gain the status of inventor and thus become originally entitled to the European patent. The individual inventorship question as well as any disputes related to the entitlement are to be brought before national courts of the EPC Contracting States.Footnote 44 These courts apply the respective national patent laws that define the inventor as a human being who actually devised,Footnote 45 made,Footnote 46 or originatedFootnote 47 an invention.
In UK law, for example, an inventor is defined as the actual deviser of the invention.Footnote 48 The actual deviser of the invention is understood to be the “natural person”Footnote 49 who “came up with the inventive concept”Footnote 50 or who “was responsible for the inventive concept”.Footnote 51 More specifically, to merit the status of an inventor, one must originate the inventive idea or contribute information necessary to make the idea patentable and enable the invention to work.Footnote 52 Entrepreneurial or managerial contributions are unlikely to be seen as inventive contributions.Footnote 53 In general, UK law requires a natural person to develop an inventive idea sufficiently to enable its use by others to solve a technical problem. Hence, human inventorship entails the origination and development of the inventive concept embodied in the invention.
Before the EPO, the person deemed entitled to exercise the right to a European patent is the applicant.Footnote 54 Given this provision, as well as the EPO's lack of competence to examine the entitlement, a European patent may happen to be granted to a person who is not entitled to it, i.e. in breach of Article 60(1) EPC. However, this can be remedied in the post-grant phase, as the European patent can be revoked by national courts of the EPC Contracting States (with the effect ex tunc and for the territory of the respective Contracting States) on the ground that its proprietor is not entitled to itFootnote 55 (lack of entitlement).
Taking this together, a European patent is legitimately granted only if it is granted to the human inventor of the underlying invention which is the subject of the application or their successor in title. Should a European patent be granted despite its proprietor's lack of entitlement, such a patent is open to a revocation attack. If eventually revoked, it is then treated as if it had never been granted in the first place.
As the revocation on the ground of lack of entitlement is governed by national laws, the revocation proceedings in the EPC Contracting States differ to some extent. For instance, in the UK, they can only be initiated by a person who was found by the court or the comptroller to be entitled to be granted that patent.Footnote 56 In Germany, application for the revocation can be brought only by an interested party, and, in case of usurpation only by the injured party.Footnote 57 In France, only the inventor or their successor in title can seek revocation on the ground of lack of entitlement.Footnote 58
This excursion to national patent laws, albeit brief, shows that the initiation of national revocation proceedings on the ground of lack of entitlement under Article 138(1)(e) EPC lies largely in the hands of the inventor or their successor in title. This is reinforced by the fact that neither the EPO nor national patent authorities (at least in the UK and Germany)Footnote 59 check the entitlement ex officio. As observed by Marcus Smith J. in relation to the UK DABUS patent application, an applicant's statements concerning the identity of an inventor or succession in title cannot possibly be audited by the national patent authority in each case.Footnote 60 Consequently, in practice, in the de facto absence of a human inventor, there seems to be no legal basis for revocation of a European patent due to lack of entitlement.
In sum, the EPC system presupposes the existence of an individualised human inventor and reflects this normatively, both in the inventor's designation and entitlement requirements under Articles 62, 81 and 60(1) EPC. Reading this in conjunction with national definitions of an inventor, a human being devising an invention is assumed to be a precondition for the existence of an invention as well as for the legitimate grant of a European patent. Hence, the human origin and history of an invention is of legal significance under the EPC system. However, as the existence of human inventors is taken for granted without verifying the inventors’ status or legitimacy of applicants’ entitlement declarations, the EPC system fails to operate flawlessly in the scenario where there is no human inventor.
D. Patentability
Leaving the realm of individual inventors’ rights and their relative claims, this article argues that (general) human inventorship is a necessary condition for the patentability of any subject matter. As shown above, the existence of an individualised human inventor and their inventorship are presupposed by the EPC (and the Paris Convention).
