1. The link between international law's humanization and constitutionalization, and the article's scope
The theory of the humanization of international law might be seen as contiguous or even complementary to the theory – or theories – on the constitutionalization of international law.Footnote 1 As is well known, the humanization theory argues that human rights have had, and continue to have, major impacts on numerous areas of international law, which, owing to that influence, is now perceived as an increasingly humanized legal system.Footnote 2 While there is no single conceptual denotation of constitutionalization, it could be summarized as an intellectual ‘project, which argues that the international legal order beyond the state exists and has a backbone, a foundational set of norms’.Footnote 3 Human rights could be seen as part of that foundational set of norms, and a common locus that bridges the two named, separate but interlinked narratives of international law and the international legal order. ‘Other than the object of the humanization of international law, human rights are one of the “ingredients” of [its] constitutionalization.’Footnote 4
This article focuses on that common ingredient – i.e., human rights – of the two named theories and observes that the transplantation of human rights from national constitutions to international law has generated major systemic changes in the latter's order that could be described by proponents of the constitutionalization theory as constitutional in nature. The core assumption we make is that the internationalization of national constitutions,Footnote 5 and especially of their human rights protection provisions, has led to the “constitutionalization” of international law.Footnote 6 This movement is reflected in the paper's title that asks whether the international legal system is moving towards the direction of acquiring a humanized “constitution”. Two preliminary explanations are due at this point.
First, there is a reason why the terms “constitution” and “constitutionalization” are between quotation marks in the previous paragraph as well as in the paper's title. In essence, we are somewhat critically “agnostic” about the constitutionalization narrative, and its power as a metaphor to explain international law and its structures. The reasons for our scepticism are briefly discussed in Section 2 of the article, but for now we would like to preface our position to the reader by saying that international law, like all legal orders, has always contained certain systemic characteristics that underpin its order,Footnote 7 and which are exclusive to it and stem from the nature of the society that developed it for its own needs and use. International law is a state-centric, decentralized, quasi-anarchic legal system. Such is the être of its constitutive society. Its core principles, sovereignty and equality, reflect the basic feature of its main “actors”, i.e., states exercising the ultimate power and authority on a certain territory and over certain people, and the fact that sovereign states live in a society that recognizes no superior authority than their very own sovereignty, leading thereby to the horizontality of the relationship between equals. Sovereignty is inextricably associated with power, and the decentralized nature of international law reflects the decentralization of power. The absence of centralization produces inter-subjective relations (ergo, the deficiency – in principle – of objectiveness),Footnote 8 based on reciprocity and self-help. These are the key features of the Westphalian model,Footnote 9 which, of course, modern international law (also because of human rights, as this paper will argue) has gradually mitigated and tempered. However, these very characteristics, as well as others such as the absence of the Hartial rule of recognition,Footnote 10 which for reasons of brevity cannot be mentioned here, remain central to international law, forming the basis that founds its system. Thus, in a sense they are “constitutional”.
If by constitutionalization we mean the existence of certain structural features of the legal order, then international law has always had a “constitution”. This constitution is informal (which is yet another reason explaining why the term is only used metaphorically) in its nature and delineates the structure (but also the confines) of its legal order. Yet, the term constitutionalization refers to something emerging;Footnote 11 rather than pointing to the aforementioned well known, and very old “constitutional” attributes of international law, it aspires to trace the signs of a dynamic transformative process marked by the emergence of a renewed constitutional “edifice”. However, to effectively debate the forces and nature of any transformation observed in the international legal system, we ought not to lose sight or underrate the foundational “constitutional” features of the international system. For the metaphor to be valid, in lieu of “constitutionalization”, the word should be that of a “constitutional reform” –and such a reform cannot be but equally informal, as the “constitution” of international law is, and has always been. Human rights are part of that “reform” and associated with changes affecting the general systemic features of international law.
Second, thus far, scholarship (admittedly, particularly European and North American scholarship) has largely referred to constitutionalization in the context of explaining why and how international law is developing what authors see as elements of a constitution. Next to that basic strand, one could add scholarly work studying how international law (and especially human rights) affects national constitutions.Footnote 12 We would like to add to that literature by framing some of its core contributions within debates on the constitutionalization of international law, but also by adding a third strand of debate concerning the impact national constitutions and their human rights provisions have or have had on the systemic premises and basic features of international law. Therefore, our intervention is unavoidably also doctrinal in nature (especially Section 4 of the study), even if we are informed by theoretical insights.
Thus, in this article, we take a step back in the debate(s) on the constitutionalization of international law by identifying the origins of that transformative (and circular,Footnote 13 in essence) process. Our core contention is that the internationalization of human rights law – to the extent that it is reflected in positive international law and is not simply a moral aspirationFootnote 14– has led to the development of certain significant features that were initially either anaemic, or even entirely absent from “classic” international law. These new features that the order of international law has acquired through the internationalization of human rights – and this is what makes them in a sense constitutional – amount now to structural elements of the international system that apply well beyond human rights as a specialized field of international law. Had they been exclusive to human rights, they would only be characteristics of self-contained-ness, and not essential, organizational, underlying constituents of the system of international law as such.
