Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-kw2vx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T06:29:58.990Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Entitlement, Epistemic Risk, and Scepticism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 August 2019

Luca Moretti*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Aberdeen, Scotland, UK
*
*Corresponding author. Email: l.moretti@abdn.ac.uk
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Crispin Wright maintains that the architecture of perceptual justification is such that we can acquire justification for our perceptual beliefs only if we have antecedent justification for ruling out any sceptical alternative. Wright contends that this principle doesn't elicit scepticism, for we are non-evidentially entitled to accept the negation of any sceptical alternative. Sebastiano Moruzzi has challenged Wright's contention by arguing that since our non-evidential entitlements don't remove the epistemic risk of our perceptual beliefs, they don't actually enable us to acquire justification for these beliefs. In this paper I show that Wright's responses to Moruzzi are ineffective and that Moruzzi's argument is validated by probabilistic reasoning. I also suggest that Wright couldn't answer Moruzzi's challenge without weakening the support available for his conception of the architecture of perceptual justification.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2019

1. Introduction

Some of Crispin Wright's ideas have been playing a pivotal role in recent epistemological conversation. Wright maintains that the architecture of perceptual justification is such that we can acquire justification for our perceptual beliefs only if we have antecedent justification for ruling out any sceptical alternative. He contends that this fact doesn't elicit scepticism, for we are non-evidentially entitled to accept the negation of any sceptical alternative. Sebastiano Moruzzi has challenged Wright's contention by arguing that since our non-evidential entitlements don't remove the epistemic risk of our perceptual beliefs, they don't actually enable us to acquire justification for these beliefs. In this paper I show that Wright's responses to Moruzzi are ineffective and that Moruzzi's argument is validated by probabilistic reasoning. I also suggest that Wright couldn't answer Moruzzi's challenge without weakening the support available for his conception of the architecture of perceptual justification.

This is the paper's structure: in §2 I detail Wright's conception of the architecture of perceptual justification and Wright's entitlement theory. In §3 I review Moruzzi's objection. In §4 I criticize Wright's responses to Moruzzi. In §5 I argue that Moruzzi's objection is validated by Bayesian reasoning. In §6 I draw my conclusions.

2. Wright's epistemology of perception

Wright (Reference Wright2004, Reference Wright and Nuccetelli2008, Reference Wright, Zardini and Dodd2014) contends that the architecture of perceptual justificationFootnote 1 is such that:Footnote 2

(PJ) A subject S's experience as if p gives S (defeasible) justification for believing p only if S has antecedent justification for accepting ~sh, where ~sh is the logical negation of any sceptical alternativeFootnote 3 sh to p.Footnote 4

(PJ) raises at least two concerns. To begin with, it looks at odds with everyday epistemic practices; one may thus doubt that (PJ) is true. Ordinarily, the reasons we attribute to ourselves or others for holding perceptual beliefs make no reference to sceptical alternatives. Imagine you have an experience as if the cat is on the mat. You would normally answer the question ‘What reason do you have to believe that the cat is on the mat?’ by saying ‘I see it’. Responding ‘I see it and have independent reason to rule out that I'm deceived by the Matrix’ would appear out-of-place (cf. Pryor Reference Pryor2000; McGrath Reference McGrath2013).

The second concern is that (PJ) prompts perceptual scepticism (cf. Pryor Reference Pryor2000; Schiffer Reference Schiffer2004). Consider a subject S experiencing as if (P) the cat is on the mat. Suppose SH is the proposition that P is false but the Matrix makes S hallucinate as if P.Footnote 5 The sceptic may adduce (PJ) to argue that S's experience as if P gives S justification for believing P only if S has antecedent justification for accepting ~SH. The sceptic will insist that S cannot have this antecedent justification. For any a posteriori evidence S might happen to possess can be conjectured to be in turn a hallucinatory state caused by the Matrix. Furthermore, S doesn't have a priori evidence for ~SH. So S has no evidence justifying her acceptance of ~SH. The sceptic will conclude that S's experience as if P cannot justify S's belief that P and – by generalizing this example – that S's experiences cannot justify any of S's perceptual beliefs.

To address the first concern, Wright has argued that the epistemological views that disallow (PJ), like Pryor's (Reference Pryor2000, Reference Pryor2004) dogmatism, are in various ways problematicFootnote 6 (cf. Wright Reference Wright and Nuccetelli2008). The only direct argument – and I think the most forceful case – for the truth of (PJ) is nonetheless a Bayesian one due to White (Reference White2006), who defends a view of the architecture of perceptual justification similar to Wright's. Let me outline White's argument, as I will use it later on. White adopts an entrenched model that construes epistemic justification as rational confidence. Let Pr be a probability function interpreted subjectively. Pr(p) expresses S's rational confidence that p. Pr(p|q) expresses S's rational confidence that p conditional on S's learning q. Suppose E is the proposition that S has an experience as if (P) the cat is on the mat, and SH is the proposition that P is false but the Matrix makes S hallucinate as if P. Since SH entails E, if S learns SH, S must be certain that E. Hence Pr(E|SH) = 1. Since S shouldn't expect to experience as if the cat on the mat, Pr(E) < 1. Thus Pr(E|SH) > Pr(E). This inequality implies that Pr(~SH|E) < Pr(~SH). Furthermore, since P entails ~SH, Pr(P|E) ≤ Pr(~SH|E). The last two inequalities imply by transitivity that Pr(P|E) < Pr(~SH). This formula says that if S learns E, S's confidence in P must remain strictly smaller than S's prior confidence in ~SH. Thus, S's learning E can make S rationally confident of P’s truth only if S is antecedently rationally confident of ~SH’s truth. This shows that S's experiencing as if P can give S justification for believing P only if S has antecedent justification for accepting ~SH (cf. White Reference White2006: 534). This argument can be reformulated to apply to any perceptual proposition p, any proposition e stating that S experiences as if p, and any correlated sceptical alternative sh. The conclusion is that

(PC) Pr(p|e) < Pr(~sh).