The presumption that each invention has an individualised human inventor subsumes a more general belief that an invention originates from a human being. More specifically, in the UK, German and French laws, the inventor is defined as someone who actually devised, made or originated respectively an invention. Rephrasing this in a subject matter-centred fashion, an invention can be understood as something actually having been devised or made by an inventor,Footnote 61 namely something owing its existence to a certain kind of human activity or intervention.
The proposition that the existence of an invention is predicated on human activity or intervention has been made on a number of other occasions. For instance, Professor Pila recognises “origination in an act of human creation (requiring a certain talent or capacity)” as one of the common definitional elements of intellectual property subject matter.Footnote 62 Elsewhere, Professor Sherman conceptualises invention as “a product of a process in which a human agent (or inventor) exercises their inventive skills to build on, modify, or adapt preexisting natural materials”.Footnote 63
Accounts along these lines are also found in commentaries from civil law jurisdictions. The former German Supreme Court judge Melullis describes the importance of human activity for the concept of invention as follows: “[a]s a result of an intellectual activity by individualised natural persons the invention is necessarily connected with the inventor; an invention without inventor is not thinkable.”Footnote 64 Professor Haedicke writes that “the prerequisite for every invention … is an intellectual process of invention”.Footnote 65
The language of origination and intellectual process brings copyright to mind. Drawing a parallel between copyright and patents could be helpful to demonstrate the relationship between human authoring (or inventing) and copyright subsistence (or patentability) of a resulting subject matter. Indeed, Professor Ginsburg argues that “originality is synonymous with authorship”Footnote 66 while the conceptions of originality (and so the contribution required to gain the status of author) differ jurisdiction by jurisdiction.Footnote 67 At a more abstract level though, originality is an internationally recognised copyright subsistence criterion.Footnote 68 Hence, in principle, if a subject matter does not have any human author and thus lacks human authorship, not only there is no one entitled to copyright, but also, and more fundamentally, such subject matter is not eligible for copyright protection as an authorial work.Footnote 69
It is curious that the connection between human inventorship (or human origin) and patentability of a subject matter does not attract much attention in modern scholarship.Footnote 70 Yet, scrutinising the patentability of subject matter that have not in fact been devised by a human inventor (but that might easily be disguised as having been so devised) is important for preserving the coherence and integrity of the modern patent system.
If subject matter that lacks human inventors could enjoy patent protection, this would be at odds with the idea of patents as rewards and incentives for human beings who devise inventions and disclose them. Granting patents for products of human inventorship as well as subject matter lacking a human inventor would eventually render the patent system incoherent and its outcomes inconsistent because it would mean treating fundamentally dissimilar objects equally. It would also represent significant legal reform by means of administrative and judicial decision-making rather than democratic legislative process.
IV. Reflections of Human Inventorship in the Statutory Patentability Requirements
Pursuant to Article 52(1) EPC, “European patents shall be granted for any inventions, in all fields of technology, provided they are new, involve an inventive step and are susceptible of industrial application”. Out of these statutory patentability criteria, this section focuses on the requirements for an invention and inventive step. At first glance, the requirement for an invention appears to be the closest reflection of human inventorship in positive law as the invention represents the inventor's contribution to the state of the art.Footnote 71 Equally, the requirement for an inventive step aims at identifying the inventor's intellectual contribution as it is suggested by its anthropomorphic phrasing.Footnote 72
Further, this section analyses the approaches to the application of these requirements adopted by the EPO and courts in the UK, Germany and France. These jurisdictions emerge from different legal traditions while adhering to the same patentability requirements harmonised by the EPC in 1973. The analysis indicates that despite these jurisdictions sharing the overarching legal basis and following the decision-making practice of the EPO,Footnote 73 they take marginally different approaches to the application of the requirements.
In each of these approaches, however, the concept of “invention” is reduced to designate merely a technical feature (the EPO, France), belonging to a technical field (Germany) or technical contribution (the UK). As a result, there is a danger that these approaches overlook the human component of invention, meaning that the authorities may find a subject matter that falls within a technical field or has a technical feature which, however, may lack the relevant human origin.