This is besides what makes the theory of the humanization of international law contiguous to that of constitutionalization. The shift in the protection of human rights from the national to the international level made it necessary for certain new systemic features to be developed in the order of international law. That is, for international law to effectively accommodate human rights protection, across the many different strands and implementing organs of this diverse body of international law,Footnote 15 it had to change. These changes can be seen as a sign of a type of humanization that – unlike other special questionsFootnote 16 or subject-matters on which human rights were understood as having an impact – affects the systemic premises of the international order. For those who endorse the constitutionalization metaphor, these are “constitutional” features. This is what justifies the paper's main argument, namely, that the internationalization of national constitutions has led to the “constitutionalization” of international law. Naturally, human rights law is not necessarily the only feature of domestic constitutionalism that has had an impact on international law. One could argue, for instance, that separation of powers issues in domestic constitutions have had an influence on international law, as part of the literature on the constitutionalization of international law suggests. Another example is the endless debate about the democratization of international law.Footnote 17 But, for the purposes of this article, we focus on the influence of human rights, even if it is not a feature of all constitutions in the world.Footnote 18
As mentioned above, Section 2 of this article critically evaluates the main tenet of the theory of constitutionalization and its principal assertion that international law develops a constitution. Section 3 discusses the links between human rights and the constitutionalization of international law. Although human rights are not exclusive to that particular account of the international legal order (i.e., the constitutionalization), they are central to it, and they fit easily within the constitutional narrative, and in many ways advance it. Section 4 discusses the internationalization of human rights and how that regime of international law has contributed to the change of the international order, in that its system had to develop certain systemic tools to allow human rights to develop their full effet utile, and facilitate effectiveness through collective enforcement. In that respect, the article identifies three main changes: i.e., collective enforcement at the decentralized level for the protection of common interests and/or values; ii. sui generis normative hierarchy beyond jus cogens; and iii. responsibility of states to protect (linked with the principle of due diligence and the so-called positive effect that human rights develop). It goes without saying that the “privileged” place human rights occupy as a branch of international law within its system and the idea of their specialty (which, besides, is linked to all three changes) cannot be dissociated from the values found in their very existential core or, to use a more technical term, the material sources that nourish them. Section 5 concludes our analysis.
2. Critiquing the constitutionalization of international law
Is international law developing a constitution? This is the principal question at the heart of the scholarly debate on the constitutionalization of international law. There are two main critical comments that can be made in that respect.
Before that, a competence “disclaimer” is due. Constitutionalization is more of a constitutional law question, and less of an international law one. Therefore, the debate on the constitutionalization of international law needs to be firmly situated within the context of domestic constitutionalism.Footnote 19 This is a precondition for a systematic analysis of what in essence remains (from a methodological point of view) an interesting hypothesis or research question. For, this is what the constitutionalization of international law is, beyond a mindset:Footnote 20 a research question that seems to be of little consequence in practice. We all know that raising a hypothesis or asking a question is the basis for building a thesis. Yet, what we, international law lawyers, are missing is the tools that will enable us to actually try and answer that question, and validate or reject the hypothesis. What is a constitution? What is constitutionalism? Is there a constituent powerFootnote 21 in the decentralized structure of international law – other maybe than all states together (the idea of the international community) and nobody in particular? Can there be a constitution without a constituent power or demos? How is a constitution found in such a system? And what, after all, allows using the language of constitutional law for the international society, which is by no means akin to a polity? What would the function of a constitution be in the context of the international order and its society? Is there an added value in the use of the constitutional lens? In practical terms, what would/will it change if international law had/has a constitution? Would that make it more legitimateFootnote 22 or effective?
