Serialism is a virtually ubiquitous phenomenon in studies of twentieth-century music. Readers and writers alike will almost certainly understand the context in which the term is used in individual instances, but those contexts differ widely. The linguistic contrast between the nouns ‘series’ and ‘serialism’ may partially account for the vast array of contexts in which serialism is used: ‘series’ refers concretely to a succession of objects in a fixed order, while the suffix ‘-ism’ in ‘serialism’ refers more abstractly to a belief in a particular practice, system, or philosophy. Within its various contexts, three broad understandings of serialism can be discerned, distinctions which, too, exhibit significant linguistic contrasts. First, serialism may refer to ordered successions of objects, including twelve-tone rows, in which case the context may be described as twelve-tone serialism or, sometimes, simply dodecaphony. Second, serialism may refer to the expansion and diversity of compositional approaches and aesthetics based on a series, which may or may not contain twelve elements. On occasion, this version of serialism might be viewed not as a continuation of twelve-tone serialism, but as a sort of opposition to dodecaphony. Third, serialism may refer to a way of thinking, ‘state of mind’ (Dallapiccola, quoted in Reference AlegantAlegant 2010: 9), philosophy, or even ideology that reveres rigour, order, and unity as compositional principles while disconnecting them from musical style or method.
Such wide-ranging, verging on contradictory, understandings of serialism shape this exploration of theorising serialism, incorporating the notion of a row or series and fixed ordering of elements, expansion of musical parameters for fixed ordering, and the extension of the serial concept into the realm of sound generation and timbre. In my view, the absence of a singular definition should be regarded positively, adding nuance to any theorisation of serialism.
Part I: Before 1945
The Serial Concept
The serial concept in musical composition originated as an organisational framework based on the principle of fixed ordering of elements. Arnold Schoenberg articulated a ‘method for composing with twelve tones which are related only with one another’ in a 1941 lecture given at the University of California at Los Angeles (Reference Schoenberg and SteinSchoenberg 1975a), which in turn was based on notes prepared in 1934 for a lecture at Princeton University known as the ‘Vortrag über Komposition mit 12 Tönen’. The published essay came to be regarded as the definitive authorial statement on Schoenberg’s twelve-tone technique, but as noted by Claudio Spies and others, the 1934 version of the material is more theoretically focused and precise, addressing compositional technique directly and dispensing with spiritual and other extra-musical elements included in the 1941 version (Reference SpiesSpies 1974; cf. Reference CovachCovach 2017; Reference HydeHyde 1982).
Fixed ordering of pitch classes acquired a privileged position in Schoenberg’s compositional practice beginning in 1921. David Lewin described Schoenberg’s twelve-tone practice as integrating the serial concept with permutations of the aggregate (Reference LewinLewin 1968: 1), which is to say, related ways of ordering a particular twelve-tone series (its prime form), stereotypically by inverting the pitch relationships (inversion), or reversing their order (retrograde), or both (retrograde inversion), and by beginning any such permutation on a different opening pitch class. Uncoupling the serial concept from permutations of the aggregate is pivotal to any understanding of the concept itself.
Schoenberg described the Suite for Piano op. 25 (composed between 1921 and 1923) as his first composition to adopt serial ordering of the twelve pitch classes, but he employed serial pitch-class ordering prior to op. 25 using series of different lengths in the Five Pieces for Piano op. 23 and in the Serenade op. 24. Fixed ordering of elements in Schoenberg’s early serial practice reflected compositional choices about the identity, number, and realisation of elements within an underlying theoretical framework. The series forms that appear in Schoenberg’s Suite op. 25 are shown in Table 1.1, with each form analogous to its manifestation in Schoenberg’s row tables from 1921, in which the row forms are displayed rather differently (Figure 1.1). Note in Table 1.1 that the inverted form begins a tritone from the first pitch class of the prime form. The four basic transformations are followed by their tritone transpositions, completing the eight row forms that appear throughout the Suite, with the result that all eight forms begin and end on pitch classes E♮ and B♭.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
The eight row forms shown in Table 1.1 belong to a complex of relations within what were to become known as the classical serial transformations, which are shown idiosyncratically in Schoenberg’s row tables in Figure 1.1, completed in 1921. The layout and labelling of the row tables in Figure 1.1 will appear unconventional a century after their creation in light of more familiar representations of dodecaphonic series and matrices in the scholarly literature, but they are of great value in revealing enduring aspects of Schoenberg’s serial thinking. In addition to the row forms that appear in the Suite, the sketch also includes four brief compositional drafts, explicitly blending theoretical and practical concerns within the single sketch.
Figure 1.1 consists of four quadrants. The upper left quadrant shows the prime (or basic) form and its retrograde, each partitioned into its discrete tetrachords over three staves with a brief compositional draft based on the prime form inserted between the prime and retrograde forms. The prime form is labelled T for Tonika, and the retrograde is labelled TK, where K refers to Krebs. Note that the three tetrachords of T appear, in order, in the top, middle, and bottom staves, while the three tetrachords of TK appear, in order, in the bottom, middle, and top staves. While the division of the complete twelve-element series into its discrete tetrachords on separate staves serves to display simultaneously the whole and significant parts, this arrangement conceals the linear retrograde relations. Such a multidimensional understanding of serialism from the outset became a critical component of Schoenberg’s serial thought. The tetrachordal partitioning also explicitly reveals the homage to Bach, and by extension the genre of the Baroque dance suite, with the BACH motive that appears in its original form in the first tetrachord of the retrograde (TK) form (seen in the bottom staff, upper left quadrant in Figure 1.1).
The other three quadrants are organised in the same fashion. The upper right quadrant shows the inversion of the row (beginning a tritone from the starting pitch of the prime form), labelled TU, where U refers to Umkehrung. The retrograde of the inversion, that is, the retrograde inversion, appears to the right of the inversion, and is labelled TUK. The bottom left and bottom right quadrants in Figure 1.1 show the prime, retrograde, inversion, and retrograde inversion forms all transposed by six semitones, with D for Dominante replacing T in the labels. The characterisation of the prime form as Tonika preserves the familiar principle of a central, referential entity to which others are related, while Schoenberg’s identification of the tritone transposition as Dominante divulges his understanding of the interval of the tritone as a type of equivalency with the most essential tonal relationship, the dominant, perhaps a strategy for mediating the radical nature of the new compositional approach with an explicit appeal to familiar, traditional relationships (cf. Reference PhippsPhipps 1986). In addition to the fundamental role of the tritone in the complex of row forms, the interval of the tritone as the boundary interval between the first and last pitch classes of the row (E♮ and B♭) ensures that each row form begins and ends on these pitch classes.
The striking brief compositional drafts that are interspersed between the prime and retrograde forms and between the inversion and retrograde inversion forms in the row tables (and their tritone transpositions) are noteworthy for their treatment of the discrete tetrachords. Within each compositional draft, the discrete tetrachords are set as a three-note sonority followed by a single pitch in beamed sixteenth notes. The setting of the first tetrachord of the prime form, consisting of the sonority E♮-D♭-F♮ followed by the single pitch G♮, appears to be a draft of the music that occurs in the opening bar of the Intermezzo. The settings of the second and third tetrachords from T in the draft replicate the same rhythmic and textural patterns, as do the settings in the remaining three compositional drafts. The three-note sonorities obfuscate the linear order within each tetrachord; they do not systematically set the first three elements, and the single note following the three-note sonority is never the fourth element. They are consistent in articulating the tetrachordal contents, but inconsistent in articulating their internal distribution. The conspicuous treatment of the row tetrachords – in the tables and in the composition – has led to some debate about whether the Suite should be understood as a hybrid work in which some movements are based on arrangements of tetrachords comparable to the row tables (the Prelude, Gavotte, Musette, Intermezzo, and Menuett), while other movements reflect the linear, fixed twelve-tone ordering (the Trio for the Menuett and the Gigue) (Reference HaimoHaimo 1990: 84–5; Reference HydeHyde 1983: 470–9; Reference BossBoss 2014: 38; Reference WhittallWhittall 2008: 32–5). I would argue that the tetrachordal partitions in the row tables, being derived from a pre-existing construct, support Schoenberg’s early and full understanding of the series as a multidimensional entity. Jack Boss describes Schoenberg’s flexible approach to serial ordering in the Suite and later works as ‘a spectrum of ways of presenting the row that ranged from an unordered aggregate on one end of the spectrum to complete, perfect ordering on the other end’ (Reference BossBoss 2014: 37). By separating compositional practice from abstract, conceptual speculation, this spectrum of possibilities succinctly epitomises the theorisation of the serial principle and foreshadows the greater expansion of the serial concept to come.
The principle of serial ordering of pitch classes represented a radical approach to the treatment of musical materials and a venture into the avant-garde, notwithstanding Schoenberg’s efforts to retain important connections with his musical heritage. The enrichment of the serial concept in the decades following its inception continued to be characterised by radical departure from compositional norms. Schoenberg’s Five Pieces for Piano op. 23 and the Serenade op. 24 are commonly regarded as precursors to Schoenberg’s twelve-tone method because they employ series of fewer than twelve elements in the first four movements of op. 23 (Reference HydeHyde 1985) and greater than twelve elements in the variations movement of op. 24 (Reference LesterLester 1968). Recalling the linguistic shifts and nuances of ‘serialism’, these works are sometimes described as ‘serial’ so as to reserve the descriptor ‘twelve-tone’ specifically for the consistent serial ordering of the twelve pitch classes and the classical permutations of the aggregate (prime, inversion, retrograde, and retrograde inversion). Given the pervasive impact of Schoenberg’s twelve-tone method, this is understandable, but for the purposes of this chapter, the twelve-tone method is regarded as a particular, and particularly significant, manifestation of the serial concept.
The serial concept expressed itself in the expansion of Schoenberg’s treatment of pitch classes into serial treatment of other musical parameters by fixed ordinal schemes and later into more complex, derived, logical processes, reflecting new ways of thinking about musical materials. The radical nature of Schoenberg’s 1921 discovery is inseparable from its iconic position in the history of musical modernism (cf. Reference MooreMoore 1995: 77–8), and similarly, the radical quality of later manifestations of the serial concept is inseparable from the cultural context in which they appeared. Theorising serialism must take cultural, historical, and aesthetic considerations into account.
Messiaen
Like Schoenberg, Olivier Messiaen is strongly identified with musical modernism in the first half of the twentieth century, and, though from a different aesthetic tradition, his teachings and compositions also inspired the development of the serial concept, independent of the permutation of aggregates. Messiaen is known for his idiosyncratic treatment of rhythm, characterised by eschewal of traditional metric and tonal patterns. His interest in non-Western rhythmic patterns (such as the deçi-tâlas collected in the thirteenth century by Śārṅgadeva), including non-retrogradable rhythms, as musical objects and his creation of independent series of pitches and durations unfolding simultaneously further underscore the multidimensional nature of the serial concept.
The first movement of the Quatuor pour la fin du temps (1941), ‘Liturgie du crystal’, scored for piano, cello, clarinet, and violin, offers a clear example of Messiaen’s early serial conception. The cello and piano parts unfold two simultaneous series in each instrument. The cello part, entirely in harmonics, superimposes a repeating short five-element series of pitches (not pitch classes) with a repeating fifteen-element series of durations. Similarly, the piano part superimposes a repeating twenty-nine-element series of chords with a repeating seventeen-element series of durations (cf. Reference TaruskinTaruskin 2005a: 237–8). The two series in the cello part come into synchronisation after every three statements of the pitch series, since five is a divisor of fifteen, while the two series in the piano part never come into synchronisation during the movement. Vincent Benitez, in discussing Messiaen’s preoccupation throughout his career with time and eternity, observes the composer’s division of musical time through discrete segments treated in a cyclical manner as a central interest in his serial thought (Reference BenitezBenitez 2009). The recurring synchronised closures of the pitch and duration series in the cello part contrast with the complete absence of closure in the piano part, which would seem to go on forever or at least well beyond the span of the movement, expressing the sense of temporal spatialisation and eternity. Similarly conceived pitch and rhythmic series recur in the remaining movements of the Quatuor, reflecting the composer’s ‘spatial understanding of musical time through its quantification’ (Reference BenitezBenitez 2009: 294).
Messiaen’s treatise, Technique de mon langage musical (1944), detaches general compositional parameters – rhythm, melody, harmony – from one another, a separation which will come to be central to later ideas of what the serial might be, while adding idiosyncratic features of the composer’s own compositional practice, including bird song and his modes of limited transposition (Reference MessiaenMessiaen 1994). Beyond the technical, the organisation and tone of this unique text anticipate some of the foundational principles of post-1945 serialism. For instance, temporality is prioritised in the Technique by its position as the first parameter to be considered (following a brief single-page chapter on the interrelations of the three parameters). The treatise and the rational processes for treatment of pitch and rhythm in the Quatuor show that Messiaen’s predisposition towards serial thinking was already established prior to the end of the Second World War. His creative autonomy, aesthetic independence from tradition, and objective attention to rhythm, equal to the attention given to pitch, isolate these primary musical parameters for individual treatment. Messiaen’s novel conceptions of pitch, rhythm, and form became pivotal for younger composers of new music and earned for him a leadership position in what would come to seem a serial movement (Reference Whittall and ShollWhittall 2007: 234). Yet through the later twentieth century, Messiaen pursued his distinctive individual compositional concerns about continuity independent of the composers he had so deeply influenced in the post-war years. As Arnold Whittall explains, ‘the remarkable heterogeneity of later twentieth-century developments indicate that avant-garde convictions evolved and persisted even as more “classical” concerns with continuity re-emerged alongside them’ (Reference Whittall and ShollWhittall 2007: 251).