In the application of the requirement for an inventive step, the notion of “obviousness” overshadowed human intellectual aspects of the inventive step which are emphasised in the EPC drafting documents, recognised in Actavis v ICOS (the UK) and found in a typology of inventive activities (Germany, France). Such approaches to application can lead to finding non-obviousness in inventions which may not involve the relevant human intellectual activity.
A. The Invention Requirement
The criterion of an “invention” is a self-standing patentability requirement under the EPCFootnote 74 and any subject matter must first qualify as an invention. The rare instance where the nature of an invention has been more comprehensively considered by the most authoritative interpreter, the Enlarged Board of Appeal of the European Patent Office (EBA),Footnote 75 is Tomatoes/State of Israel. Footnote 76 The EBA was asked, inter alia, whether a method of crossing and selecting plants escapes the exclusion of Article 53(b) EPC of “essentially biological processes” by virtue of containing an additional feature of a technical nature.Footnote 77
In its response, the EBA made a general statement that the “essence of invention” is “human intervention in a process in order to bring about a desired result”.Footnote 78 The EBA thus interpreted the concept of “invention” as requiring “human intervention”Footnote 79 or an intentional abstention therefrom.Footnote 80 Most recently, this approach was embraced in the EBA's decision on patentability of a simulation method (i.e. outside the biotechnology context).Footnote 81 The EBA also added that the technicality of the invention “implies that an object is created, or a process is run with some purpose based on human creativity”.Footnote 82
These decisions suggest that a human intervention is required for an invention to be created.Footnote 83 In Tomatoes, the EBA required the intervention to cause a durable and permanent change in the resulting subject matter (such as a genetic change in a living productFootnote 84) and that the intervention was repeatable.Footnote 85 The EBA thus acknowledged the necessity of a causal connection between a human being who intervenes in the world with a view to achieving a desired result and a materialised result.Footnote 86 Such causally determinative human intervention is referred to henceforth as human “creative” intervention.
1. The invention vs discovery
An invention (understood as a creation) is often juxtaposed to an unpatentable discovery. According to a Comparative Study of Substantive Law (the “Comparative Study”) which influenced the drafting of the EPC 1973 and its accompanying Community Patent Convention, “[a]s a general rule, a patent can only protect an invention (a creation) and not a discovery, i.e. the simple taking note of a pre-existant [sic] reality”.Footnote 87
The French scholarship captures the distinction as follows: “[i]n the invention itself, the activity of a human is productive, in the discovery, [the activity] is, so to say, receiving.”Footnote 88 This is affirmed by another definition of an invention founded on the underlying activity and thus defined as “every action or endeavour of a human being to shape and utilise the nature and the matter”.Footnote 89
The German account of the distinction hinges on the relevant activity as well: “ʻ[i]nvention' and ʻdiscovery' each describe the product of a particular human activity, that of discovering and that of inventing. These two forms [discovery and invention], therefore, simply mean ʻwhat is discovered' and ʻwhat is invented' and primarily indicate the nature of activity that leads to this acquisition of knowledge.”Footnote 90
In general, a discovery involves finding and disclosing information about the natural world, including describing properties of a pre-existing matter.Footnote 91 A transformation of a discovery into an invention requires “an act of invention or human ingenuity”.Footnote 92 For instance, a discovery that is implemented in a reproducible process may constitute an invention whereas a mere reformulation of a discovery in the form of a technical teaching does not render it patentable.Footnote 93 Exceptionally, the required human intervention is specified, such as in the case of biotechnological inventions the making of which requires an act of isolation of biological material from its natural environment, or its synthetic production.Footnote 94
2. Teleological interpretation and historic reasons for a human intervention
The policy documents which accompanied the amendments of the EPC in 2000 further corroborate the importance of creations under the EPC framework. Prominently, they state that “[t]he new wording of Article 52(1) EPC plainly expresses that patent protection is reserved for creations in the technical field”.Footnote 95 This equates inventions with creations. According to the Oxford English Dictionary, the ordinary meanings of “creation” are (1) “something created by divine or natural agency” and (2) “an original production of human intelligence, power, skill, or art; esp. a work of imagination”.Footnote 96 Since modern patent law was designed for human inventors and their inventions, (Section III) creations by God and nature can be disregarded.