Moving then to the first critical comment, to duly frame the question on the constitutionalization of international law, we need to build a common understanding of what a constitution and constitutionalism are. The absence of such a consensus might explain why the language used lacks unity as to whether that constitutionalism is internationalFootnote 23 or transnational,Footnote 24 globalFootnote 25 or pluralistic.Footnote 26 It might also explain why De Wet,Footnote 27 for instance, emphasizes normative hierarchy (which, as we argue in Section 4, is a point to which, under certain conditions, we agree) as a consequence of human rights, whereas FassbenderFootnote 28 situates the constitutionalization of international law in the framework and organizational structure of international organizations,Footnote 29 especially of the UN, the Charter of which is seen an a exhibition of constitutionalism. It might further explain why Dunoff and TrachtmanFootnote 30 approach the question from a purposive, functionalist perspective that focuses on the function of the constitutional rules – leaving much to be complemented by practice, that would prove that, indeed, there is a commitment in the international community to lift those rules to the constitutional level. Be they thought-provoking and pointing to elements of international law of gravity, these approaches fail to establish common ground as to what are the essential constitutional elements of international law; in some instances, they mix positive law with normative aspirationsFootnote 31 (that is, the lex lata with the lex ferenda), but also, and most importantly, they miss the fundamental question of what makes these elements constitutional in nature – beyond what could be described as (an admittedly inflated) analogy or metaphor.Footnote 32
The second objection has to do with disagreements regarding the impact and effect of those elements in terms of positive international law. An example is the idea of the verticalization of international law, through the establishment of normative hierarchies (linked to human rights), defended by many authors and (as already mentioned) explicitly perceived as an attribute of constitutionalism by De Wet,Footnote 33 as opposed to the non-hierarchical, pluralistic vision of the international legal system defended, for instance, by Krisch.Footnote 34 This disagreement is more than two different accounts of constitutionalization or a simple divergence in the way the two scholars perceive international law. Moreover, what these two opposing interpretations reveal goes beyond a merely different understanding of the ambit of human rights (i.e., pluralist v. universalist). Indeed, we may wonder if behind such a discrepancy over what is allegedly the same phenomenon, i.e., the constitutionalization of international law, certain (ideological) preferences are hidden, translated in selection bias regarding what the constitutional elements of international law are, but also how these ought to be conceived and interpreted.Footnote 35 But it may also be that there is no truly empirically observable constitutionalization process, and that concept owes its very existence to scholar creativity, that is, to our “collective imaginary” that has constructed a notion using the language of constitutional law that needs now to be given legal content at the international level.Footnote 36 Of course, the absence of a clear-cut distinction between positive law and normative aspirationsFootnote 37 (a problem which is inherent to international law and its lack of centralization) adds complexity by giving scholars wider discretion as to what they can exclude or include in their own narrative of constitutionalization.
Thus, one cannot but agree with Kennedy, who perceives constitutionalization as yet another “project” next to other ones (one may think for instance of global administrative law, third world approaches, the process school, or even ‘New World Order’ and the global norms it identifiesFootnote 38 – aspiring to provide ‘new thinking about how the global order coheres’).Footnote 39 We wonder however if in the case of constitutionalization, rather than a common “tale”, there are disparate perceptions of it. It seems that international law is undergoing several constitutionalization processes at once, with the term acting as an all-encompassing “umbrella” with multiple meanings, and perceptions allowing it to host wide-ranging narratives. The common theme is that international law is changing with regards to its foundational rules, with globalization turning sovereignty thinner and these changes making its system more constitutionalized – whatever this may mean to each one of us.
3. Linking human rights to grand narratives of the international legal order
Having finished with this brief, critical account of the constitutionalization narrative(s), and declared our lack of competence as international law lawyers to confirm or reject it/them and, consequently, our critical “agnosticism” vis-à-vis it/them, we now move to the next step in our analysis, which aims at demonstrating that human rights are part of said narrative(s). The field of human rights is always in the background of several grand narratives of international law, but hardly ever at the foreground. We bring international human rights law to the foreground and take on claims about the role human rights play in particular in three grand “projects” of the international legal order, namely fragmentation,Footnote 40 international legal pluralismFootnote 41 and, of course, constitutionalization.Footnote 42 Admittedly, human rights are assigned a role and occupy a privileged place within other narratives of international law as well. However, space contraints require that our brief discussion be limited to only those narratives that are comparable with and can be directly juxtaposed to constitutionalization. Our focus is the latter in an effort to highlight its links with human rights. Particularly, we wish to advance the claim that human rights law is an integral part to a constitutionalized reading of the international legal order, and in many respects serves to advance it.