Part II: After 1945
The Serial Movement
It is inviting, or even seductive, to reflect on the post-1945 period as a new beginning or Stunde Null (Zero Hour) in musical composition because of the impact of the enormous social and political upheaval at the end of the Second World War in Europe. A young generation of composers from different European countries, who had been deprived of the opportunity to hear and study new music during the years of political repression and war, aspired to build an utterly new and radical approach to composition that repudiated their European musical heritage in favour of isolating individual elements of parameters of compositional materials (pitch, duration, dynamics, articulation, timbre). This allowed for a focus on individual sounds as discrete objects, and the novel attitude to composition, harnessed in unique ways by individual composers, became known as serialism, implying an affiliation with Schoenberg’s twelve-tone method introduced about a quarter of a century earlier. Yet, at the same time, the most vocal of the young serialist composers rejected the classical techniques of Schoenberg’s method; their fascination lay, in many cases, with Messiaen, then later with Anton Webern, in whose music they discovered great abstraction, purity, and examples of proportional and permutational treatment of musical elements.
Nevertheless, one of those younger composers, Bruno Maderna, would later underscore continuity over rupture in post-1945 musical composition, arguing that ‘there has never been any zero-year in music … just as there never can be any zero-year of culture’. Maderna would stress that the idea of a zero-year (or Zero Hour) was an illusion for the young that assisted them in ‘re-ordering [their] ideas before going forward’ (Maderna, quoted in Reference FearnFearn 1990: 316). Maderna’s serial practice itself was ‘as deeply rooted in the contrapuntal tradition of the past, as it was committed to the exploration of new ideas in musical expression’ (Reference NeidhöferNeidhöfer 2007: 1). M. J. Grant, among others, has rejected the idea of a Stunde Null because, despite the prevalent belief in the creation of a new society among the younger generation, the growing polarisation created by the Cold War among other factors resulted in something closer to cultural pluralism (Reference GrantGrant 2001: 17–20; cf. Reference BealBeal 2000: 107–10).
The infamous essay by another young composer, Pierre Boulez’s ‘Schoenberg Is Dead’ (Reference Boulez1952), described as the ‘ultimate statement of the Stunde Null position’ by Richard Taruskin (Reference 402TaruskinTaruskin 2005b: 18–19), observes Schoenberg’s recent death only months after it occurred, though notably some seven years after the end of the war, but then castigates Schoenberg for taking serialism in the wrong direction by confusing series and theme, for devising a method intended for rigorous control of chromatic writing, for maintaining the outmoded texture of melody and accompaniment, and for not exploring new corresponding modes of structural organisation. The essay concludes by elevating Webern above Schoenberg for his innovations in rhythm and his avoidance of large, extended forms. Though Boulez was exposed to Webern’s music through his teacher, René Leibowitz, author of Schoenberg et son école (Reference Leibowitz1947), it is perhaps worth noting that Boulez later distanced himself from Leibowitz (Reference BoulezBoulez 1952; cf. Reference ErwinErwin 2020).
The intricate narrative of discourse about new music in the years following the Second World War and into the early 1950s embraces the advancement of and later distancing from serialism by some of its proponents; it must balance the opposition of radical innovation, as in the Stunde Null perspective, and historical continuity, including varying stances on serial and contrapuntal practices of Schoenberg and Webern. The serial movement in Europe in the early 1950s, which was characterised by what appeared to be a core of shared compositional interests, was ultimately short-lived, as the representative composers sometimes became engaged in aesthetic disputes and pursued separate compositional trajectories (cf. Reference Toop, Cook and PopleToop 2004: 453–5).
Die Reihe and Darmstadt
The journal Die Reihe: Information über serielle Musik, published in German from 1955 to 1962 (followed by an English edition from 1958 to 1968), launched its run, with editors Herbert Eimert and Karlheinz Stockhausen, with a volume devoted to electronic music. The foreword to that first volume pronounces the journal to be a ‘mouthpiece for the younger generation’ (Reference GrantGrant 2001: 19) and effectively exposes the far-reaching connotations of the serial concept immediately upon the journal’s launch by associating it definitively with the new medium of electronic music. The essays in the first volume impart a shared vision of a radical commitment to electronic music as a fitting medium for music of the time. This shared vision and mode of discourse embody the enlargement of the serial concept to incorporate sound generation and timbre. In his essay, ‘What Is Electronic Music?’, Herbert Eimert describes the radical nature of the new medium and asserts Webern as a principal inspirational source through his visionary understanding of proportion and stylistic purity (Reference EimertEimert 1958). That said, Eimert was not of the younger generation purported to be the voice of the journal; yet in opposition to the journal’s stated aims, his was the first text a reader would encounter. Thirty years younger than Eimert, Paul Gredinger, in his essay ‘Serial Technique’, explicitly portrays the new medium as an expression of serialism that features approaches to proportion and mathematical rationalisation shared with architect Le Corbusier’s methods of calculating architectural proportions (Reference GrantGrant 2001: 165–6). Gredinger wrote: ‘It is our task to describe a fundamental attitude; a principle that we may call the Series … Our aim is an art, in which proportion is everything: a Serial Art’ (Reference GredingerGredinger 1958: 40; translation modified, italics and capitalisation in original).
The Internationale Ferienkurse für Neue Musik in Darmstadt acted as a locus for the study and reception of new music. Young composers from across Europe – including countries recently occupied by Germany – such as Pierre Boulez, Luigi Nono, Bruno Maderna, Karel Goeyvaerts, and Karlheinz Stockhausen, became known as the Darmstadt School, an incongruous moniker in light of the aesthetic differences and disputes among the members, as well as its relatively brief existence. It is fitting that Darmstadt became the setting for the educational and ideological platform of the Darmstadt New Music Courses, dedicated to the study and performance of new music, as Darmstadt had been a cultural centre, including a leading centre in the Jugendstil movement earlier in the twentieth century, and underwent a dramatic rebirth after the catastrophic destruction at the end of the Second World War (Reference IddonIddon 2013: 1–32). While the voices of young composers, particularly Boulez and Stockhausen, strongly articulated the central tenets of the serial attitude, they were encouraged by contemporary composers of an older generation, notably Olivier Messiaen and Herbert Eimert, whose experience, iconoclastic approaches to composition, and knowledge of repertoire offered guidance and leadership.
Messiaen visited Darmstadt in 1949, and his ‘Mode de valeurs et d’intensités’, the second and most abstract movement of the Quatres Études de rhythme, written there, became emblematic for many of the younger composers (Reference IddonIddon 2013: 31). Each of the three parts of the movement is based on permutations of thirty-six pitches (three divisions of twelve each), twenty-four durations, seven dynamic levels, and twelve modes of articulation. As M. J. Grant and others point out, the order of elements is not fixed; as a component of a mode, each pitch is assigned a corresponding duration, dynamic, and articulation value, but the order of presentation is flexible (Reference GrantGrant 2001: 61–2). The permutations are determined by disparate processes distinct from the aggregate permutations of twelve-tone serialism and reflect an interest in control over all aspects of sound. Whereas pitch material in twelve-tone serialism is strictly ordered and other parameters (durations, dynamics, articulation) are free, in ‘Mode de valeurs’ the reverse is true: the other parameters are fixed in relation to pitch while the order of pitches is free (Reference JohnsonJohnson 1975: 106–7). The allusion to the rigour and discipline of Schoenberg’s method in ‘Mode de valeurs’, not to mention the use of series of twelve elements, is clear, but the resulting three-part texture created by the predetermined sonic objects in each mode, characterised by varying levels of activity and absence of rests, avoids all reference to traditional textures and structural organisation; the interest in fundamental properties of sound production – attack, duration, decay, dynamics – reveals the link of the serial concept with electronic composition. As a performer, Messiaen was no doubt acutely sensitive to the sonic implementation of his music. Pianist Peter Hill describes the experience of preparing ‘Mode de valeurs’ for performance.
The piece as a whole began to reveal a shape, with a sense of exposition at the opening as the ‘modes’ begin to unravel, and of a corresponding winding-down at the end, where the upper stave resumes its mode in the original order. Meanwhile the interest in the central part of the piece lies in the incisive interplay between staves, especially where notes of similar dynamic come in quick succession.
Hill’s account of Messiaen’s 1951 recording of the Quatres Études de rhythme, made shortly after the completion of the composition, reinforces his remarks about the challenges of creating clarity and differentiation of the elements of dynamics and articulation (Reference Hill, Dingle and SimeoneHill 2007: 89).
‘Mode de valeurs’ had a direct impact on several of the young serial composers, in some cases reinforced by Messiaen’s recording (Reference IddonIddon 2013: 59–60). Three pertinent examples are Boulez’s Structure Ia, the second movement of Karel Goeyvaerts’s Sonata for Two Pianos, and Stockhausen’s Kreuzspiel. A brief review of mutual precompositional principles underlying these three works will illustrate the serial underpinning of the Darmstadt School in the early 1950s.
Boulez’s Structure Ia (1951–2) for two pianos takes the first series or division from ‘Mode de valeurs’ and assigns order positions from 1 to 12 to each pitch class, treating the series as a twelve-tone row, but avoiding the classical twelve-tone permutations. The numerical values of the order positions from Messiaen’s original series always refer to the pitches in the original series and are translated into representations of pitch classes; two 12 × 12 matrices, one derived from the original form of the series and the other derived from the inversion, display the twelve transpositions and twelve inversions of the series, respectively. The series of twelve durations in ‘Mode de valeurs’ is likewise read in the same matrices, while the predetermined link in Messiaen’s work between pitch and other parameters is abolished. The two piano parts systematically deploy forms of the series from the matrices in reciprocal fashion for the most part, with occasional spontaneous choices or liberties, and the sense of three continuous textural layers in Messiaen’s work is absent (Reference 402TaruskinTaruskin 2005b: 33–4). In effect, Structure Ia, though derived from procedures in ‘Mode de valeurs’, is based on very different precompositional strategies.
The second movement of Karel Goeyvaerts’s Sonata for Two Pianos, presented in Darmstadt in 1951, does not make direct use of Messiaen’s pitch material from ‘Mode de valeurs’ but applies algorithmic procedures to the same parameters of pitch, durations, dynamics, and modes of articulation. Goeyvaerts’s compositional procedure involves the assignment of discrete values to the elements of each parameter as they pertain to notes or points in the score, absolutely or relative to an arbitrary reference point. Parametric values are summed and correspond, in principle, to Goeyvaerts’s mystical idea of the ‘synthetic number’ (cf. Reference IddonIddon 2013: 53–7; Reference DelaereDelaere 1996; Reference ToopToop 1974: 153–4).
Stockhausen’s Kreuzspiel (1952, later revised), scored for oboe, bass clarinet, piano, and three percussionists and first performed at Darmstadt, was inspired in recognisable ways by Messiaen’s ‘Mode de valeurs’ and the second movement of Goeyvaerts’s Sonata for Two Pianos (Reference MaconieMaconie 1976: 26). In Kreuzspiel, as in Messiaen’s ‘Mode de valeurs’, pitches are fused with non-pitch parameters into sonic units. In Kreuzspiel’s three main sections, the sonic units unfold continual permutations that are based on systematic registral reorderings mirrored in time over the course of the work. Serial treatment in Kreuzspiel includes dynamic repositioning of composite elements on local and large scales (cf. Reference IddonIddon 2013: 72–5; Reference MaconieMaconie 1976: 21–6; Reference ToopToop 1974: 158–64).
Herbert Eimert, already an established composer, author, and musicologist before the war, became a leading figure in the propagation of new music through his involvement in the Darmstadt New Music Courses between 1946 and 1951, his editorial position for Die Reihe, and his roles as radio broadcaster and administrator in the Nordwestdeutscher Rundfunk from 1945 to 1955 (Reference IversonIverson 2019: 23–4). Although the Stunde Null perspective on new music in early post-war Germany is associated with youth, Eimert’s familiarity with new technology and his experience in administration and publication facilitated the dissemination of the serialist agenda. His influential Musikalisches Nachtprogramm, ‘a bimonthly broadcast aimed at educating listeners on the concepts and sounds of the “new” music that had been suppressed or unknown during the war’ (Reference IversonIverson 2019: 23–4), helped to bring the experience of hearing new music to the young composers who sought to formulate their own declaration of a compositional philosophy. As co-editor of Die Reihe with Stockhausen, Eimert’s engagement in the serialist agenda was particularly visible. His leadership role at the Westdeutscher Rundfunk from its beginning in 1955 (following the separation of the Nordwestdeutscher Rundfunk into the Norddeutscher Rundfunk and the Westdeutscher Rundfunk) enabled him to promote music created in the major electronic music studios in Germany and beyond as music ‘that could finally take full compositional control over timbre, as well as the other compositional elements such as pitch, duration, and dynamics’ (Reference IversonIverson 2019: 76). In this way, understanding electronic music as a reflection of the serialist agenda, overtly expressed in the first volume of Die Reihe, is consistent and logical. An essay by Wolf-Eberhard von Lewinski in the fourth volume of Die Reihe devoted to young composers captures this linkage:
[The most gifted of today’s composers] have found a new way that promises a solution for their conflict of conscience – to compose no superfluous notes and yet not to imitate Webern. They have been urged on by the timely ‘invention’ of electronic music … Webern’s intentions have been regarded as completely justifying serial modes of procedure, but now they can be revivified by applying them in a field that is new and spacious … the field of electronic musical material. Composition with this material, more than any other, requires very comprehensive laws.