Hence, the reference to creations in all technical fields refers to products of human intelligence, skill, etc. in all technical fields. The Comparative Study further emphasises the role of human origin of an invention: “one can infer from what has been said the rule that the author of a patentable invention must have been presented with a problem and have indicated a solution to it.”Footnote 97
In the landmark decision Rote Taube (pre-dating the EPC 1973), the German Supreme Court affirmed that subject matter should not be treated as non-inventions when they involve a methodical utilisation of controllable natural forces and phenomena (not only in the fields of physics, chemistry but also biology) to achieve a causal, perceivable result.Footnote 98 The requirement of repeatability of the method and reproducibility of the result was adopted by the EBA in Tomatoes/State of Israel to form part of the EBA's interpretation of the notion of “invention”.
As creations from all technical fields must be treated equally,Footnote 99 an identical definition of an invention should apply to subject matter coming from any field of technology. Therefore, the authorities should apply the same standard to ascertain whether a given subject matter is an invention, including the aspect of its origin. This means asking whether the subject matter constitutes a product of human creative intervention, and thus is attributable to a human being.
3. Application of the invention requirement
In practice, when the EPO examines the requirement for an invention, the scrutiny is limited to finding so-called “technical character”. The requirement of technical character emerged from the case law on the application of Article 52(2) EPC. This provision contains a non-exhaustive list of categories of subject matter that are excluded from patentability as non-inventions.Footnote 100 This list may also be read as a “negative definition of the notion of invention”Footnote 101 and it “covers subjects whose common feature is a substantial lack of technical character”.Footnote 102
Yet, where a subject matter merely relates to excluded subject matter it can qualify for protection as an invention provided its technical character is demonstrated.Footnote 103 It is through this interpretative route (via the negative definition of an invention) that the requirement for an invention became transformed into a “requirement of technicality”Footnote 104 (or technicity). In practice, the technical character can be demonstrated through a subject matter (1) involving technical means, (2) producing a technical result or (3) involving a technical field of human activity.Footnote 105 When it comes to computer-implemented methods, the EPO looks for “further technical effect”Footnote 106 going beyond the normal interaction of the features.
In the UK practice, no positive definition of an invention is recognised by courts.Footnote 107 In the view of Lord Hoffmann, the novelty, inventive step and industrial applicability criteria, when taken in conjunction, probably amount to an invention, unless the grant of a patent for it is excluded.Footnote 108 A subject matter is considered not to be excluded if the contribution contained therein is “actually technical in nature”.Footnote 109 In the case of computer-implemented inventions, the required technicity is established if the subject matter produces a relevant technical effect which depends on the facts of each case.Footnote 110
For instance, in HTC Europe v Apple, it was found that “a method of dividing up the screen of such a device into views and configuring each view as a multi-touch view or a single-touch view using flags with a specific functionality” makes a technical contribution, its embodiment in software notwithstanding, as it “presents a new and improved interface to application programmers, … and makes it easier for them to write application software”.Footnote 111 This approach reduces the legal question of whether the subject matter constitutes an invention to a set of questions of fact of what type of improvement of what type of software counts as an improvement of hardware.Footnote 112
In contrast to the UK practice, current French law officially recognises the requirement for an invention as a “true, positive and autonomous requirement”Footnote 113 which is separate from the excluded subject matter categories. However, it seems that French courts “do not take it into consideration, at least explicitly”.Footnote 114 Rather, the courts follow the EPO practice. It is noteworthy that interpreting the notion of “invention” as “having a technical character” caused its semantic overlap with another patentability requirement: “[t]he historic condition of industrial character may cover not only the modern requirement for industrial applicability but also the one for invention [as in the past] industrial meant to produce technical goods or results.”Footnote 115
In German law, the concept of invention has been consumed by the requirement for “technicity” which is understood as a “solution serving to solve a concrete technical problem with technical means”.Footnote 116 As a result, a subject matter is found to amount to an invention if it provides such a solution through technical means or if it is “characterised by a piece of knowledge that is based on technical considerations”.Footnote 117
What makes some considerations technical or what types of problem can be characterised as “technical” remains unclear. The concept of the technicity (Technikbegriff) is dynamicFootnote 118 and therefore it can accommodate subject matter lying in all future branches of the traditional technical fields.Footnote 119 Recently, this dynamic potential was realised when German courts accommodated data processing, storing and transmission among fields of technology.Footnote 120
To summarise, the assessment of whether a subject matter amounts to an invention is concerned with its technical features or effect. The requirement is deemed fulfilled if the subject matter comprises a technical feature or relates to a technical field. This means, in effect, that, the two definitional elements of (1) invention and (2) lying in any of the technical fields (i.e. an “invention in all fields of technology”Footnote 121) were merged into a single concept of “technicity”. Consequently, the approaches depending on “technicity” fail to address the possibility of a subject matter that, on the face of it, falls within a technical field or has a technical feature but which does not constitute an invention – due to lack of human creative intervention.