The named three projects are comparable in that fragmentation and pluralism work as two sides of the same coin (fragmentation seen from “above” is pluralism seen from “below”),Footnote 43 and both can work as a counter-narrative to constitutionalization (challenging its centralizing nature). But then pluralism can also be seen as constitutionalizing, at least as far as judicialized international law is concerned, in the sense that it contributes to more cross-fertilization, dialogue and cooperation between courts and their converging towards a central normative focal point.Footnote 44
Scholars working on the grand narratives of international law seem to assume that human rights played a somewhat marginal role in projects of the international legal order, or, even when some more central role was given to human rights, it was never fully fleshed out. To articulate this assumption, it is necessary to first try to place human rights discourse in current narratives of the international legal order, and address what seems to be one of the biggest factors behind what can be described as a certain reluctance towards human rights in many of these projects, namely, the claim of human rights’ role in the hegemonic tendencies of international law, at least inasmuch as it advances an Euro-centric perspective on the values behind human rights law and law-making. Scholars aligned with the constitutionalization projectFootnote 45 tend to look at human rights as indeed a very central part of their normative aspirations, particularly by looking at the reception and entrenchment of human rights in domestic legal orders and at the ways through which judicial and other institutions assert and protect human rights.Footnote 46 In this sense, human rights law operates both as the cultural context (or the “entrenched” law necessary to the constitutionalist project) and as the background against which the entire project is built. Human rights is one of the ingredients of the constitutionalization narrative.Footnote 47 The constitutionalist project also usually assumes some sort of charter of rights is a part of their project (even if scholars aligned with this project often fail to explore the content of any such charter)Footnote 48 and suggests that international human rights law has the potential to become the “Grundnorm” of the international legal order.Footnote 49 The reliance of this project on institutions is somewhat limited, as proposed by Kumm, whose idea of “cosmopolitan constitutionalism” is less dependent on institutionalism, while still relying on human rights as a fundamental normative aspiration of a constitutionalized international legal order.Footnote 50
The fragmentation project, at least to the extent it is perceived as a counter-narrative to the constitutionalization project, is very critical of institutionalization, particularly with respect to human rights. For some, the ‘inchoate institutional character’ of international law is one of the greatest obstacles to a unified international legal order.Footnote 51 In a way, fragmentation tends to stick to a deceptively descriptive account of international law as a means to avoid committing to any sort of normative project. The problem is that this position in itself is normative.Footnote 52 Fragmentation, by being this empty shell, easily becomes prey to the status quo, only under new guise, through mechanisms like “strategic fragmentation”, but also others.Footnote 53
Fragmentation, by being non-committal on the surface, tends to skirt accusations of participating in what Koskenniemi, referring to international human rights law, calls a hegemonic strategy of international law.Footnote 54 According to him, international human rights law is an essential part of the hegemonic strategy to the extent human rights is an ideology and political project.Footnote 55 The solution to the hegemonic strategy of international law seems to be, according to Koskenniemi, a return to formalism.Footnote 56 This call to formalism finds followers also among scholars in the constitutionalization project, particularly Peters.Footnote 57 This return to formalism seems to be the principal claim of the fragmentation narrative, particularly with respect to international human rights law. Of course, the main problem with it is that formalism does not avoid political commitments. It simply reinforces the status quo.
There are two ways to look at the relationship between international human rights law and the fragmentation of international law. From an internal perspective, the question is how different human rights bodies relate to one another, and how their different instruments are interpreted, especially in light of very similar (or identical) factual situations.Footnote 58 From an external perspective, the key question is how international human rights law relates to other bodies of international law.Footnote 59 The former perspective (or a version of it) is the most relevant for our current purposes (because we are trying to understand how human rights law operates endemically, even if on a domestic/international interplay), but a few words might be needed with respect to the latter.
Regional human rights courts have used “foreign” (that is, non-human rights) instruments extensively in expanding the scope and reach of rights protected under their constitutive instruments.Footnote 60 The reason why foreign instruments have only been applied “indirectly” is because the Inter-American and European human rights courts have only the competence to declare violations of the American and European Conventions, respectively. Thus, because of their constitutive constraints, they are forced to “translate” all legal issues before them into human rights issues. This translation effort has two main effects: on the one hand, it promotes some sort of unity, by bringing all of international law under the human rights umbrella, which means to say that international legal norms are considered in light of their impact upon human lives (which is, arguably, the reason why law exists in the first place – to have an impact upon human lives). This unity further enhances the legitimacy of international human rights law. On the other hand, by bringing everything under the human rights umbrella, human rights courts create an informal or de facto hierarchy of international legal rules, putting human rights norms at the top of the pyramid. International human rights law affects the “systemic premises” of other areas of international law through this interaction,Footnote 61 with one consequence being a possibility for hierarchization. This consequence is, again, mandated by the constitutional constraints of these courts, and their popularity makes this hierarchization seem all the more pervasive, and it easily becomes part of the hegemonic project Koskenniemi is so critical of.
Finally, international legal pluralism lies somewhere in between the constitutionalization and fragmentation narratives (while challenging both) and echoes the constitutional pluralism debate in the European Union.Footnote 62 It ‘provides a normative vision of restructuring plural orders into pluralist ones – that is, re-envisaging them from fragmented, closed, sovereign legal orders into an open, interacting, interlinked, interdependent, multi-level structure of legal ordering.’Footnote 63 However, it does not have the unification agenda and accepts a fragmented plurality of legal orders out of which none necessarily prevails.
The main perceived power of international legal pluralism is precisely to offer a counterpoint to the constitutionalist narrative, and a response to the dangers of constitutionalism, and also fragmentation: it is something of a positive spin on fragmentation focusing on the potential of a diverging legal order, as opposed to its apparent chaos. While fragmentation undermines international law, pluralism strengthens it,Footnote 64 even if what looks like fragmentation seen from above can easily look like pluralism seen from below.
International legal pluralism generally lacks an overarching hierarchical structure, favoring the openness of different legal systems. Unlike constitutionalism's search for Grundnorm(s), pluralism accepts the notion that there is no such common point of reference.Footnote 65 Pluralism can be either systemic or institutional, with the latter dealing with institutional viewpoints, whereas the former addresses more substantive issues across plural fora.Footnote 66 In a way, it is a mirror image of institutional and systemic fragmentation.