Just as serial precompositional schemes and structures regulated by numerical patterns or designs in acoustic serial music were sometimes overridden by composers’ aesthetic and poetic choices, composers of electronic music also had to make compromises for practical reasons due to technological limitations in the studio (Reference IversonIverson 2014b: 345–6).
Partitioning the twentieth century into pre- and post-1945 periods serves a useful purpose and marks an undeniable point of division, but, as the quotation from Maderna above (p. 10) implies, the Stunde Null perspective taken literally is oversimplistic and loses sight of strands of continuity from before 1945 that persisted, including the continued interest in and extension of Schoenberg’s twelve-tone techniques in spite of their renunciation by some of the most vocal younger composers. Luigi Nono, for example, some of whose early works were performed at Darmstadt in the early 1950s, wrote about the atomic concentration on individual properties of sound in terms of an expansion, not rejection, of Schoenberg’s twelve-tone technique (Reference Nono, De Benedictis and RizzardiNono 2018b; cf. Reference NonoNono 1958). Nono’s Il canto sospeso (1955–6), a nine-movement work, exhibits serial precompositional schemes to profile individual musical parameters, including a single, all-interval twelve-tone series that governs the pitch content (Reference NielingerNielinger 2006). His compositional technique expresses the serialist aesthetic of rigorous permutational control over individual musical parameters but distinguishes itself with its expressive text and overt political, anti-fascist message. Similarly, Luciano Berio embraced aspects of the serialist agenda in the early 1950s, and followed practices similar to other Darmstadt composers, but did not relinquish authority to serial routines. As Christoph Neidhöfer explains, ‘[Berio] had a clear vision of, and maintained full control over, how the music would ultimately sound’ (Reference NeidhöferNeidhöfer 2009: 304).
The coherent and related expressions of serialism as a compositional practice and aesthetic in the early 1950s in Darmstadt were transitory, as the composers pursued their individual conceptions of musical material, organisation, and continuity. The cessation of publication of Die Reihe in 1962 perhaps similarly reflects the dearth of common ground in the conception of serialism, both as compositional technique and as a way of thinking (cf. Reference Toop, Cook and PopleToop 2004: 475).
Serialism in the United States of America
Of the three understandings of serialism given in the introduction to this chapter (p. 3), only the first two (serialism in terms of fixed ordering of elements and serialism in terms of expansion and diversity of compositional approaches and aesthetics) prevail in serialism in the United States, explained in part by the different dissemination of Schoenberg’s twelve-tone technique. Before the Second World War, Schoenberg’s music was not well known in the United States outside ‘ultra-modern’ composers such as Henry Cowell, but interest in his music grew dramatically after the war (Reference Peles and NicholsPeles 1998: 500–4). The third understanding of serialism (serialism as a philosophy or ideology) did not evolve analogously in the United States, due to different attitudes towards Schoenberg, different wartime experience, different cultural and political contexts, and different views about history and historical consciousness (Reference Peles and NicholsPeles 1998: 509). No cohesive school of thought or doctrine analogous to the Darmstadt School appeared in the United States, yet the end of the war coincided in the United States with a desire among many composers for artistic renewal.
Between 1955 and 1961, composer and music theorist Milton Babbitt published three articles that set the foundation of twelve-tone theory in terms of a theoretical expansion of Schoenberg’s method (Reference BabbittBabbitt 1955; Reference BabbittBabbitt 1960; Reference BabbittBabbitt 1961). Babbitt’s music is sometimes described as aggregate music because of the successions of aggregates whose interior pitch-class arrangement is directed through the organisation of arrays (Reference MeadMead 1994: 13–16). Babbitt generalised Schoenberg’s techniques in mathematical terms while uncovering the potential for expansion beyond Schoenberg’s practice. Drawing on mathematical group theory, he demonstrated that combinatoriality, for example, a technique explored extensively by Schoenberg, could be generalised within the twelve-tone system to reveal compositional potential far beyond that utilised by Schoenberg. Babbitt employed mathematics in his theoretical writings and music not as a compositional device, but as a means to expose a system of seemingly endless abstract possibilities (cf. Reference MorrisMorris 1987). Babbitt was appointed to the faculty at Princeton University in 1938, and his advanced training in mathematics, formal logic, and analytical philosophy helped to facilitate the addition of the PhD in composition to its highest degrees in music along with musicology. Indeed, the expansion of access to college education was profitable to the dissemination of serialism in American higher education, as seen in the 1956 dedication of the Schoenberg Hall as a concert space at the University of Los Angeles at California (Reference FeisstFeisst 2011: 236). With the inclusion after the war of musical composition as a subject for advanced study in the American academy, new music began to escape much of its association with the avant-garde. Serialism acquired a more mainstream image and was characterised by a wide range of compositional applications that were influenced to varying degrees by techniques of Schoenberg. Many, though certainly not all, serial composers were affiliated within a university setting (Reference StrausStraus 2008: 373–7).
The legacy of Schoenberg’s twelve-tone technique in the United States is reflected in the compositional practices of composers such as Roger Sessions, Aaron Copland, Elliot Carter, and Igor Stravinsky, in addition to Babbitt. Sessions, who had been Babbitt’s composition teacher, engaged in serial practices in his Solo Violin Sonata in 1953 only after recognising its potential in the music of Dallapiccola and Babbitt. With his knowledge of Schoenberg’s music, Sessions explored the capabilities for greater control over the circulation of the aggregate (Reference Peles and NicholsPeles 1998: 508). Like Sessions, Copland too explored serial techniques, perhaps most notably in his orchestral work, Connotations (1962), synthesising with them tonal strategies and sonorities (Reference Peles and NicholsPeles 1998: 515). Elliot Carter did not explicitly espouse serial practice, but his compositional style became significantly more rigorous following the war with the development of his signature technique of metric modulation (Reference 402TaruskinTaruskin 2005b: 275–6), a method for proportionally transforming one metre into another, combinatorial methods of identifying subsets of the aggregate (Link 2022: 33–9), and his exploration of all-interval series (cf. Reference Morris and StarrMorris and Starr 1974). These mathematically inspired techniques, undoubtedly discovered independently, reflect the composer’s new sense of purpose (Reference 402TaruskinTaruskin 2005b: 276–80). Finally, Stravinsky, who emigrated to the United States in 1939, became interested in Schoenberg’s music in 1952, following Schoenberg’s death. Stravinsky’s direct engagement with Schoenberg’s techniques waned as he explored serial techniques influenced by Ernst Krenek, particularly the technique of rotational arrays (Reference StrausStraus 2001: 8–21). Stravinsky had read Krenek’s Studies in Counterpoint (Reference Krenek1940) and attended a lecture by Krenek at Princeton in 1959 that was later published as ‘The Extent and Limits of Serial Techniques’ (Reference KrenekKrenek 1960). Stravinsky became known for his application and extension of Krenek’s technique of rotational arrays, explained in detail in Krenek’s article, in his later works (Reference StrausStraus 2001: 141–82).
Part III: Conclusions
The distinction between serialism in Europe and the United States, while expedient in a discussion of theorising serialism, becomes limited in its effectiveness, partially in consideration of technological developments after 1945, including computer and recording technologies that have impacted the composition and dissemination of new music. The serial concept has in some way or another engaged aesthetic and practical interests of composers across the Western world for the last century, regardless of nationality.
Notwithstanding the absence of a straightforward, secure definition, serialism became a leading force in twentieth-century music in Europe and the United States. Universal principles of purity, rationalism, and objectivity and a demand for severance from the past seem to underlie the aesthetics of the serialist movement in post-war Europe, even if these principles, on close examination, were not held uncritically (Reference WhittallWhittall 2008: 151; cf. Reference IversonIverson 2019: 75). In the United States, the need for separation from the past after the war did not carry political overtones in the same way, but a wish for distance from the past in the spirit of artistic revitalisation can be recognised in the music of many composers. The desire to explore fresh, innovative means of musical organisation through varying conceptions of serialism created common ground across geographical and temporal divides. The common ground across the geographical divide of the Atlantic Ocean between conceptions of serialism in Europe and the United States, and the common ground across the temporal divide between debates surrounding Schoenberg’s method before and after the war illuminate the adoption of serialism into the realm of intellectual history (cf. Reference AshbyAshby 2001).
As Marcus Zagorski explains, referring to serialist composers in Europe, attention to discipline and control over material was a connecting link that was reflected in individual compositional decisions and technique (Reference ZagorskiZagorski 2009). Such a broad characterisation of autonomy granted to individual material constituents in musical composition can similarly be recognised in new music by composers on the other side of the Atlantic, as Anne C. Shreffler writes:
If there is a common denominator in the diverse techniques and approaches called ‘serialism’, then it is the notion of granting autonomy to the different qualities of musical material. In the absence of an a priori harmonic system, pitch and rhythm were no longer privileged as the defining features of musical content.
Recognising this common denominator, however, plays only a part in theorising serialism. Cultural context, along with the individualistic and conflicting attitudes, circumstances, and compositional approaches among key figures involved are further vital factors. Theorising serialism recognises its transmutation, in technical, theoretical, and philosophical terms, across most of the twentieth century. Acknowledging the dynamic disposition, instability, and impermanence of serialism is essential to framing its theories.
Any study of the aesthetics of serialism should begin with definitions of ‘aesthetics’ and ‘serialism’, for the long and complex histories of these terms have given rise to conflicting usage. This chapter begins with definitions and then analyses examples of serial aesthetics found in writings about serial music. Following this, six central themes in the aesthetics of serialism are outlined and supported with further examples from a diversity of sources. The chapter concludes with thoughts about what relevance serial aesthetics might have for the study of music and the humanities today.
Serialism
As this Cambridge Companion so abundantly illustrates, serialism is not one thing. It is a variety of different practices by different people, in different locations, in different periods, and under different historical conditions. Why does this caveat matter? Because even if the same term ‘serialism’ is used, it may mean different things to different people, and that is why definitions form a necessary starting point. In the most basic sense, serial music is music that is based on a series of something. The series makes the music ‘serial’. Beyond this, however, it becomes complicated, for the question ‘a series of what?’ can be answered differently according to different understandings of the term ‘serialism’.
In English and French, ‘serial music’ or musique sérielle is used broadly to refer to any music that uses the serial principle, both when the series is applied only to the organisation of pitch (as in the music of Schoenberg and his students) and when it is applied to multiple aspects of music at the same time, such as pitch, duration, loudness, and timbre (as in the music of many post-war serial composers). This post-war practice is sometimes called ‘multiple serialism’ or ‘total serialism’ in English. The English and French terms for serial music follow the original meaning of musique sérielle, which was coined by the composer and author René Leibowitz in 1947 in his writings about the twelve-tone method of Schoenberg and his students (Reference Blumröder and EggebrechtBlumröder 1995). German usage differs. In German, there are two terms: Zwölftonmusik (twelve-tone music) and serielle Musik (serial music). Zwölftonmusik refers to music that uses the series only for the organisation of pitch. Serielle Musik, on the other hand, refers to what is sometimes called ‘multiple serialism’ in English, that is, to compositional techniques developed in the 1950s and 1960s that (to a greater or lesser extent) purposefully differentiated themselves from Schoenberg’s pitch-based serialism and applied the series simultaneously to other so-called parameters of music, including duration, loudness, and timbre. This chapter, like this book as a whole, understands serialism in the broadest sense and includes all meanings and practices; it encompasses music that uses a series to organise pitch only and music that uses a series to organise anything else.
Aesthetics
‘Aesthetics’ is also a term that has different traditions of usage. The philosopher Wolfgang Welsch has argued that aesthetics, as defined narrowly in philosophical encyclopaedias and by philosophers in the discipline itself, would be more accurately named ‘artistics’: it is an ‘explication of art with particular attention to beauty’. As such, it does not respect the much more general ‘science of sensuous cognition’ that was established by Alexander Baumgarten in the eighteenth century and for which he invented the name ‘aesthetics’. Aesthetics in the narrow sense – what Welsch calls ‘artistics’ – means only the philosophy of art, and Welsch notes that this meaning was introduced by Immanuel Kant, developed by G. W. F. Hegel, and is still preferred by many philosophers today (Reference Welsch and HonkanenWelsch 1997).
My ‘aesthetics of serialism’ understands ‘aesthetics’ in the narrower sense. This chapter is concerned with ideas about art – more specifically, ideas about serialism, as they appear in writings on music and the philosophy of music. This includes ideas about what serialism is or what it should be, ideas about why it is or why it should be, ideas about where it came from or where it is going, ideas about its value or significance, and ideas about its connection to other realms of culture, including other art forms, the sciences, and politics. These facets of the aesthetics of serialism are not separate and distinct; rather, they blend together, are subtly interconnected, and are fused with ideas about compositional technique. In fact, this is one of the most challenging aspects of the aesthetics of serialism: texts that are ostensibly about compositional technique often include aesthetic positions and touch upon other branches of philosophy such as ethics and metaphysics, and other realms of culture such as politics, science, and history. Two specific examples will help to illustrate this point. These examples, taken from the writings of the philosopher Theodor W. Adorno and the composer György Ligeti, will introduce some, but not all, of the central themes in serial aesthetics that are outlined later in this chapter.