B. The Inventive Step Requirement
For a grant of a European patent, an invention must be inventive in terms of involving an inventive step or activityFootnote 122 as well as achieving some progress or advancement of the state of the art.Footnote 123 In relation to human inventorship, the requirement for an inventive activity may seem to play second fiddle to the invention requirement.
Nonetheless, this section argues that the requirement for an inventive activity reflects human inventorship in requiring a genuine intellectual activity involved in solving the underlying technical problem. The required activity is intended to be of human origin because it is referred to as “intellectual” in the EPC drafting documents and is benchmarked against a hypothetical decision-making and acts of a notional natural person-the person skilled in the art. In this respect, the person skilled in the art standard works similarly to other legal standards of notional persons, such as “reasonable person” or “average consumer”.
1. Teleological interpretation and historic reasons for a human inventive step
Contrary to the conventional approach which focuses on inventiveness as a property of an invention, here the interpretation of the requirement begins with the literal meaning of the notion of “inventive activity” and its purpose. As a treaty of international public law, the EPC must be interpreted “in good faith in accordance with the ordinary meaning to be given to the terms of the treaty in their context and in the light of its object and purpose”.Footnote 124 Therefore, the terms of “inventive step” or “inventive activity” shall be given their ordinary meaning of inventive (intellectual) step or activity. Hence, the activity that is required to be involved in devising an invention under Article 52(1) and Article 56 EPC means (1) a genuine intellectual activity that is (2) of a certain quality.
Under the heading “creative effort”, the Comparative Study references a requirement that “the invention should represent a manifestation of intelligence which appreciably exceeds the normal train of thought of which any specialist in art would be capable”.Footnote 125 Kühnemann's report to which the EPC travaux préparatoires refer as well, formulates “the requirement of creative effort in an indirect manner so that a realisation of a subject matter that was within the reach of an average expert was excluded from patentability”.Footnote 126 Additionally, a German delegate to the Patents Working Party expressed the view that “under German law, the concept of Erfindungshöhe [inventive level] did not necessarily involve creative effort (flash of genius) on the part of the inventor. It was enough if he broke new ground and applied some intellectual activity”.Footnote 127
There is an observable tension inherent in these accounts. On one hand, an involvement of inventor's genuine intellectual activity in the process of devising an invention is both presupposed and required. Requiring a genuine intellectual activity is also aligned with the purpose of patent systems as laid out in justificatory theories (Section IV(D) below). On the other hand, when it comes to the inventive quality of the activity and how to prove it, there is a reluctance to define it in positive terms.
As a result, Article 56 EPC provides for a legal presumption of inventive activity: “[a]n invention shall be considered as involving an inventive step if, having regard to the state of the art, it is not obvious to a person skilled in the art.” Hence, inventiveness is measured according to an objective standard of an average expert and a hypothetical of what would have been within their reach. In effect, to make an inventive invention, an inventor is required to do what an average expert would not have done.