The pluralist narrative seems to be the most apt to enable international human rights law and values to form an integral part of a project about the international legal order, alongside Kumm's ‘cosmopolitan constitutionalism’.Footnote 67 But human rights courts seem to be more focused on the constitutional narrative, because that narrative privileges adjudicators, at least to the extent it mirrors domestic constitutional systems, which are anchored on judicial systems for their functioning. Additionally, how does the promise of pluralism (or cosmopolitan constitutionalism) react in light of the phenomenon of fragmentation of international law, which puts in evidence the difficulty of consistent interpretations of international legal norms across different fora? The (quasi-)adjudicatory practice of human rights bodies can contribute or become a hurdle to narratives of the international legal order.
The specificity of human rights law, which is (to give an example) connected to the way it is interpreted (evolutive or pro homine interpretation, as opposed to ordinary meaning),Footnote 68 challenges the capacity of international human rights law being fully a part of general international law, seen as it chooses to play by its own rules. This idiosyncrasy is created by, and reinforces, the expertization and specialty of international human rights law,Footnote 69 which is an important element in the fragmentation of all areas of international law. At the same time, though, the endemic practice of human rights institutions, and particularly of human rights courts, is to see themselves as playing a part in a constitutionalist project of international law, especially as they can often be perceived as engaging directly with domestic courts (even if they will reject the notion of being a “court of fourth instance”).Footnote 70
4. The specialty of human rights: the impact of the internationalization of national constitutions on the system of international law
Having argued that human rights are interlinked with the constitutionalization of international law, the paper now turns to its main assertion, namely that the internationalization of human rights protection has helped the international legal order to develop certain systemic, “constitutional” features that mitigate the rigidity of the Westphalian structure.
In its general lines, the legal history of human rights in the West and its landmarks, the Magna Carta, the English Bill of Rights and the American and French revolutions in the era of Enlightenment, are well known. Gradually, human rights attained the form and strength of constitutional rights aiming to limit public power, but also to invite public authorities to develop policies to guarantee and enhance the well-being of the persons under their jurisdiction. That these bills of rights were included in the “basic” (to borrow the German term) law of a polity reflects their importance for the society and the idea that they are part and parcel of its constitutive/constitutional legal act and the social contract underlying it. Thus, apart from organizing power, the polity and the functioning of its institutions, national constitutions were also employed as a means to subject the acts and omissions of the polity's organs (governmental, but also beyond the executive) to the societal values that shape its public order, impose limits and preclude conducts that cannot be tolerated within it. This is a rough sketch of the national constitutional model in the West, we concede, but it should suffice for our present purposes.
The Second World War, its atrocities – and especially Shoah – came to prove in a tragic way the dramatic inadequacy of that model. Before the era of internationalization, flagrant human right breaches principally constituted a matter of municipal law, falling within (what nowadays seems to be) a sort of overstated domaine réservé. Protecting human rights at the national level alone had proven to be ineffective – especially where democratic roots were weak – allowing states to hide behind the veil of sovereignty and the prohibition of the interference with domestic affairs. Yet, to paraphrase Clemenceau, human rights are too important a matter to be left to national constitutions.
Human rights need to be effective. Their internationalizationFootnote 71 came just to address that very social necessity. However, that process required more than simply “copying-and-pasting” the rights one could commonly find in national constitutions. An area of law originally and in principle related to the relationship of the individual/citizen with public power had to be transplanted within a system originally and in principle regulating inter-state relationships. Thus, for constitutional human rights to be converted into international human rights, they had to be not only posited by the means of the sources of international law (such as treaties or custom), but also adapted to its systemic features. Their teleology and overall function have both remained unchanged. But, they now produce their effect within an entirely different context, society and legal framework. Consequently, the mindset changes too. This time, the scheme is rather oblique. States “promise” one another that they shall safeguard the rights of the human person. Thereby, they recognize the right of other states to lawfully react to violations – in principle – occurring within their national legal sphere. Hence, sovereignty becomes thinner, more transparent and states acquire a droit de regard, that is, the right to monitor human rights performance inside other states. The human being is still the primary beneficiary of the obligations at issue, but these are owed by the state to other states and also to the human being itself. The latter aspect is closely linked to the self-executing nature of human rights treaties,Footnote 72 allowing them to be invoked by the individual before domestic courts, as well as to the fact that certain instruments provide for control and establish international institutions – such as the UN Human Rights Committee, or the Inter-American Commission and Court – endowed with the competence to receive individual petitions for human right breaches.