Example 1 Adorno
In his book Philosophy of New Music, Adorno described Schoenberg’s twelve-tone method as ‘truly the fate of music’:
The rules are not arbitrarily conceived. They are configurations of the historical obligation in material. … A system of the domination of nature results in music. It corresponds to a desire present since the beginnings of the bourgeois era: to grasp and order all sound, and to reduce the magic essence of music to human logic. … The subject dominates music through the rational system, only to fall victim to the rational system itself.
Before unpacking this passage, one should note that Adorno’s study of Schoenberg in Philosophy of New Music is titled ‘Schoenberg and Progress’. Progress is perhaps the most essential idea in the aesthetics of serialism, and it lies behind many of the central themes examined later in this chapter; it was present from the inception of the technique in the 1920s and through its widespread and varied practices in the 1950s and 1960s and continues to be germane for those composers who are still today influenced by serial techniques.
Adorno’s understanding of progress, however, was not the usual one. Throughout his writings, he argued that, although we have little choice but to follow the dictates of historical progress, such progress may not always result in a better world – or better music. One must therefore, he believed, constantly assert subjective individuality against the collective historical process. This dialectic is the key to understanding the passage on Schoenberg’s twelve-tone method just quoted, as well as much of Adorno’s other writing about music. But understanding the dialectic itself is not straightforward, for it brings together the philosophy of Hegel, the social theory of Max Weber, and the theory of a ‘dialectic of enlightenment’ that Adorno had developed with Max Horkheimer. The complexities of these ideas obviously deserve an explication that goes beyond the confines of this short chapter, but it is possible to summarise Adorno’s dialectic and then explain its import in a bit more detail.
The briefest possible summary for the cognoscenti would be as follows. The history of intersubjective consciousness in Western culture (a kind of Hegelian Geist) advances according to the efforts of humans to free themselves from the forces of nature, which they accomplish through the control and mastery of nature. This process can be seen in the progressive demystification of the world (as in Weber’s idea of Entzauberung, to which I turn presently) and the increasing rationalisation of all aspects of social life. But in its drive to master nature, human subjectivity has given rise to instrumental rationality, the absolute domination of which turns against the liberated subject and becomes a new form of control over the subject. The twelve-tone method, according to Adorno, reflects this process in the very material of music.
Now, that may be fine as far as summaries go, but what does it really mean? One must return to Adorno’s text as quoted and examine it line by line to better understand. The reason that Schoenberg’s twelve-tone method is said to be ‘truly the fate of music’ is the same reason that its ‘rules are not arbitrarily conceived’: Schoenberg did not so much choose to compose in this way but was thought to be required to do so. Adorno believed that serial music resulted from a historical process in which musical expression developed through the breakdown of formal conventions, increasing chromaticism, and increasing dissonance to atonality, as well as (though not mentioned in the quotation in question) through the use of the variation principle in the music of Beethoven, Wagner, and Brahms. These developments were said to be consolidated in Schoenberg’s twelve-tone method and subjected to rational control.
Adorno’s belief that a supposedly ‘objective’ historical process directed the course of compositional technique depends upon a philosophy of history that can and should be critiqued. In other words, the question of whether there really was an obligation for Schoenberg to compose twelve-tone music, as Adorno claimed, should be asked; the alternative is that Schoenberg merely chose to compose twelve-tone music. Notably, Adorno’s historical narrative favours practices from a certain period of Austro-German music while ignoring other periods and other cultures – and ignoring, by the way, Schoenberg’s own reasons for inventing the twelve-tone method.
Adorno’s philosophy of history is evident in the next sentence of the quoted passage: the rules of the twelve-tone method, he claimed, are ‘configurations of the historical obligation in material’. This ‘historical obligation’ can be understood as a version of Hegel’s idea of an objective Geist, or ‘spirit’, that directs world history. Adorno saw no problem in using Hegel’s idea, and he later admitted that it was a central theme in his Philosophy of New Music and even ‘taken for granted’ in his own experience of the world (Reference AdornoAdorno 1950). But Adorno’s ‘objective spirit’ was not strictly Hegelian. It depended also on Weber’s social theory of increasing rationalisation in Western culture, and the connection to Weber helps make sense of the next part of the quotation.
‘A system of the domination of nature results in music’, the next sentence states. ‘It corresponds to a desire present since the beginnings of the bourgeois era: to grasp and order all sound, and to reduce the magic essence of music to human logic.’ These sentences read like a textbook example of Weber’s idea of Entzauberung, the literal translation of which is ‘the process of taking the magic out of something’, or ‘demystification’. Weber, a tremendously influential sociologist, wrote of the increasing rationalisation of social practices in the Western world from the period of the Renaissance onwards and described this as entailing a belief that ‘whenever one desired, one could find that there are fundamentally no mysterious, incalculable forces involved [in things], but rather, that all things – in principle – can be controlled by means of calculation. But this means: the demystification [Entzauberung] of the world’ (Reference WeberWeber 1995: 19). Weber argued that this tendency went hand in hand with the progressive domination of nature, and Adorno described the twelve-tone method explicitly as a system by which music dominates nature. For Adorno, the nature being dominated was both the sound material manipulated by the composer and also the expressive impulse of the composer himself – both were controlled by the rationality of the twelve-tone method, which reduced the ‘magic essence of music’ by subjecting it to the order of ‘human logic’.
If at this point Adorno’s aesthetics begins to look like a critique of serialism, the final sentence in the quoted excerpt leaves no doubt: ‘the subject dominates music through the rational system, only to fall victim to the rational system itself’. In other words, the effect of Schoenberg’s twelve-tone method of composition was that it enchained the composer and robbed him of his subjective freedom. But Schoenberg was not the only victim, according to Adorno. His compositional method mirrored a larger social process in which humans are robbed of their freedom and enslaved by the forces of rationalisation. This larger social theory was presented by Adorno and Horkheimer in their book Dialectic of Enlightenment, in which they critically examined the development of Western culture up to the period of the Hitler regime and tried to understand ‘why mankind, instead of entering into a truly human condition, is sinking into a new kind of barbarism’, the ‘barbarism’ in this case referring not only to the rise of totalitarianism but also the manipulative forces of capitalism and the culture industry (Reference Horkheimer and AdornoHorkheimer and Adorno 1972: xi). They argued that a particular idea lies at the root of Western culture and can be ‘traced back to the first chapters of Genesis’, that is, that humans have tried to advance their own interests by means of the domination and control of nature (Reference JayJay 1996: 258). Such efforts, however, which were intended to liberate humans from the forces of nature, have developed into a new force that impedes the realisation of liberation. In other words, the use of instrumental rationality to control nature now controls the user and precludes their freedom; that is the dialectic of enlightenment.
The ideas presented in Dialectic of Enlightenment were essential for the Schoenberg critique in Adorno’s Philosophy of New Music, and Philosophy of New Music was seen by Adorno as ‘definitive for everything that [he] wrote about music thereafter’ (Reference Adorno and TiedemannAdorno 1977: 719). Understanding these texts will help one understand Adorno’s music aesthetics. Subsequently, as serial practices spread beyond the Schoenberg school in the 1950s and were developed by a younger generation of composers, Adorno believed his critique of pre-war serialism to be even more applicable to post-war serialism. As composers applied serial ordering to not only pitch but also duration, loudness, and timbre, Adorno critiqued the further expansion of rational control and greater loss of subjective freedom. Post-war composers, on the other hand, saw their expansion of serial technique as progress, and they did not concern themselves with the dialectics or discontents of that progress.
Example 2 Ligeti
One example of the narrative of progress many post-war serial composers shared can be seen in a passage from an essay by the composer György Ligeti:
After Schoenberg had found a rule-based method for ordering free atonality, the serial principle, which was first applied only to the dimension of pitch, strove for expansion to the totality of form. This led to the discrete quantification of all parameters, through which such music became the result of overlapping prefabricated arrangements … But only shortly after durations, intensities and timbres had been serially organised, the expansion of this method sought to cover more global categories, such as relationships between [different] registers and densities, and distributions of types of movement and structure, as well as the proportioning of the entire course of form.
What Ligeti described here is the post-war development of serialism in Western Europe, from a method that applied serial order only to pitch to a method that applied serial order to many other aspects of music. The reason his description is of interest is because it implies that the serial method did not result from the preferences and decisions of composers; rather, it was the result of some larger historical process. Although Ligeti did not explicitly invoke an ‘objective spirit’ as Adorno did, that spirit is at work behind the scenes. This becomes apparent in the way in which Ligeti’s writing endows technique with agency: the serial principle, he claimed, ‘strove for expansion to the totality of form’; the expansion of the method then ‘sought to cover more global categories’. In Ligeti’s telling, it was not the subjective decisions and aesthetic preferences of composers at work; rather, it was the technique, and history itself, that directed composers’ actions.
Many other serial composers believed in this historical narrative and thereby ignored their own personal preferences in choosing compositional techniques. Pierre Boulez wrote in 1952 that serialism was a ‘logical consequence of history’ (Reference Boulez and ThéveninBoulez 1991f: 214), and he wrote this in an essay titled ‘Schoenberg Is Dead’, apparently oblivious to the fact that Schoenberg himself, in the essay ‘Composition with Twelve Tones’, described the twelve-tone method as a necessary historical development that was dictated by the laws of nature (Reference Schoenberg and SteinSchoenberg 1975a). Schoenberg, it seems, was not dead: he lived on in some of Boulez’s own ideas about music. Boulez learned the twelve-tone method from the student of Anton Webern, friend of Schoenberg, and creator of the term musique sérielle René Leibowitz, who argued in lectures and writings that serialism was a logical and necessary development resulting from the history of polyphony (Reference KappKapp 1988: 5–6). By the late 1950s and early 1960s (the time in which Ligeti’s essay appeared), a diversity of composers refused to let this myth die. Luigi Nono, for example, claimed in 1958 that an ‘absolute historical and logical continuity of development prevails between the beginnings of twelve-tone music and its current state’, and he cited as evidence the same historical stages given by Ligeti in the quotation discussed here (Reference NonoNono 1958: 25). In 1964, Dieter Schnebel also cited these historical stages and then proposed additional steps to continue their further progress (Reference Schnebel and ZellerSchnebel 1972).
Schnebel has been seen by some as a critic of serialism, but he did, in fact, preserve the historical narrative so essential to its aesthetics. Ligeti also was seen as a critic of serialism, and the essay from which the quotation is taken was interpreted by some readers as ‘the epitome of an anti-serialist manifesto’ (Reference BorioBorio 1993: 33). But the fact that this historical narrative was maintained by these supposed critics of serialism, and remained relatively long in circulation, shows the extent to which serial aesthetics also influenced developments away from early serial composition. Similar ideas about history were shared by otherwise dissimilar composers, and these ideas bind the post-serial music of the 1960s and beyond to the aesthetics of serialism and testify to its influence. The appeals to historical necessity and progress were not only voiced explicitly, as in the statements discussed here, they also underlie most of the themes that are examined in what follows.
Themes in the Aesthetics of Serialism
It is difficult to reduce serial aesthetics to essential themes – both because of the amount and diversity of writing on the topic and because these themes are not necessarily presented distinctly as such in this writing. But there are shared ideas that helped give serial music and aesthetics their features and that contributed to the prestige they once had. It should be noted that many of these ideas arose in the post-war period. This is understandable given that the technique became widespread after the Second World War, and there was a corresponding increase in writing about the topic then. The reasons why serialism became widespread are considered in an ensuing subsection on the influence of serial aesthetics (‘The Influence of Serial Aesthetics’).
History, Necessity, and Progress
The excerpts from Adorno and Ligeti quoted in Examples 1 and 2 express a belief that composers are not free to choose the materials with which they work; rather, composers are said to be required to act in accordance with the demands of some higher power, and doing so contributes to historical progress. This general idea, with differing details, is frequently encountered in writings on the aesthetics of serialism. It can be seen in Schoenberg’s assertion that the twelve-tone method was dictated by the ‘laws of nature’; it is clearly a part of Adorno’s belief in an ‘objective spirit’; and it informs the understanding of history outlined by later serial and post-serial composers including Boulez, Nono, Ligeti, and Schnebel. The idea of progress is also relevant to most of the themes outlined below: it is relevant to the relation between serialism and the political realities of the post-war period, to the connection of serialism to science and technology, to the idea of composition as experimentation, to the serial ideals of unity and organicism, and to the new culture of listening and musical perception implicit (and sometimes explicit) in serial music. The idea of progress has, accordingly, been given pride of place in this chapter. It is an idea that depends upon the assumption that progress is desirable or, at least, necessary, and this assumption tells us much about the period in which serialism became widespread. It tells us perhaps even more about the immediately preceding period, for progress can seem desirable or necessary when the past (or present) becomes unbearable.
Politics: Anti-fascist Resistance, Anti-communist Resistance, and Freedom
It is a paradox of serial aesthetics that, while many composers believed twelve-tone and post-war serial practices were historically determined, they also embraced the technique as a new beginning. In the post-war period, one of the central concerns of serial composers was to find a new approach to composition, something very different from tonal music. Their motivation for doing so was substantially influenced by extra-musical factors. In 1933, for example, the inventor of the twelve-tone method was stripped of his professorship in Berlin, and his scores were publicly burned in front of the national opera house. Schoenberg’s Jewish background and his role as a leading modernist artist made him doubly offensive to the Nazi regime and earned him a place in their infamous ‘degenerate art’ exhibition (Reference Hinton and MorganHinton 1993: 101 and 106). This made his twelve-tone method very appealing to post-war composers, for it seemed ‘untainted by any whiff of collaboration’ and was thought to represent ‘intransigence and resistance’ (Reference KappKapp 1988: 13). Leibowitz associated it with the freedom of the human spirit and worked secretly with it during the war years. He published five books and fifteen articles about it immediately after, and these publications were a significant part of the post-war reception of twelve-tone music (Reference ShrefflerShreffler 2000: 33–5).