2. Application of the inventive step requirement
Where an invention consists of both technical and non-technical features, the inventive step is assessed only in respect of those features that contribute to the solution of the technical problem by providing a technical effectFootnote 128 (or a further technical effect in the case of computer-implemented methods). Hence, the necessary intellectual activityFootnote 129 should be involved directly in solving a technical problem and thus be reflected in those features that contribute to the solution.Footnote 130
However, in practice, the EPO does not examine whether an intellectual activity was actually involved in solving the underlying problem. Rather, the EPO deals exclusively with the inventiveness (or non-obviousness) standard. Whether the standard is achieved is examined from the position and capabilities of a person skilled in the art (PSA). The PSA is a notional expert (or a team of experts) in the technical field of the inventionFootnote 131 who has common general knowledge, has read all publicly available documents, knows publicly available uses of the technology, understands all languagesFootnote 132 and possesses the necessary equipment and technical tools which vary according to the technical field. This person is conservativeFootnote 133 and unimaginative and therefore they would miss every step that goes beyond ordinary good practice and routine.
To determine whether an invention is non-obvious, the EPO uses a so-called problem-and-solution test. The test comprises the following steps: “determining the ʻclosest prior art', defining the ʻobjective technical problem' to be solved, and assessing whether or not the claimed invention, starting from the closest prior art and the objective technical problem, would have been obvious to the skilled person”.Footnote 134
The UK non-obviousness test, the “Windsurfing/Pozzoli test”, is a sort of problem-and-solution test which in its fourth stage (closes the circle as it) asks whether overcoming the differences between the prior art and the invention is obvious or requires any degree of invention, namely an inventive activity.Footnote 135 The UK courts approach obviousness as a multi-factorial assessment,Footnote 136 a kind of jury question, whereby finding obviousness depends on concrete circumstances of the case.Footnote 137
In Actavis v ICOS the Supreme Court stressed that the problem-and-solution tests should not be applied mechanistically.Footnote 138 This case cautions against the reduction of the assessment of an inventive step to a mere test for non-obviousness as manifested in the invention. An invention can (wrongly) be found inventive only because in its concrete form (e.g. 5 mg dose in Actavis v ICOS) it would have been non-obvious and surprising to the PSA at the beginning of the process of its devising. However, it would be wrong to infer involvement of an inventive activity from the non-obviousness of the invention because the non-obvious air of the invention does not make the routine, non-inventive steps (which would have led to its devising) inventive. As reiterated by the Supreme Court, the steps or the activities which would have been undertaken by a PSA in the process of devising the invention are decisive.
German courts, too, apply a problem-and-solution testFootnote 139 within which they address the following questions: (1) Which steps would the PSA have had to undertake so that they achieved the solution of the patent in question? (2) Would they have had any instigations or considerations prompting them to set the direction towards the invention? (3) What are the reasons for or against the fact that the PSA would have arrived at the solution proposed in the patent on the basis of such considerations?Footnote 140 The focus is strictly on comparison of the actual outcome and the hypothetical outcome of the hypothetical process of thinking and acting which would have been performed by the PSA.Footnote 141
The approach of French courts closely follows the one of the EPO as well.Footnote 142 In brief, according to the French Supreme Court, it is sufficient to succinctly conclude that “the state of the art did not suggest the invention”Footnote 143 and, as a consequence, trigger the legal presumption of inventive activity.
In sum, the approaches to the application of the inventive step requirement have developed to a mere comparison of the claimed invention with the prior art. The authorities then may easily lose sight of the literal meaning and purpose of the requirement for an inventive step and omit to ask whether a genuine intellectual activity was involved in the process of invention and whether this activity was of a certain quality which is to be measured by PSA's hypothetical steps.