However, the admittance of the human being as a recipient of rights directly at the international level could not leave the legal system unaffected. The study gives the example of three main changes in the systemic premises of international law, which partially owe to human rights as well. The first two stem from the erga omnes (partes) quality of human rights rules,Footnote 73 whereas the third is linked to the principle of due diligence. The point made here is that the influence of human rights on the system of international law goes well beyond the obvious fact that the individual came to be added to the list with the subjects of international law,Footnote 74 expanding thereby its span, and also bringing to an end the exclusiveness of states, which however remain the primary subjects of the system.Footnote 75 These changes discussed below are of systemic, i.e. in a sense “constitutional” proportions.
4.1. Collective enforcement at the decentralized level for the protection of common interests and values
The main such influence of human rights is that their protection bestowed international law with rules that reflect values and aim to safeguard interests that are not exclusive to each state individually, but to all of them collectively. This has rendered necessary that they are also protected collectively. Definitely, this is not the only area of international law with this characteristic. The same applies in the case of environmental protection, for instance, or in the protection of cultural heritage.Footnote 76 However, this is not a trivial development. Human rights prepared the soil for the emergence of what could be seen as an international public order for the protection of common interests/values – and this also explains why human rights are associated with the constitutionalization of international law.
For international law to effectively accommodate human rights, it was inevitable that its system would change too. This involved developing certain features and tools that were not necessary to it when its operation was confined to merely reciprocal obligations destined to safeguard under the logic of self-help individual state interests – that is, in the framework of the jus inter gentes, marked by the idea of absolute state sovereignty. As already explained, the ambit of the change brought by human rights in that respect is a rather controversial issue among scholars – and we tend to think that the humanization theory is indeed inflated.Footnote 77 Yet, it is incontestable that human rights are entwined with the concepts of jus cogens and obligations erga omnes.Footnote 78
Erga omnes (which, besides, encompass jus cogens in the sense that all peremptory norms have an erga omnes (partes) effect) were first confirmed as part of international law by the ICJ in its famous obiter dictum in Barcelona Traction.Footnote 79 That class of rules has found its place in the ILC norms on state responsibility, which recognize the ability of non-(directly) injured states to invoke the responsibility of the state breaking an obligation it owes erga omnes.Footnote 80 Practically speaking, any state may invoke the responsibility and react (possibly by countermeasures as well)Footnote 81 to the wrongful contact of a state breaking an obligation it owes erga omnes. This has found numerous applications in international law,Footnote 82 one of which is the idea of inter-state applications for human right breaches before international fora, such as the ECtHR.Footnote 83 As far as the reason why obligations erga omnes, such as human rights, are owed towards all (as the term literally suggests), this is so because they refer to issues that concern everyone in the society, i.e., they reflect shared interests/values. If an obligation is owed towards all other states, in the case of general international law, or all other states-parties, in the case of a treaty law, then it flows naturally that all those states be allowed to react to wrongfulness.
Seen from a strictly legal viewpoint, human rights are special because they are owed erga omnes. Yet, the reason why they are owed erga omnes is because they are materially special, that is, because they reflect common values and collective interests that are considered to be important and, therefore, worthy enough to benefit from collective enforcement. When a given right of the individual is recognizedFootnote 84 as a human right, it is automatically acknowledged as having a special erga omnes normative effect. This allows maximizing its effectiveness and fostering its enforcement, which, given the absence in principle of centralized authorities in international law, will continue to operate at the decentralized level, albeit (ideally) in more a communitarian,Footnote 85 or collective, manner. Thus, the entrance of an area of law like human rights in international law has generated changes within its system by rendering necessary the development of new mechanisms, such as obligations erga omnes, that enable the collective enforcement and protection of ‘legitimate community interests’.Footnote 86 In the absence of a centralized public authority similar to the one that exists within states, the decentralized system of international law invites (but does not oblige) each and every state in the world to partake in the collective enforcement of the values shaping the international public order.
However, outside the framework of international organizations (which may have the power to sanction human right breaches within an institutional, hence partially centralized, structure), collective enforcement of erga omnes rules continues to operate under the same decentralized logic that underpins the international legal system. It is not reciprocity stricto sensu that applies.Footnote 87 Rather, it is a renewed, broader concept of mutuality that enlarges the circle of concerned/affected states, and allows them as non-directly injured parties to react to wrongfulness, that is to partake in the collective enforcement of common values, through lawful means of action.Footnote 88 The broader framework and its logic (i.e., the decentralized structure of the system) remain in essence unchanged. Yet, within that framework, reasonable adjustments are made so that the community of states is allowed to collectively enforce the rules that are special to it.