Nazi cultural policies seemed to be repeated in communist countries of the Eastern bloc only a few years after the end of the war, and this gave additional impetus to the appeal of serialism. When the Soviet’s Division of Propaganda officially denounced ‘formalism’ in 1948, which included twelve-tone music, and promoted socialist realism, many artists and ‘supporters of the avant-garde saw a clear analogy between the repressions of the Third Reich and those of Stalin’ (Reference Kovács, Borio and DanuserKovács 1997a: 117). More recently, scholars have shown that serial music was in fact practised in many parts of the Eastern bloc and even supported by some socialist governments. But Western observers at the time saw direct parallels between communism and National Socialism regarding the condemnation and prohibition of particular techniques and figures in modernist music.
Western governments responded to this by increasing their support for modernist art. The Darmstadt New Music Courses, for example, which were founded in 1946 to help promote music banned by the Nazi regime, became a centre for the promotion of music prohibited in the East and a beacon for compositional approaches such as serialism, which was thought to represent the values of Western democracies (Reference Kovács, Borio and DanuserKovács 1997b). Those values are apparent in the central themes of serial aesthetics outlined here: progress, freedom, rationality, and, as we will see, superior science and technology. Serialism represented freedom not only in a political sense, but also in a technical sense, and this is another paradox of serial aesthetics. To understand how such a highly rationalised and strictly controlled approach to composition could represent freedom in this way, one must consider the role that science and technology had in reinventing music from what were thought to be the most basic elements of sound.
Science and Technology
Although not terribly relevant for the aesthetics of Schoenberg and his students, science and technology were absolutely essential for post-war serial composers. Looking again at Example 2 from Ligeti, in which he described the historical development of serialism in Western Europe, one will find a specific term to which the serial idea was applied: the ‘parameters’ of pitch, duration, intensity, and timbre. The term ‘parameter’ was taken directly from contemporaneous research being done in electro-acoustic music studios, and it represented the nucleus of post-war serial composition. It was first applied to serial music by the composer and theorist Karlheinz Stockhausen, who used it in 1953 to describe the pitches, durations, intensities, and timbres of his composition Kontra-Punkte (Reference Blumröder and EggebrechtBlumröder 1995; cf. Reference Stockhausen and SchnebelStockhausen 1963a: 37). Stockhausen acquired the term from Werner Meyer-Eppler, a leading researcher in electronic music, whom he met in 1952 and with whom he studied (Reference Blumröder and EggebrechtBlumröder 1995: 335). But Stockhausen acquired much more than terminology from electronic music studios; he also acquired his very conception of music there, a conception of music dependent upon the kind of analysis and synthesis of sound enabled by studio work. In early electronic music studios, sounds were understood to consist of four component elements: frequency (or pitch), duration (which generated rhythm), intensity (or dynamics), and waveform (or timbre); these became the parameters to which composers then applied serial techniques in their effort to advance history beyond the pitch-only serialism of Schoenberg.
These individual components of sound were also the focus of work being done by composers in the United States, such as Milton Babbitt. Babbitt had a background in mathematics, did pioneering work in early electronic-sound studios, made extensive contributions to music theory, and had a tremendous influence on the development of music composition and theory as academic disciplines. In a widely read essay from 1958, he compared the serial music of the time to physics and mathematics and argued that, like these disciplines, music needed the support of universities to ensure its further progress (Reference BabbittBabbitt 1958). Electronic music studios on both sides of the Atlantic, and elsewhere, enabled composers to create any sound or structure imaginable, or at least they promised to do so. This, in turn, supported the desire to create a new music unrelated to the past, and it imparted a sense of freedom limited only by the capacity for invention. Post-war serialism was an expression of this creative freedom.
The Idea of the Experiment
As post-war composers reinvented music without the traditional syntax and forms of tonality, they often conceived of individual pieces as experiments that furthered their research. The concept of composition as experimentation was, according to the musicologist Carl Dahlhaus, ‘nothing less than the fundamental aesthetic paradigm of serial and post-serial music’ in the 1950s and 1960s (Reference Dahlhaus and JostDahlhaus 1983b: 84). Dahlhaus was uniquely placed to make this assessment: he was one of the most prolific and influential music scholars of the twentieth century; he knew post-war music at first hand and wrote extensively about it; and his knowledge of the history of aesthetics was unparalleled among musicologists. His idea of an aesthetic paradigm of experimentation consisted of three complementary elements that he believed characterised serial and post-serial music in Western Europe after the war: first, a philosophy of history dependent upon ideas from Adorno’s writings; second, the idea of a ‘problem-history’ of composition that unfolded in a way analogous to the history of science; and finally, the idea of a ‘work-in-progress’ that replaced the nineteenth-century work-concept of a closed, perfected whole (Reference Dahlhaus and JostDahlhaus 1983b: 82–85).
Adorno’s philosophy of history should now be familiar: a quoted passage from his Philosophy of New Music and my detailed explication of it appear above (pp. 22–5). Adorno had a significant influence on post-war serial composers, even if they did not understand his philosophy with the nuance and erudition it deserved (see Reference ZagorskiZagorski 2005 for a reception history). What they took from his writing was the idea that not all musical materials are available to composers at any given time; rather, a composer is ‘required’ to work with only those materials history dictates to be appropriate. Dahlhaus was critical of this idea, and he thereby criticised historical metanarratives long before so-called ‘new musicologists’ did. But he recognised how this particular narrative did much to shape music history.
Adorno’s philosophy of history led post-war composers to believe that serialism was a ‘logical consequence of history’, and I have shown already that Ligeti, Boulez, Nono, and Schnebel, among others, held this view. These composers saw it as their task to find the next ‘logical consequence of history’, and Dahlhaus argued that this caused them to view music history as a ‘problem-history’ of composition. In such a ‘problem-history’, each new approach to composition was thought to be a solution to problems found in the preceding approach, and each new approach created new problems that required further solutions and generated new techniques. Dahlhaus drew parallels between this problem-history and the history of science, specifically, the theory of ‘normal science’ presented in Thomas Kuhn’s influential book The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Reference KuhnKuhn 1996; for the Dahlhaus comparison, see Reference Dahlhaus and JostDahlhaus 1983b: 83). But there are even clearer links to Stockhausen’s writings. In the essay ‘Erfindung und Entdeckung: Ein Beitrag zur Form-Genese’, for example, Stockhausen interpreted his own compositions from the 1950s as a series of problems begetting solutions, and he illustrated this idea with nearly twenty pages of examples from his scores (Reference Schnebel and SchnebelStockhausen 1963b). Because Stockhausen was an exact contemporary of Dahlhaus and perhaps the most influential serial composer and theorist in West Germany in the 1950s and 1960s, it seems likely that Dahlhaus was influenced, at least in part, by his writings.
Dahlhaus argued that the second element in his theory of the experiment, the ‘problem-history’ of composition, led to the third element of his theory, the idea of a musical work as a ‘work-in-progress’. The ‘work-in-progress’, he claimed, had great relevance to the history of music aesthetics, for it represented a counter-concept to the nineteenth-century ideal of a closed musical work: when new compositions were conceived primarily as solutions to problems posed by earlier compositions, no individual piece formed a closed whole but was only an incomplete part of a larger series of works. This idea of a ‘work-in-progress’ also can be linked to the writings of post-war serial composers. In this case, it is again Stockhausen who wrote in the early 1950s of the need to overturn the older ideal of a closed, perfected work in favour of something that would stand as a small part of a larger process (see Reference Stockhausen and SchnebelStockhausen 1963a; Reference Schnebel and SchnebelStockhausen 1963i). Later in that decade, Ligeti made similar statements: in his well-known analysis of Boulez’s Structure Ia, he described composing as a kind of research and experimentation that surrendered the claim to produce great works, and he argued that all composers must think this way if they hope to effect progress (Reference LigetiLigeti 1958: 62–3). Dahlhaus read the writings of serial composers and interpreted them in the context of the larger history of music aesthetics. His erudition and insights about the relation between compositional theory and intellectual history make his work uniquely valuable.
Unity and Organicism
Essays about compositional theory were the primary vehicle for serial aesthetics, and extracting aesthetic content from these essays requires one to see links between descriptions of compositional techniques and the aesthetic ideals that motivated them. There was an explosion of compositional theory in the post-war period, which followed from the desire of composers to reinvent music from the ground up. And as with the twelve-tone method itself, the precedent for prolific prose-writing was Schoenberg. In his essay ‘Composition with Twelve Tones’, Schoenberg explained not only how he used the technique, but also why. ‘Form in the arts, and especially in music’, he wrote, ‘aims primarily at comprehensibility. … Composition with twelve tones has no other aim than comprehensibility’ (Reference Schoenberg and SteinSchoenberg 1975a: 215). For Schoenberg, the twelve-tone method supported the comprehensibility of his musical ideas by providing a consistency of intervallic relations and unified pitch structure that corresponded with phrasing and formal ideas. The method was therefore essentially connected to his decisions about form, and the basic set created a unifying force that reflected an organicist ideal of composition.
Post-war composers shared this organicist ideal, but, strangely, they criticised Schoenberg for not going far enough with it. Boulez led the charge, claiming that Schoenberg ‘took no trouble to find specifically serial structures’ in his music and ‘never concerned himself with the logical connection between serial forms as such and derived structure’ (Reference Boulez and ThéveninBoulez 1991f: 213). Boulez overlooked Schoenberg’s insistence that ‘the possibilities of evolving the formal elements of music … out of a basic set are unlimited’ and ploughed ahead with his own programme (Reference Schoenberg and SteinSchoenberg 1975a: 222). That programme was, he wrote, to generate ‘structure from material’ by ‘generaliz[ing] the serial principle to the four constituents of sound: pitch, duration, dynamics/attack, and timbre’ (Reference Boulez and ThéveninBoulez 1991f: 214). The results of Boulez’s organicist ideal took shape in his Structure Ia.
Stockhausen also wrote, with an insistence that bordered on fanaticism, of the need to compose according to a unifying principle, and he repeatedly demanded ‘consistency’ between individual elements and the totality. In sentence after sentence of a technical essay on early serialism, ‘Situation des Handwerks (Kriterien der punktuellen Musik)’, he called for the ‘subordination of tones under a unifying principle’, for ‘consistency between the ordering of the individual elements and the whole’, for a ‘unified conception of music, which only a unified material ordering can create’, for ‘the constant presence of the unifying idea’, and for ‘the necessity of total order’ (Reference Schnebel and SchnebelStockhausen 1963e). The language here is striking given that Hitler had just inflicted a period of ‘total order’ on Europe. It is a language echoed in Boulez’s statement that his intention with Structure Ia was to create a synthesis of elements that ‘would not be marred from the start by foreign bodies’ (Boulez, quoted in Reference ToopToop 1974: 144). The ‘foreign bodies’ were the remnants of the tonal tradition he detected in Schoenberg’s work, and like many others, he believed a more robust organicism would allow composers to move forward. This belief extended far beyond Boulez and Stockhausen and was one of the primary concerns of serialism.
Perception and Listening
As Boulez and other post-war composers expunged the ‘foreign bodies’ of tonality from their music, they also abandoned a syntax that was familiar to listeners. Schoenberg and his students claimed that traditional syntax was not so much abandoned as made ‘more efficient’. But in both cases, and seemingly with all serial music, new demands are made upon the listener. In Schoenberg’s music, traditional syntax struggles to compensate for the novelty of the new pitch structure. In the music of Boulez and other post-war composers, conventions of both syntax and pitch are effectively abolished and replaced by a new idea of what music and listening can be. Comparing one of Schoenberg’s early twelve-tone pieces, such as the Intermezzo from his Suite for Piano op. 25, with Boulez’s early serial piece, Structure Ia, provides a good example of this: immediately apparent is a difference in the textural conception of the pieces. Whereas in Schoenberg the hierarchy of parts common to tonal music since the classical era persists, in Boulez there is no such hierarchy, no distinction between primary and subsidiary voices or melody and accompaniment. The texture is characterised instead by a scattering of ‘points’ across sound-space, which helps makes sense of why such music was described as ‘pointillistic’ at the time. Additionally, the sound environment of Structure Ia is static rather than dynamic or goal-oriented; this is an intended result caused by the obliteration of metre, lack of registral focus, and unchanging loudness and articulation – to say nothing of pitch.
The new demands serialism placed upon listeners were noted repeatedly by Babbitt in the essay by him cited above. He argued that because serial composers could determine musical events with greater precision, listeners needed to listen with greater precision in order to correctly perceive the music (cf. Reference BabbittBabbitt 1958). This may be true in the case of Babbitt’s music, but there are many other ways of listening to serial music, just as there are many other serial composers. What is appropriate for one is not necessarily appropriate for all.