3. The actual inventive activity and typology of inventive activities
Despite the proclaimed disregard for the way the inventor made their invention or inventor's subjective assessment of their efforts,Footnote 144 the UK courts consider so-called “secondary evidence”. These relate to the contemporaneous events, reactions to the invention, the realities surrounding making the particular invention and actual ways of approaching the particular technical problem undertaken at the time of the invention.Footnote 145 Telling the actual story of an inventor devising the invention can be favourable to the patentee.Footnote 146
Moreover, the German and French application practice yields a typology of inventive activities. The activities of overcoming technical obstacles, formulating a novel technical problem and breaking new ground,Footnote 147 answering a series of objectively difficult questions,Footnote 148 reversing a bias, misleading belief or technical stereotype,Footnote 149 surprising a PSA,Footnote 150 making a selection from among a great number of possible solutions or combining at least three documents of prior artFootnote 151 are all considered inventive. Thereby, the jurisprudence indicates what kind of activity may constitute the necessary intellectual activity to devise an inventive invention.
C. Human Inventorship as Reflected in the Statutory Patentability Requirements
It is necessary to acknowledge that the requirements for an invention and inventive activity do not offer a complete picture of human inventorship even if read in the light of the underlying factual assumptions and the purpose of these requirements. Yet, they render some reflection of human inventorship: a subject matter must constitute a creation, namely a result of a human intervention which intervention directly and causally determines the relevant elements of the subject matter to meet the requirement for an invention. To meet the requirement for an inventive activity, a subject matter must constitute a result of a genuine intellectual activity expended on solving the technical problem in a manner that makes the invention inaccessible to an average expert.
If European patent law is treated as a coherent body of norms, the national rules on inventorship for entitlement purposes (which define the inventor as a person who devises, makes, or originates an invention) could help to sharpen the contours of the implicit requirement for (general) human inventorship. Bringing these national rules on individual inventorship and the reflection of human inventorship in the statutory patentability criteria together, human inventorship requires an invention to be devised through a human creative intervention and intellectual activity of inventive quality.
A subject matter that is not a result of the required human creative intervention and human inventive activity is not merely excluded because there is no “inventor,” but also because there is neither an “invention” nor subject matter that involves an “inventive step.” Such subject matter cannot be readily accommodated by the EPC system without compromising the system's theoretical basis, foundational factual assumptions and rules on entitlement and designation of the inventor.
D. Human Inventorship as Reflected in Justificatory Theories
On a more abstract level, human inventorship and human creative activity are the cornerstones of many patent justificatory theories which accompany patent laws from their early days until today.
Human intellectual creative effort, conception of an idea and mental labour are nowadays associated with copyright rather than with patents. Despite this stereotype, in the nineteenth century, the language of creativity was used in “all areas of law which granted property rights in mental labour”,Footnote 152 including patent law, and “the model of creativity employed by the law was not limited to literary property nor was it restricted to the late eighteenth century”.Footnote 153
For Adam Smith, Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill, patents were just compensation and reward for a person's mental labour and experimental endeavours.Footnote 154 While these “reward-by-monopoly” theories were based on merit and fairness reasons,Footnote 155 the idea of patents as rewards and thus incentives for human creative activity forms part of more contemporary narratives as well.
For instance, as put by the economist Fritz Machlup in the mid-twentieth century, “the profit expectations connected with the hope for a patent monopoly may induce inventive talents to exert their efforts”.Footnote 156 He further acknowledges that even after the ways of organising research and innovation in technology have changed over time, the ultimate task – to induce inventive talents to exert their effort – remains unchanged.Footnote 157 The common justificatory theme of the reward and incentives theories is the involvement of human intellectual and creative activity in a process that results in an inventive contribution to the art.