4.2. Normative hierarchy beyond jus cogens
Moreover, for human rights to effectively operate at the decentralized international level – and, thereby, cause (constitutional?) changes within its system as well – it is not only the mode of enforcement that needed to be adapted. Unlike national constitutions that traditionally benefit from formal normative supremacy, international human rights do not enjoy the same favoured treatment within the order of international law. This is because the logic of formal hierarchy – i.e., supremacy owed to the formal “box” that contains the rule, that is, the source that has generated it – is foreign to international law,Footnote 89 where all sources are equal. Yet, what is not foreign to international law is the idea of substantive hierarchy, thanks also to human rights and particularly the role of human rights bodies, as discussed above. It is common knowledge that, should a rule be recognized as jus cogens, its effect cannot be limited, no exceptions or derogations are allowed, whereas conflictingFootnote 90 rules shall suffer nullity. It is not the form of the rule that counts, but its content, which is seen by the society as imperative, absolute and therefore not susceptible to limitations, but also powerful enough to restrict the individual will of the sovereign state.
Admittedly, erga omnes (partes) do not share the same privileged status as jus cogens. Yet, be they part of jus dispositivum, they differ from “everyday” international law rules which are based on the logic of reciprocal (“contractual”, quid pro quo or du ut des) obligations in that they are integral,Footnote 91 but also in that – to our understanding – they are in general more “weighty” than bilateral(-izable) obligations. The ILC has rejected the idea of the primacy of erga omnes obligations,Footnote 92 but part of the literature disagrees with that narrow approach,Footnote 93 the main arguments in that respect being the material value of human rights, the aforementioned non-reciprocal nature of erga omnes obligations, and that it is logically not possible for states to mutually agree to depart from an obligation they owe erga omnes, i.e., towards a broader circle of states.
Yet, a different argument could be made as well. Erga omnes could be seen as developing a special type of ad hoc, occasional “hierarchy”.Footnote 94 Although erga omnes (contrasting to jus cogens) can be limited, because of their material importance they tend to overweigh conflicting obligations and their teleology and are given priority in their fulfilment. Whereas only remarkably few human rights qualify as jus cogens,Footnote 95 they all fall in the broader, more “modest” and susceptible to limitations class of erga omnes. When these are juxtaposed to and balanced (by the means of proportionality) against other rules, usually (taking into account, among other factors, the particular circumstances of each case) priority is recognized to them. Of course, this is due to the material values that underpin human rights and the importance they have for the society.Footnote 96 As a result, conflicting rules can only produce effects to the extent that they do not disproportionately infringe human rights. Yet, this is solely the outcome of a balancing act, which, as such, operates (in exactly the same way as it does in the national legal systems as well) on a strictly occasional, that is, an ad hoc basis, depending on the facts that are particular to each individual case. This is why the priority in the fulfilment suggested here cannot be but occasional and subjected to the strict exigencies of a balancing act. What allows obligations erga omnes to benefit from priority in such a balancing act is their material value. Proportionality, as the exemplary form of balancing, and especially its stricto sensu dimension,Footnote 97 allows value judgments. Outside evaluating the necessity of the deployment of certain means that may be harmful to a right, but essential for a given purpose (be it a specific right protected by law, or public/general interest), balancing allows juxtaposing the teleology of the former rule and that of the latter interest/rule. Their teleology, i.e., their purpose, is inextricably linked to the value they have for the society. Thus, next to the mechanic dimension of balancing (test of appropriateness/necessity of means), there is another intrinsic one that invites us to evaluate, rank and prioritize values, which, in a given context, end up conflicting. To give a very simple example, if in order to save human life it is indispensable for a state to break its obligations under a bilateral-izable international treaty (for instance, the obligation not to enter the premises of a foreign embassy), priority shall be given to the right to life. This will not exonerate the responsibility of the state – unless if the conduct at issue is seen as a justified lawful limitation of the obligations stemming from the international treaty at issue, in which case there is no wrongfulness. Yet, the fact remains that priority will be given to the erga omnes obligations, and this owes to the importance of the values it aims at protecting.
It is definitely a sloping solution, which is however inherent to the value of human rights (that also explains their constitutional origins), the way these are called to unravel their effet utile in a system of law that was designed to be, and which essentially remains, formally horizontal, decentralized, state-centric, sovereignist and, therefore, largely also voluntarist. However, the quintessence of public order is to restrict, one way or another, individual will. This is the “constitutional” function of human rights, the sui generis way they develop their effect and unfold their material scope within a sui generis system, like the international one. It may not be full, formal supremacy, but international law has the means to grant human rights, and more generally obligations erga omnes (partes) the prominence they deserve.
4.3. Due diligence and the responsibility of states to protect
Moving to the third and last area discussed in this paper where the internationalization of human rights may be associated with signs of systemic change in positive international law, this corresponds to the positive effect of human rights,Footnote 98 and more generally to the idea of their protectionFootnote 99 (as opposed to the strands of respect and fulfilment), that are linked to the well-known principle of due diligence.Footnote 100 Undeniably, this is an old principle of international law that applies in many areas that go well beyond human rights. Discussing in full detail due diligence and its ramifications (especially with regard to state fault and the law of international responsibility)Footnote 101 exceeds the scope of the paper. Suffice it here to highlight the links with human rights, and their constitutional protection at the national level.