Stockhausen can serve as a useful counterexample to Babbitt, for he also wrote specifically about how to listen to new music but took a very different position. Stockhausen argued that listeners could approach music with a spirit of ‘invention’ and a spirit of ‘discovery’. To apply ‘invention’ to listening is to actively devise form for music, to respond creatively to what is heard and give it structure. The essential point is that there need not be one form that is identified by all listeners; rather, the same music can generate different formal ideas in different listeners. This approach suggests a departure from the conventional practice of listening, in which known formal parts are identified similarly by different listeners. What is more important for Stockhausen is that each listener perceive the music personally and creatively. ‘Discovery’ in listening, on the other hand, does not allow for this creative engagement with form but urges listeners to accept forms that are unusual and unfamiliar. For Stockhausen, new musical ‘discoveries’ require listeners to accept and devote attention to that which is unconventional. He was critical of listeners who were intolerant of unfamiliar structures, and he deemed them poor discoverers (see Reference Schnebel and SchnebelStockhausen 1963b: 226–7; cf. Reference ZagorskiZagorski 2018).
If one considers the hostility with which serial and post-serial music has been received at times (not infrequently by musicians and music scholars themselves), one can better understand this entreaty for tolerance. But the fact remains that listening to serial music has been considered difficult by the majority of those who have heard serial music. One must therefore wonder how serialism could become one of the most influential compositional techniques of the twentieth century.
The Influence of Serial Aesthetics
The influence of serialism was due in large part to the ideas behind the technique – in other words, to its aesthetics. It was, of course, music to be listened to, even when it required new kinds of listening. But more so than perhaps any other music, it was the ideas associated with serialism that contributed to its widespread practice. The themes in the aesthetics of serialism outlined in this chapter reflect the features of its influence, and behind them lie different conceptions of progress. For Schoenberg and his students, progress lay in a new method for ordering pitch that fulfilled their need for formal cohesion and seemed the culmination of hundreds of years of prior practices. For post-war composers, serialism represented the new beginning that was wanted after the period of fascism, elevated a technique the fascists condemned, and also seemed the logical consequence of earlier musical progress. During the Cold War, in both East and West, the modernism and abstraction of serial music were considered to be the polar opposite of Socialist Realism, and they lent serialism the prestige of (mostly) forbidden culture on one side of the Iron Curtain while representing the ideals of freedom and democracy on both sides. Finally, serial music’s development in the 1950s and 1960s was made possible by the science and technology that defined the era and promised unlimited creative freedom through the electronic generation of sound.
The influence of serial aesthetics can be seen also in critical reactions against it. Given the great influence of serialism, its geographical scope, variety of practices, and staying power, it has attracted countless critiques. Those critiques particularly worth mentioning are two compositional trends that fashioned themselves as antipodes to serialism, and which became two of the most influential compositional approaches since 1970: spectral music and minimalism. The ideas that motivated these approaches can be usefully contrasted with ideas that motivated serial composers.
Closing Thoughts
Despite the abundance of critiques, and because of them, serialism has been an important part of the music and aesthetics of the past hundred years. It can also contribute to a better understanding of modernism and the many cultures that participated in its ideals. Those many cultures, the long history of serialism, and the richness of its aesthetics suggest myriad ways to approach the topic. One can, for example, examine local contexts that focus on particular times, places, institutions, composers, theorists, or political conditions. Or one can combine this with broader historical interpretations linking artistic practices to the beliefs and motives that underpin human behaviour and elucidate the metanarratives we construct. These metanarratives may be out of fashion today, but they are still worth studying; the same can be said of serialism. I hope this chapter has shown that the aesthetics of serialism is an extremely rich and intellectually stimulating topic. It is also a historical fact that, whatever we may think of the music and its aesthetics, it had a tremendous influence on the twentieth century and continues to be influential in the twenty-first century. Its legacy lives on not only in its critics, but also in generations of composers who, long after the heyday of serialism in the post-war period, continue to be guided by its ideas.
What Happened When
An early account of what became known as serial composition can be traced to 1923, when the composer Josef Matthias Hauer published a text called Treatise on Twelve-Tone Technique: The Nature of Musicality (Lehrbuch der Zwölftontechnik: von Wesen des Musikalischen). A year later another important feature of musical modernism was pinpointed in a book by Herbert Eimert called Theory of Atonal Music (Atonale Musiklehre). Both titles seem to reflect a concern to promote musical characteristics that were starkly opposed to the familiar notion of tonality, of something sacred to the great masters of the past: just as ‘atonal’ implied the absolute negation of tonality, so ‘twelve-tone technique’ might appear to imply the absolute negation of tonality’s ‘seven-tone technique’, the drawing of tonally functional chords and relationships from the diatonic major or minor scales, coupled with commitment to the time-honoured distinction between consonance and dissonance.
All these technical terms – tonal, atonal, twelve-tone technique – have musical connotations that are more direct than those relating to ‘serialism’, simply because the essential concept of ‘tone’ (as reflected in dictionary definitions) is musical where that of ‘series’ is not. It is also because from the outset twelve-tone technique depended on deriving the entire compositional texture from twelve pitch classes arranged in a fixed linear sequence, and any ‘fixed linear sequence’ in tonal composition was likely to be primarily motivic or thematic in character, and not directly reproduced in other strands of the texture. Such a fundamental difference began to be explored in technical writing like Hauer’s and Eimert’s more or less at the same time as composers were beginning to write serially. But it could never be taken for granted that ‘composition with twelve tones’ was also, by definition, atonal. Twelve-tone serial composition, like other kinds of modernist and often expressionist music, might be less securely tonal than much music written before 1900. But fundamental vestiges of tonal thinking and tonal procedure stubbornly resisted all avant-garde attempts to eradicate them.
As my initial reference to Hauer shows, Arnold Schoenberg was not the only musician in the early twentieth century to have intuitions about the need for, and nature of, an organising principle that would facilitate a properly modern character for the creation of compositions fit to stand alongside the greatest achievements of the past. Nevertheless, his pre-eminence during the early years of music’s twelve-tone phase is entirely understandable, given the quality of his pre-serial works, and also his role as teacher and mentor to several of the first generation of twelve-tone composers, including Alban Berg and Anton Webern.
It was in July 1923 that Schoenberg, at the age of forty-eight, finished his first completely twelve-tone serial work, the Suite for Piano op. 25. Over the next twenty-eight years, most of the compositions he worked on were twelve-tone, and this body of music is striking, among much else, for the degree to which it compensates for his avoidance of such standard generic titles as string quartet and concerto during the fifteen years between 1908 and 1923. In the 1920s, many of Schoenberg’s pupils followed his lead, not just into twelve-tone serialism, but in aiming to demonstrate that this new method of composition was not simply an intransigent, destructive avant-garde initiative. Rather, it offered an innovative approach to texture and design that grew organically out of the increasing chromaticism and intricate motivic processes of much nineteenth-century music. Above all, it could be felt to offer invigorating discipline at a time when use of traditional procedures was difficult to distinguish from dull and derivative recycling of jaded tonal clichés.
In the 1950s, it would become a familiar claim that the twelve-tone compositions of Schoenberg and his followers were less radical, less obliquely aphoristic, than such examples of post-tonal, pre-serial expressionism as Schoenberg’s Erwartung (1909) and Pierrot lunaire (1912) or the various sets of miniatures written by Webern between 1908 and 1916. In addition, as historians have often observed, one should never underestimate the consequences of the fact that, although the basic language of music appeared to change radically between 1900 and 1930, and twelve-tone compositions were at the forefront of such changes, the nature of voices and instruments, and of the institutions that preserved and promoted serious music within society, remained much as it had been since well before 1900. It was only after the middle of the twentieth century that new ways of making sound, especially recording on tape and the subsequent transformation of analogue into digital technology, began to influence not just the dissemination of music, but compositional methods as well. Yet the result, far from turning into a complete and unrelenting rethinking of compositional principles, turned out rather to favour the kind of intensely heterogeneous range of styles and techniques that has characterised contemporary music over the past half century. The radical shifts and reshapings of the concept of serialism that can be detected during the early post-war years proved to be no more permanent or all-determining than any other innovative initiative of that time.
Serial Materials
Twelve-tone serial technique was multiple rather than singular from the beginning; it proposed basing pitch materials not simply on a single succession of all twelve semitones of the chromatic scale, but on the forty-eight such successions that become available when the principal or basic series form is transposed onto the other eleven pitch levels, and when its inversion, retrograde (reversion), and retrograde inversion are similarly transposed (see Figure 1.1). As a result, twelve-tone composition involved the constant shifting or transformation of the original twelve-tone series ordering, as various inversions and reversions of that ordering were deployed. There was nevertheless no prior expectation that a twelve-tone serial composition required the equal use of all these distinct series forms, and compositional practice soon brought another important matter to light: while equality – ensuring that the in-built pitch hierarchies of tonal scales and themes were avoided – might be a theoretical ideal, such absolute equality was difficult to achieve in practice and even more difficult to imbue with musical life. The later initiative to interpret serial multiplicity as applying the other elements beside pitch, as demonstrated with special consistency and resourcefulness by Milton Babbitt after 1940, has been widely studied but has not so far swayed the broad currents of compositional development in its direction. What amounts with Babbitt to a highly specialised kind of atonal athematicism remains a rarely acquired taste, and a rarely followed model.
In the formative years of pitch serialism, the 1920s and 1930s, using several ordered series forms at once, or combining vertical with linear presentations of series segments, also meant that there could be a considerable difference between the ordered successions of series forms visible in a printed collection of set tables or matrices and the pitch materials sounding in the actual score. With this fundamental distinction between theory and practice, twelve-tone serialism became a liberating rather than constraining principle; so (for Schoenberg in particular) the most immediate result of the method’s formulation was to make it possible to conceive and complete works on a larger scale than he had managed between 1909 and 1923. Serial technique could be employed for vocal as well as instrumental music, for opera or oratorio as well as for Lieder and other smaller-scale texted pieces. Indeed, serial music was no more inherently anti-lyrical than it was anti-classical. At the same time, however, it could share with the other strands of musical modernism during the years between 1920 and 1950 an openness to expressionistic, late Romantic, and neoclassical expressive tendencies.
As noted earlier, twelve-tone serialism appeared by definition to be ‘anti-tonal’, requiring ‘total’ chromaticism and therefore the complete and unambiguous absence of consonant diatonicism. But just as the attraction of dividing the twelve notes up into smaller groups of six, four, or three to bring out possible thematic/motivic similarities between these subgroups soon became a common procedure for early serial compositions, so did approaches to harmony and counterpoint that stopped short of incontrovertible atonality. While the more folkloric melodic qualities found in the music of Janáček, Sibelius, or Vaughan Williams did not transfer naturally to serialism, it was perfectly possible to use a folk-like melody as the source for a set of twelve-tone variations on a simple tonal theme, as a movement from Schoenberg’s Suite op. 29 (1924–6) showed (cf. Reference WhittallWhittall 2008: 58–60). No less prescient, for the longer-term evolutionary history of serialism, was Alban Berg’s quotation of a Styrian folk tune in the final stages of his Violin Concerto (1935), making audible the link between the tune’s artless diatonicism and the triadic interval-content of the work’s twelve-tone series without attempting to contrive a literal, unifying process of connection between folk tune and series form. Even more startling was Berg’s incorporation of a complete chorale, ‘Es ist genug’, as harmonised by J. S. Bach, in the concerto’s finale. The first four notes of the chorale melody – the whole-tone ascent B♭, C, D, E – formed the last four notes of the work’s twelve-tone series. But the music makes abundantly clear that, as an exemplary modernist, Berg was more interested in the poignant disparity between Bach’s original and his own twelve-tone fantasia on and around that original than he was in contriving an ideally integrated synthesis between the two.
Describing Serial Designs
Between 1945 and 1951, only the ageing, ailing Schoenberg survived from the original twelve-tone triumvirate, and to the end he remained as reluctant to contrive verbal justifications for his compositional decisions as he was to teach the ‘rules’ of serialism to his students. He was never likely to provide a triumphalist slice of autobiography, recalling the euphoria of the early 1920s when he moved so quickly from demonstrating the new method’s ability to transform traditional small-scale dance forms in the Suite op. 25 to the fully symphonic scale of its immediate successor, the Wind Quintet op. 26 (1923–4), and then advancing further within the next four years not only to the elaborate orchestral textures of the Variations for Orchestra (1926–8) but also to making plans for very different operas – the mildly comic Von heute auf morgen (1928–9), the weightily tragic Moses und Aron (1930–2). Euphoria might also account for Schoenberg’s confidence that the works he found so rewarding to conceive and complete would also excite audiences, that the urgent expressiveness consequent on transforming abstract serial materials into living sound would reinvigorate a musical world in serious danger of being lulled into apathy by what he saw as Stravinsky’s effete neoclassicism, reaching its nadir in diversions with titles such as The Fairy’s Kiss (1928/50) and The Card Game (1936–37).
Such concerns may explain the sense of urgency with which Schoenberg sought to move beyond the satisfying but restricted and not exactly un-neoclassical scope of that first completely twelve-tone composition, the Suite for Piano op. 25. There, the explicit associations between his own movement titles and textures and the movement titles and textures of Bach’s keyboard suites seemed specifically intended to help performers and listeners comprehend this music as music, irrespective of its purely technical innovations. A Schoenberg twelve-tone canon would be more dissonant than a Bach canon, a Schoenberg Musette would have a rather different relation between a repeated pitch or interval in the bass and what sounded above it to a Bach Musette, but there could be a fundamental and audible identity between the textures and styles of twelve-tone and tonality-based forms. And despite the occasional tendency of critics to disparage Schoenberg’s initiative as merely presenting ‘wrong-note’ versions of something that, in Bach, sounds both natural and right from beginning to end, Schoenberg persisted in his conviction that what serialism made possible was not a distortion of tradition but a valuable and inspiring transformation of tradition, a much-needed reinvigoration of an increasingly moribund musical language.