There are other influential justificatory theories that are not centred on human inventorship. Chief among them is “exchange-for-secrets” theory which is oriented at disclosing inventions in a sufficient (or enabling) manner in contrast to keeping them in secrecy. In the UK, the requirement of sufficient disclosure emerged in case law in the final decades of the eighteenth century.Footnote 158 In this connection, a theory of social contract between an inventor and the public developed whereby the justification for granting patents became the sufficiency of disclosure of the invention. Yet, even after the social contract model established itself as the dominant justification in the UK, inventors’ labours and heroic stories of invention were reasons for special recognition through rewards granted by the Parliament.Footnote 159
What is more, the “exchange-for-secrets” theory has never operated self-sufficiently. It rather stands on the shoulders of the property, reward, and incentive theories as it neither relies on disclosing subject matter that have not been devised nor justifies property rights where the legitimising relationship between the subject matter and its inventor is missing.Footnote 160
Another set of justificatory reasons for the patent system is offered by Kitch's prospect theory. This asserts that the patent system promotes the efficient allocation of opportunities (prospects).Footnote 161 However, as Kitch himself acknowledges, his prospect theory is only complementary to rewards theory which is founded on human inventorship.Footnote 162
Hence, the raison d’être of patents can be formulated as to incentivise human beings (possibly through intermediaries) to employ their brainpower, talents and creativity in efforts to devise a contribution to the state of the art and, if successful, disclose it in a sufficient manner. It follows that any contributions to the state of the art whose production did not involve human inventorship in the above sense ought to lie outside the scope of patent protection.
V. Test for Human Inventorship
Since an individualised human inventor who devised an invention is factually presupposed, the EPC system has not hitherto developed specific means to verify or test whether an invention the subject of a patent application indeed has a human inventor. The human inventorship aspects are almost entirely overlooked in the application of the requirements for an invention and inventive activity. Before AI-driven systems replace human inventors in performing narrowly defined tasks of solving specific technical problems and authorities encounter technical solutions with no human inventors, these shortcomings may be regarded as mere idiosyncrasies of the system. Yet, given the current advancements in AI and the employment of neural networks in the production of inventions, the factual assumptions about human inventorship become problematic.
Therefore, this article proposes a reform that builds on the implicit requirement for human inventorship. Foremost, the requirements for an invention and inventive step should be interpreted in a way that takes their human inventorship aspects into account, namely whether the subject matter owes its existence to a human creative intervention and intellectual activity of inventive quality. For this purpose, patent applicants should be required to disclose the role of an AI-driven system,Footnote 163 if any, in devising the subject matter in a manner enabling to conduct an adequate patentability assessment.
Such a disclosure could be part of the description of the technical problem and solution according to Rule 42.Footnote 164 The applicant would be obliged to disclose if, and to what extent, an AI-driven system was used and describe the steps in the process that were undertaken by it. Whenever an applicant fails to explain the steps undertaken by an AI-driven system and their significance, the EPO should refuse the application under Article 90 EPC for not complying with the formal requirements of patentability.
The disclosure should supply enough information to assess, on a case-by-case basis, whether the activities conducted by human beings in the process of devising the subject matter possessed the required creative and intellectual inventive quality in relation to the technical features of the subject matter. For instance, if the invention is found non-obvious, it should also be ascertained whether the non-obviousness is not due to the steps undertaken by the AI-driven system (which may be superior to the state-of-the-art AI-driven systems).
In practical terms, such a reform could be easily achieved because it is a mere extension of the existing description of the technical problem and solution under Rule 42 with a view to equipping examiners with more relevant information.Footnote 165 The reform is not in conflict with the EPC Contracting States’ commitments in the realm of patent law because it does not introduce any new patentability condition, nor impedes the grant of patents procedurally.Footnote 166
To ensure a wider scrutiny of involvement of human inventorship, competitors and the public in general should be able to challenge the accuracy of the disclosure before the EPO or national courts, such as via revocation under Article 138(1)(a) EPC on the ground that the subject matter is not patentable.Footnote 167 At the end of the day, this would enhance transparency regarding the role of AI in the production of inventions and enable recalibration of examination practices accordingly.
VI. Conclusion
If modern patent law is to cope with the ever wider and more significant employment of AI-driven systems in devising novel technical solutions, it is desirable to remedy the shortcomings in examination and adjudication regimes. At the heart of the problem is a failure of the current approaches to appreciate the central role of human inventorship not only in determining the entitlement to a patent but also in the patentability of subject matter. To establish the presence of human inventorship with confidence, applicants should be obliged to disclose the necessary information. Only then it will be possible to ensure that the patent protection is restricted to the true inventors for their inventions.