National constitutional provisions on human rights were originally conceived as merely vertical, with a view to restrict the exercise of public power and shield the individual-subject of the State-Leviathan (with a capital “s”) from its arbitrariness. This corresponds to the so-called negative dimension of (traditionally, civil and political) human rights, prohibiting state organs from directly causing wrongful results. The evolution of human rights protection at the national level has led to the expansion of their scope by adding a positive axis, next to the negative one. The positive dimension of human rights reflects the idea of a state that, far from abstaining or being neutral, has a legal obligation to be pro-active in the protection of rights (through prevention, punishment etc.) by employing means available to it.Footnote 102 This applies beyond the horizontal effect of human rights, but it is that dimension that was mainly developed at the national level, through the theory of Drittwirkung that requires the state to protect people under its jurisdiction from the wrongful conduct not only of its own organs (directly caused by the state, hence directly attributable to it),Footnote 103 but of other individuals as well (even if indirectly). The horizontal effect of human rights was adopted by international human rights fora, that placed it in the broader framework of protection, which in international law is linked to the principle of due diligence. Thus, that old principle of international law found ample application within the regime of international human rights law, which has promoted due diligence and put it again emphatically on the map of international law, (plausibly) contributing to its use in other areas of law.Footnote 104
Last but not least, the broader impact due diligence (in the context of human rights) may have on international law is evidenced in the (still immature in terms of positive international law) doctrine of Responsibility to Protect (R2P),Footnote 105 inviting states first – and, in case of failure, the international community – to protect people under their jurisdiction from heinous crimes such as genocide or ethnic cleansing.Footnote 106 One could argue that the rationale behind R2P is identical to that of protection under due diligence.Footnote 107 Thus, to the extent that these two concepts coincide (i.e., lawful measures adopted by a state in light of its obligation to demonstrate diligence that serve the purposes of R2P) the latter doctrine may be seen as acquiring a compulsory, hard law dimension as well. Yet, the most important similarity between the two concepts for our purposes is that, now, sovereignty is not only seen as a right, but also as responsibilityFootnote 108 to protect through pro-active, diligent conduct. This is yet another sign of erosion, or transformation of sovereignty,Footnote 109 which is one of the systemic, foundational, that is, “constitutional” cornerstones of international law.
5. Conclusion
However inflated, the humanization narrative offers a useful lens to comprehend the impact human rights have on the systemic premises of international law. Because of their material “specialty”, their transfer from the national to the international order could not leave the system of international law unaffected. Hence, international law has developed within the confines of its decentralized structure special “tools” and features enabling it to accommodate human rights, which, likewise, had to adapt to the idiosyncrasy of a structure that has been modelled in different terms and under a different logic than the vertical and centralized one that characterizes the domestic level. The constitutionalized version of international human rights law seems to be favoured by the practice of international human rights institutions, and thereby aligns with a narrative of human rights as standing in the dialogue between the domestic and the international.
These emerging features, such as the introduction of a more vertical tone, the reconceptualization of sovereignty as a prerogative that comes with obligations and responsibilities, and the entitlement of states to be actively engaged in the protection of what they deem important, are linked to and indeed descend from the concepts of obligations erga omnes and due diligence. Even if due diligenceFootnote 110 – as well as possibly jus cogens Footnote 111 – predate the internationalization era of human rights, it is through that regime of international law that they acquired solid flesh and bones. Thus, even if human rights did not create the concepts, they borrowed them from general international law and fed them back to the general international law, in much stronger form. Besides, that they are not exclusive to human rights, that is, that they extend in a number of other areas and regimes of international law, makes them “systemic” elements of modern international law. International law has thus restructured its constitutional features, and that restructuring owes a lot to the internationalization of national constitutional provisions on human rights. Our anticipation is that this is an ongoing process that has more to bring. Its potential for further evolution may be evidenced in the emergence, for instance, of obligations for individuals (with soft law on corporationsFootnote 112 being the most notorious example in that respect), or the development of individual criminal responsibility.
Yet, there is another, broader, potential as well. The recalibration of the system of international law that this paper attempted to portray in its general lines means that, apart from readjusting its physiognomy by developing certain features that made possible the accommodation of human rights, international law is now equipped with what is necessary for it to lodge, under similar terms, other less established or developed areas of law as well – as long as these present similarities to human rights, mainly in that they aim at safeguarding collective interests/values. In other words, the “constitutional” change brought in international law by human rights has prepared that order to effectively accommodate further areas of national (constitutional) law aiming to safeguard values that societies rank as important. In a nutshell, while remaining decentralized and sovereignty-basedFootnote 113 the international legal system is now prepared to host public order rules. The framework has been updated. What remains is to give it substance. The more the public order dimension will flourish and become tangible, the more the reconceptualization of sovereignty and the decline of the old, Westphalian model will be discernible, and the international society of states will be transformed into a more homogeneous as to its core values and their collective protection community.Footnote 114