Reluctant though Schoenberg was to theorise verbally about things best left, in his view, to the aesthetic discrimination of the listening mind, his 1941 essay, ‘Composition with Twelve Tones’, discussed aspects of his first large-scale serial piece, the Wind Quintet op. 26 in ways that transparently build bridges between serial techniques and pre-serial formal and harmonic characteristics, such as modulation: ‘while a piece usually begins with the basic set itself, the mirror forms and other derivatives, such as the eleven transpositions of all the four basic forms, are applied only later; the transpositions, like the modulations in former styles, serve to build subordinate ideas’ (Reference Schoenberg and SteinSchoenberg 1975a: 227). As the essay’s accompanying music examples show, it was easy enough to see how the relevant series forms, represented as successions of integers or letter names, translated into the pitches of a polyphonic texture clearly stratified between melody and accompaniment. A decade earlier, Anton Webern had risked an even simpler and more direct explanation of similarities and differences between old and new musics. First, difference was focused on the extent to which traditional terminology, predicated on the hierarchic characters of the tonal system, no longer applied: ‘considerations of symmetry, regularity are now to the fore, as against the emphasis formerly laid on the principal intervals – dominant, subdominant, mediant, etc. For this reason the middle of the octave – the diminished fifth – is now important.’ Then came similarity: ‘for the rest one works as before. The original form and pitch of the row occupy a position akin to that of the “main key” in earlier music, the recapitulation will naturally return to it. We end in the same key! The analogy with earlier formal construction is quite consciously fostered: here we find the path that will lead us again to extended forms’ (Reference Webern and ReichWebern 1963: 54).
There have been many objections to Webern’s breezy and artlessly oversimplifying assurances down the years, especially to his claim that the diminished fifth – despite lacking the foundational acoustic functions of those ‘principal intervals’ in the well-tempered harmonic series – could nevertheless have a comparable structural importance. But his basic instinct, to emphasise that a degree of ‘invariance’ – recurrences leading to the perception that some elements in the music are structurally more important than others – mattered in twelve-tone serial music as much as they did in tonal compositions. In both cases, comprehension by ear and mind was the result of musical thinking that was, in essence, hierarchic.
Nevertheless, by 1931–2, when Webern made these comments, he had already shown in his String Trio op. 20 (1927), Symphony op. 21 (1927–8), and Quartet op. 22 (1928–30) how difficult it was for highly contrapuntal instrumental compositions using the twelve-tone method to be heard in exactly the same way as compositions with key signatures and bass lines emphasising chordal roots and key notes. And whereas Schoenberg’s serial textures unusually involved thematic materials shaped melodically, so that developmental transformations and varied repetitions or recapitulations could still, with practice, be aurally distinguished from each other, Webern’s much more concentrated motivic tapestries had a consistency whose potential for aural recognition involved a sense of constant focus around a few basic intervals, like the semitone and major third (and their compounds) in the first movement of the Concerto for Nine Instruments op. 24 (1931–4). Begun around the time of the lecture just quoted, the op. 24 Concerto could have been specifically designed to demonstrate how a serial composition could be coherent even if analogies ‘with earlier formal constructions’ dependent on the concept of ‘key’ are more metaphorical than literal. The earlier formal feature that remains present in Webern is the motive, the brief cell of pitches and intervals whose ‘developing variation’ proved crucial to the music’s ability to communicate a tightly organised thematic discourse whose emphasis on easily audible motivic invariants compensated for the absence of prolonged tonal functioning (cf. Reference Schoenberg, Carpenter and NeffSchoenberg 1995: 365).
‘Developing variation’ was a concept that Schoenberg-the-teacher deduced from the practice of tonal composers from (at least) Bach to Brahms, and it was flexible enough to fit Webern’s short motivic cells as well as Schoenberg’s own more expansively melodic ideas. It also provided the best guarantee that a serial composition would have a distinctive and engaging musical character, a ‘personality’ that might be in constant evolution but could convey a coherent and connected narrative, however much contrast and divergence might occur along the way. A case can be made for the argument that, from the 1970s onwards, developing variation of recognisable motivic elements, as found in Webern and Berg as well as Schoenberg, proved to be the principal legacy of earlier serial practice to continue within the diverse procedures of late modernism. However, for the Babbitts and Boulezs of the years in the immediate aftermath of their exposure to twelve-tone music’s initial phase, developing variation was little more than evidence of neoclassical nostalgia, the desire to write old music in a different way rather than truly new music.
Method, System, Meanings
By the mid-1940s – obviously a time of seismic upheaval on the world stage – the possibility of serialising musical features such as duration, dynamic level, registral position, and mode of articulation were being explored not only by Milton Babbitt in the United States but also by Olivier Messiaen in France. Both believed that it was a positive step forward to extend the concept of serial multiplicity represented by the forty-eight possible versions of twelve-tone pitch-class series forms, as one way of achieving greater distance from what seemed to some the frankly regressive qualities of Berg’s Violin Concerto or Schoenberg’s Ode to Napoleon (1942). In his short piano piece, ‘Mode de valeurs et d’intensités’, Messiaen used three twelve-tone sequences (treated as unordered collections, or modes, rather than fixed series forms) projected with different (shorter) series of durations, dynamics, and articulation.
Messiaen worked on the piece during his visit to the Darmstadt New Music Courses in 1949, and Martin Iddon has provided a detailed study of that institution during the years when several younger composers and pupils of Messiaen, including Pierre Boulez, Michel Fano, Karel Goeyvaerts, and Karlheinz Stockhausen, tried out different ways of working with kinds of multiple serialism involving stricter ordering principles than Messiaen had employed (Reference IddonIddon 2013). While these composers knew enough of Berg and Schoenberg to conclude that both had compromised the serial principle rather than developing its true potential, it was with Webern, as they gradually grew more familiar with scores not widely available in published form until the 1950s, that a genuinely inspiring ‘path to the new music’ was revealed. For Boulez, in particular, Webern’s shunning of expressionistic flamboyance in his twelve-tone works, coupled with the avoidance of traditional harmonic allusions and (in certain contexts) strict control of relations between pitch, duration, dynamic, and register, was sufficient compensation for his retention of clearly defined motivic materials that could obey the precepts of Schoenberg’s model for compositional coherence rooted in the developing variation of such motives.
In the second half of the 1940s, when he was in his early twenties, Pierre Boulez had written music that was not exactly anti-Schoenbergian or anti-Bergian in its allusions to sonata and other traditional forms and in its explosively expressionistic tone of voice. But by 1950, it would seem to Boulez and others that victory in the hard-fought battles of early modernism, which had seen diatonic tonality overthrown and thematicism itself called into question, had been betrayed by a failure of will, or imagination, on the part of the victors-turned-law-givers, with their serial sonatas, symphonies, and concertos. There is therefore a neat equivalence between the critical claim that the first phase of twelve-tone composition was insufficiently alive to the innovative potential of serialism as a principle to transform the character of compositional invention, and the no less familiar critical claim that the integral or multiple serialism represented by works like Stockhausen’s Kreuzspiel (1951) or Boulez’s Structure Ia (1951–2) imposed such elaborate mechanisms on composing that it deprived music of those communicative essentials that had sustained it during many centuries of continuous stylistic and technical evolution up to the present.
Opinion remains divided as to whether, from the 1970s onwards, Boulez and his contemporaries retreated into techniques closer to those of the original pitch-only serialists, or whether they advanced into a newly flexible kind of serial thinking that was nevertheless still more systematic in principle than that of the inter-war pioneers. Many composers were impressed by Stravinsky’s boldness, during the 1950s, in transforming himself into the inheritor of a serialism inspired primarily by Webern’s intense austerity yet finding a new degree of flexibility in building matrices of series forms on the principle of transformational rotation rather than simply transposition. This was a kind of multiplicity that Boulez would adopt after 1970, as Stravinsky’s own career was coming to an end.
As seen earlier, Stravinsky had been nothing if not critical of both Schoenberg and Berg during his earlier neoclassical years, but knowledge of and enthusiasm for Webern, facilitated by the performances of his assistant Robert Craft, made possible the kind of commitment to twelve-tone thinking shown in one of his earliest reported exchanges with Craft, first published in 1959.
RC: Do you think that the masterpieces of the next decade will be composed in serial technique?
IS: Nothing is likely about masterpieces, least of all whether there will be any. Nevertheless, a masterpiece is more likely to happen to the composer with the most highly developed language. This language is serial at present and though our contemporary development of it could be tangential to an evolution we do not yet see, this doesn’t matter. Its resources have enlarged the present language and changed our perspective on it. Developments in language are not abandoned, and the composer who fails to take account of them may lose the mainstream. Masterpieces aside, it seems to me the new music will be serial.
Stravinsky and Craft doubtless had the recent serial ‘masterpieces’ of the 1950s in mind here – they mention Boulez’s Le Marteau sans maître (1953–5) and Stockhausen’s Gruppen (1955–7). Today, such works are probably best thought of as signalling the transition from the purest possible multiple serialism to something more like ‘post-serialism’ – music which both acknowledged and countered serial thinking, just as post-tonal music was both acknowledging and countering the rich heritage of tonality. The decade from 1956 to 1966, which marked Stravinsky’s own most productive engagement with serialism, saw Boulez and Stockhausen loosening serial strictness further in response to new initiatives in electronics and Cageian experimentalism. Thereafter the inevitable serial polarity between ordered and ‘unordered’ elements would contribute to a phase of late modernism notable for its independence of Schoenbergian alignments with classical forms and textures.
For Babbitt, Schoenberg’s retrograde stylistic tendencies in his twelve-tone compositions mattered far less than his distinctive structuring method of combining pairs of transpositionally related twelve-tone series forms (most commonly P0/I5 – the Piano Piece op. 33a being a ‘textbook’ instance) in which each of the superimposed hexachords contained six different pitch classes, laid stimulating foundations for the aggregate constructions and other refinements of Babbitt’s serial practice (cf. Reference Babbitt, Dembski and StrausBabbitt 1987b: 63–84). For Boulez and his European colleagues, it was Webern’s pointillistic foreshadowing of a kind of serialism in which individual pitches were given fixed registral positions and unique dynamics and modes of articulation, then disposed symmetrically above and below a central axis, as shown in the second movement of the Variations for Piano op. 27, that suggested the best way forward, into a new world in which the serial principle was all-pervasive, all-determining, and ‘composing as before’ was anathema.
With the caustic confidence of youth, Pierre Boulez accused the recently deceased Schoenberg of a desire ‘to reconstitute tonal language within the dodecaphonic system. Witness the Ode to Napoleon, whose feebleness of thought and poverty of execution are completely typical’ (Reference Boulez and ThéveninBoulez 1991h: 199). To listen today to the opening of Boulez’s Structure Ia for two pianos (1951–2) is to encounter pure musical intransigence: atonal, athematic, expressionistically assertive as it strides boldly across its predetermined space, the two instruments sharing in a fractured yet interdependent discourse, the sustained contrast between their initial dynamic extremes an early indication that divergence, resistance to integration, was central to the music’s avant-garde aesthetic. This music embodied a no less intransigent critique of Boulez’s principal teacher Messiaen, since it adopted one of the twelve-tone modes of ‘Mode de valeurs et d’intensités’ only to subject it to far more systematically ordered serial treatment than Messiaen himself had employed. For Boulez a ‘yawning chasm had opened up’ between the infrastructure of tonality and a ‘language whose organisational principles are as yet dimly perceived’ (Reference Boulez and ThéveninBoulez 1991f: 212). The problem for the would-be systematic, multiple (or integral) serialists would prove to be that ‘organisational principles’ in which not just pitch but as many different parameters of the music as possible were subject to serialisation would remain ‘dimly perceived’, and soon come to seem even less appealing, even less convincing, than what Schoenberg and Webern had offered.
Boulez would remain committed to the belief that serialism represented ‘a complete reaction against classical thought’; that ‘classical tonal thought is based on a universe defined by gravity and attraction, serial thought on a universe in continuous expansion’ (Reference Boulez and ThéveninBoulez 1991c: 236). Nevertheless, this polarity would be tempered by conceding the fundamental need for compositions to communicate, and therefore to contain ‘recognisable musical objects’, a ‘new thematicism’ that amounted to a retreat from avant-garde extremism to modernist moderation (cf. Reference GoldmanGoldman 2011: 56–79; Reference WhittallWhittall 2008: 203–9). Only on the rare occasions when integral serial composers chose highly emotive subject matter rather than purely structural processes as their material might such a composition manage to attract an audience beyond the intrepid devotees of the most demanding kind of new music – Luigi Nono’s Il canto sospeso (1955–6), with its eloquent treatment of texts from martyrs of the wartime Italian resistance, is a telling instance. In practice, therefore, the grandly comprehensive matrices or magic squares of mutually interdependent lines of up to twelve integers, whose numbers could be translated into ordered sets of different durations, dynamics, and modes of attack as well as pitch classes, tended to move further into the background of compositional process and decision-making – a source from which appropriate selections might be made rather than an inviolable and all-determining grid imposing its rigorous discipline on all aspects of the musical material, and on the resulting listening experience.
Critics and Composers
As an activity applicable to musical composition, criticism has a much longer history than serialism, implying as it does a considered, written response to composers and their works. Critical criteria are notoriously elusive, rooted in feelings and psychological predispositions as much as in consciously crafted intellectual convictions. Even the greatest composers have their detractors, although with the likes of Bach and Beethoven these will be a tiny minority, and for the majority who approve, the ‘end’ of compositional effect is likely to be of more immediate concern than the ‘means’ of compositional technique or method, despite the ease with which both qualities can be brought together under the capacious heading of ‘style’.
By the time of twelve-tone serialism’s compositional advent, barely a century ago, musicology had become an accepted, institutionalised scholarly discipline, and a cluster of concepts, both technical and historical, had emerged to provide a possible framework for collective viewpoints about how musical works and their materials might be defined and categorised. By 1920, terms like ‘sonata’ and ‘rondo’, ‘consonant’ and ‘dissonant’, ‘tonality’ and ‘atonality’, ‘classical’ and ‘modern(ist)’ were all available to be argued over, and between about 1920 and the end of the ‘long’ twentieth century – 2005, in my reckoning – a vast number of writers on music were bold or incautious enough to include the very recent past in their historical surveys, or even to focus their interpretative work entirely on the most recent years.
The year 2005 saw the publication of Richard Taruskin’s monumental one-man, six-volume history of Western art music, and serialism takes its not especially prominent place there in the panoply of descriptive terms against which the author’s critical responses to centuries of musical activity are projected. Unlike those critics and historians between 1920 and 1960 who attempted to get the measure of twelve-tone technique in its early years, Taruskin could take a longer view, and that required placing aesthetic and technical constructs like modernism and serialism in the political and cultural contexts contemporary with them. For example, writing of Webern, Taruskin characterises his twelve-tone works as ‘dehumanized’ and ‘impersonal’, exuding ‘the atmosphere of a solitary alpine peak’, and declaring that
it is not hard to connect Webern’s artistic vision, in the context of the turbulent 1930s, with the Utopian or Arcadian (futuristic or nostalgic) cravings that dominated European social and political thought. … Webern’s musical Utopias, the most orderly and disciplined worlds of music ever to have been conceived or realized by that time, seem in their tidy beauty of conception and their ruthlessly exacting realization to broach a theme that was on the mind of every artist then alive – ominous to some, inspiring to others – of art and totalitarianism.
With Webern, whose sympathy with right-wing political ideas paralleled his conservative Roman Catholic religious beliefs, it is perfectly legitimate to indicate how it might be possible to react to a perceived conjunction between life and (twelve-tone) work in the way Taruskin does. But with Schoenberg, who switched from his inherited Judaism to Christianity and back again during a lifetime in which he was forced to leave Europe for America, and for whom the conjunction of religion and politics was inevitably more fraught that was the case with the unpersecuted Webern, it is more difficult to presume the validity of claims about serialism’s fetishising of strict, even repressive ‘laws’. Might not Schoenberg’s intransigent notions about politics and society after the founding of Israel and his response to invitations to move to that country in the late 1940s reflect the bruising experiences of himself and his family as victims of fascist antisemitism? Early twenty-first-century musicology has not always been willing to allow for this possibility; for instance, Klára Móricz – with clear echoes of Taruskin’s claims about connections between serialism and totalitarianism – has been explicit in arguing that Schoenberg’s apparent enthusiasm, late in life, for the newly founded state of Israel cannot be separated from the long-standing authoritarian tendencies of his personal political agenda: ‘Schoenberg’s stubborn, self-righteous political rhetoric overshadows his quasi-religious images and thus creates an unpleasant association between his psalms [that is, his final vocal compositions] and the ruthless political utopias of the twentieth century. … Schoenberg had a strong dislike for “democracy”’, and, as ‘a true utopian … considered any hint of disunity unacceptable’ (Reference MóriczMóricz 2008: 208 and 212).
As I have argued elsewhere, Móricz’s line of reasoning risks undervaluing the modernist ambiguities and centrifugal tendencies in Schoenberg’s twelve-tone compositions, or even of erasing their significance in pursuit of political and religious point-scoring (Reference WhittallWhittall 2016). Nevertheless, the occurrence in recent years of such far-reaching critiques of Schoenberg and the serial principle, long after the technique itself had ceased to be used either with the relative strictness and comprehensiveness of its first phase or with the short-lived intensification of serial mechanics that immediately followed it, underlines the ambivalence and scepticism that have affected assessment of serial initiatives from the beginning. The suspicion that the true serialist is an unrealistic Utopian, obsessed with unity at all costs, and attaching more significance to what can be read on the page (in notes as well as words) than to what can be heard, has often been aired, but it always needs to be approached with proper critical caution.
Teaching the Tone Row
The first century of serial composition, and of critical-historical writing about serial music, has also been a time of burgeoning composition pedagogy. Schoenberg believed that students should focus on techniques deducible from the classic compositions of tonal tradition; there was no question of him providing instruction in the twelve-tone method, even though in the 1920s he claimed to believe that the method would guarantee the supremacy of German music for the next century. (He might have done better with the vaguer suggestion that music to which serial principles makes fundamental contributions would dominate the next century.) But guides to twelve-tone compositional technique, often alongside analytical demonstrations of serial practice in short examples from Schoenberg and others, were not long in coming, and by the 1940s composer-teachers like Ernst Krenek, René Leibowitz, and Herbert Eimert were producing self-help introductions and manuals which achieved wide circulation (Reference KrenekKrenek 1943; Reference LeibowitzLeibowitz 1947; Reference EimertEimert 1950). A little later, in 1966, Reginald Smith Brindle’s Serial Composition was aimed no less directly at students. This copiously illustrated textbook came complete with exercises, and serialism’s forty-year history was represented, in a text dedicated ‘to my friend Luigi Dallapiccola’, by examples ranging from the first generation of Schoenberg, Berg, and Webern to the post-war triumvirate of Boulez, Stockhausen, and Nono (Reference Smith BrindleSmith Brindle 1966).
Smith Brindle’s references to real music, as well as to specially constructed examples of his own, acknowledged the increasing trend, by the mid-1960s, for critical discussions of serialism to concentrate on the historical process by way of analysis of extracts selected for specific scholarly purposes. In this respect, the American composer and academic George Perle’s Serial Composition and Atonality was particularly significant (Reference PerlePerle 1963), with its emphasis on serialism’s emergence from what Perle termed ‘“free” atonality’, the scare quotes around ‘free’ signalling that, in all instances of ‘post-tonal music’, ‘freedom’ was best conceived in terms of relations between collections of pitch classes grouped not so much according to their places within the many millions of different twelve-tone series forms, but within the 200 or so pitch-class sets obeying a strict and uniform ordering principle analogous, as Milton Babbitt was one of the first composer-theorists to point out, to the mathematical concept of set theory. With the publication in 1973 of the first book-length introduction to pitch-class set theory (Reference ForteForte 1973), the play between set and series, in music that might have little or nothing to do with ‘orthodox’ twelve-tone technique, introduced the more varied approaches to both compositional process and theoretical enquiry around and beyond serialism characteristic of the years since 1980. It is particularly appropriate, therefore, that around 1973 and 1974, the centenary of Schoenberg’s birth provided a platform for musings about the status of serialism in its assumed context of atonality and modernist formal discontinuities – serialism as something uneasily poised between respect for transformed tradition and principled rejection of outdated and oppressive hierarchies.
A Critical Centenary
In October and November 1973, the London Sinfonietta presented a series of twenty-six concerts, twelve in London, containing ‘the complete chamber music of Arnold Schoenberg and Roberto Gerhard’. Gerhard, a Schoenberg pupil and twelve-tone composer long resident in England, had died in 1970, and the sense of a double commemoration was reflected in the substantial programme book that accompanied the series. Among the essays included was Hans Keller’s ‘Schoenberg and the Crisis of Communication’, which among other things acted as a reminder that it was still possible, around that time, to believe that atonality and serialism might and perhaps should consign the extended tonality of Britten and Shostakovich (both very near the end of their careers in 1973) further to the margins. Maybe there are elements of such thinking in Keller’s portrayal of Schoenberg as ‘musical history’s most tragic figure – its most uncompromising clarifier and its leading confuser at the same time’. Keller wrote that ‘it must have been shortly after the fourth string quartet [of 1936] that the shock of atonality was at last totally assimilated, that twelve-note technique had become as instinctive to Schoenberg as tonal language had been’ (Reference Keller and AthertonKeller 1973). But what Keller does not say here is that the now ‘instinctive’ twelve-note music had not become incontrovertibly atonal: the fourth quartet has become a favoured example for music theorists attempting to demonstrate how that notoriously elusive Schoenbergian concept of ‘suspended tonality’ might have been manifesting itself in his twelve-tone works (cf. Reference WhittallWhittall 2008: 110–11). Even Jack Boss, whose recent pair of books about Schoenberg fight a resourceful rearguard action in support of ‘atonal’ as a viable technical concept, has written of the first movement of the fourth quartet that ‘D minor and B flat major serve as tonal-reference surrogates for the two principal motives of the piece’ (Reference BossBoss 2014: 328).
This circumstance lends even more force to Keller’s claim that ‘the ensuing, continued history of tonality’ – between 1936 and 1973, that is – ‘proved that Schoenberg had come too soon’, thereby contributing decisively to ‘the current crisis of communication’ which, Keller says, ‘is not merely, not even chiefly, produced by one musical language having split into several. The one language has also, over a considerable part of the contemporary scene, evaporated into none’ (Reference Keller and AthertonKeller 1973: 48). In clarifying Schoenberg’s persistent duality so cogently, Keller identified the cultural quality of a modernity, centred on serialism, that appeared to have better chances of productive survival if old and new were encouraged to converge, or at least coexist. This meant that Schoenberg and especially Berg provided more promising signals for the future of composition than Webern and the various followers of Webern who constituted the atonal-serial avant-garde of the 1950s and 1960s. Schoenberg and Berg could still provide technical stimulus to much later composers even if serialism and atonality as originally understood, have tended to merge with various alternatives – minimalism, spectralism, and working with interval cycles among them. In the musical world of the 2020s, where late modernism and post-modernism enact an uneasy but productive coexistence, there is still a sense of serial or set-based thinking as a useful component of compositional initiatives whose multivalence by no means ensures a sense of diluted progressiveness in its most prominent exemplars (cf. Reference WhittallWhittall 2019).
The American George Rochberg, a near-contemporary of Hans Keller, is a particularly striking example of a composer who seemed to fall foul of what Keller diagnosed as Schoenberg’s premature attempt to rethink the foundations of musical expression. Rochberg certainly cannot be accused of not taking serialism seriously. He emerged – traumatised, according to one recent narrative, from combat in the Second World War – in search of stylistic security and stability, and his diaries and other writings vividly trace the twists and turns of the consequent quest. Directly linking his life experiences with his compositional methods, Rochberg declared that
one of the most prominent impulses toward twelve-tone serialism … was my reaction to my war experience. The darkness of that whole experience really has rooted itself. … I need to find a language with which I could say what I experienced, but obviously refracted, not brutalized by the nature of the experience itself. I had to make damn sure that what I composed … would be as beautiful as I could make it.
In 1952, the year after Schoenberg’s death, Rochberg, at the age of thirty-four, responded ecstatically to a first hearing of the String Trio – ‘one wonders if this were written by a man or by an angel. Such a work reminds us that music is still a human art’ – and lauded the ‘new visions’ that would surely come from recognising that ‘it is past the time for tonality’ (Reference WlodarskiWlodarski 2019: 50). Rochberg’s contacts with Dallapiccola, composer of Il prigioniero (1944–48), around this time clearly reinforced his convictions about the compassionate humanistic essence of using twelve-tone methods to control and direct a highly expressionistic emotional intensity, cogently confronting trauma rather than simply succumbing to its destructive force. But by the early 1960s, Rochberg was reacting negatively to what he now termed the ‘“overwrought, expressionistic emotional palette” of Schoenberg’s fourth quartet (1936). … “The music sounded ugly and unbeautiful to my ears”’ (Reference WlodarskiWlodarski 2019: 50), and Rochberg would soon find a very different kind of expressiveness in the imitative evocations of Beethoven and Mahler that pervaded his later compositions.
Few today would rank Rochberg among the leading figures of later twentieth-century composition, but his turn against expressionism, and his need to musically embody consolation rather than melancholia, were fundamental within the aesthetic and expressive divergences that came to dominate the decades after 1960. Rochberg had no time for what he considered the arrant academicism of post-tonal theorists like George Perle. But it would be simplistic as well as insensitive to characterise Rochberg’s flight into the consolatory as escapist. Many other composers whose early experiences matched Rochberg’s to some extent were also likely to aspire to something transcendent, even if they continued to question it rather than embrace it wholeheartedly, thereby allowing some kind of residual sadness and insecurity to survive within their music’s material manifestation.
Judgements in Perspective
In my Introduction to Serialism, written mainly between 2006 and 2008, I was clearly not disposed to concede that the serial principle has gone the way that diatonic tonality appeared to have gone between 1920 and 1960, becoming marginalised, a refuge only for unimaginative conservatives refusing to move with the times. Transformation rather than entropy was not merely serialism’s strategy for survival. Rather, its self-renewing characteristics were the positive, practical consequence of the implicit and explicit critiques that had attended its invention and early evolution. As a result, post-tonal serialism, like tonality, takes its place as a compositional principle eternally available for access and adaptation as composers see fit. Serialism owes its own particular strengths to the critique of tonality and diatonic harmony that brought it into being, and which it has so far completely failed to erase from contemporary super-pluralistic musical consciousness. This paradox is the essence of serialism’s power, and serialism was at its most potent between 1920 and 1970.