(PC) vindicates (PJ).

Although Wright often construes epistemic justification as rational confidence (see for instance 2014: 233–4), he hasn't explicitly adduced (PC) to support (PJ). Wright (Reference Wright and Nuccetelli2008: 42) has nevertheless levelled a Bayesian objection to Pryor's dogmatism consisting of a variant or incomplete version of White's argument.Footnote 7 So Wright would endorse this argument. Note that (PJ) takes S's evidence to be S's experience as if p, whereas (PC) takes S's evidence to be S's reflective belief that (e) she has an experience as if p. One could question whether S's belief that e constitutes a reliable model of S's experience as if p in epistemic evaluations (cf. Moretti Reference Moretti2015). Wright nevertheless doesn't distinguish between one's experience and one's reflective belief that one has an experience when discussing scepticism (cf. 2002, 2004, 2008, 2014). Wright seems to share White's (Reference White2006: 353) and Silins' (Reference Silins, Gendler and Hawthorne2007: 120n17) conviction that one's experiences and one's reflective beliefs about one's experiences are interchangeable in most epistemic contexts.

To address the second concern – the worry that (PJ) elicits scepticism – Wright (Reference Wright2004, Reference Wright and Nuccetelli2008, Reference Wright, Zardini and Dodd2014) admits that there is no or very little evidence in support of propositions like ~SH. Yet he argues that there exists a type of non-evidential justification – called by him entitlement – that all rational subjects possess by default for accepting the logical negation of any sceptical alternative.Footnote 8 Acceptance is an attitude more inclusive than belief. Belief entails acceptance but the reverse is false. Wright acknowledges that an entitlement to accept ~SH is not one to believe ~SH. For it is dubious that S could rationally believe a proposition with no or very little evidence for its truth (cf. Wright Reference Wright2004: 176). This thesis is widely held in epistemology nowadays (cf. Chignell Reference Chignell and Zalta2017: §5). Wright suggests that the type of acceptance licensed by S's entitlements is rational trust, or a very similar attitude (cf. Wright Reference Wright2004: 194).

Wright's thesis that we are entitled to accept propositions like ~SH has attracted criticism of various types (see McGlynn Reference McGlynn2017 for a survey). For instance, some authors contend that what Wright calls entitlement isn't epistemic justification (cf. Pritchard Reference Pritchard, Moyal-Sharrock and Brenner2005; Jenkins Reference Jenkins2007). Wright (Reference Wright, Zardini and Dodd2014) has made a good effort to address most of these objections. In the following, I concentrate on an important criticism made in discussion by Sebastiano Moruzzi (cf. Wright Reference Wright2004: 208n 26), which I think hasn't properly been addressed so far.

3. Moruzzi's objection

Moruzzi's challenge exploits a notion of epistemic risk introduced by Wright himself. Wright emphasizes that whenever S accepts a proposition p the truth of which is insufficiently supported by her evidence, S runs a risk – the one of accepting a proposition as true that is actually false. Since this type of risk is incompatible with S's justifiedly believing and knowing p, Wright calls it epistemic risk. More accurately, the relation that Wright claims to hold between epistemic risk and epistemic justification is this: S's accepting p is epistemically risky if and only if S's evidence doesn't suffice to justify her believing p. Note that S's accepting p when p is insufficiently supported by evidence would be epistemically risky even if S's acceptance were justified by an entitlement to p. This is so because this entitlement of S would not rest on or produce any evidence for p’s truth. For example, Wright (Reference Wright2004: 208–9) acknowledges that S's accepting ~SH would be epistemically risky despite S's entitlement to ~SH.

Moruzzi's objection rests on the intuition that for any p and correlated sceptical alternative sh, the epistemic risk of ~sh transmits to p. The objection says that since S's accepting ~sh is epistemically risky despite S's entitlement to ~sh, S's accepting p is also epistemically risky despite S's experiencing as if p. Consequently, S's justification for p depending on S's experience as if p (if any) cannot sustain S's belief that p. If this is true, S's entitlements might permit S to trust perceptual propositions, but they cannot enable S to believe them. The sceptical challenge invited by (PJ) would remain unanswered in this case.

4. Analysis of Wright's responses

Wright (Reference Wright2004) and Wright (Reference Wright, Zardini and Dodd2014) have respectively given Moruzzi's objection two different responses. In both papers Wright insists that no epistemic risk transmits from ~sh to p but the reasons he adduces go in opposite directions. I now criticize both responses in turn.

Wright (Reference Wright2004: 207–9) argues that the intuition that the epistemic risk of ~sh transmits to p is flawed because it relies on a false assumption.

Since the risk involved is that of acceptance of a proposition without knowledge of or evidential [justification] for its truth, the idea that the risk transfers from [~sh] to p is just the contrapositive of the idea that knowledge and evidential [justification] transmit from p to [~sh]. So interpreted, then, the worry about [epistemic risk] is just a version of the discredited assumption that [justification] is unrestrictedly transmissive. (Wright Reference Wright, Zardini and Dodd2014: 229)

Let's unpack this condensed explanation. The expression ‘evidential justification’ refers to justification depending on evidence (i.e. a belief or an experience) sufficient to sustain belief. Recall that p entails ~sh. Wright (Reference Wright2002, Reference Wright and Nuccetelli2003, Reference Wright and Nuccetelli2008) has argued that evidential justification doesn't always transmit across entailment. S's justification for p resting on evidence e transmits across the entailment from p to q – according to Wright – just in case (i) S has justification for believing p from e, (ii) S knows that p entails q, and (iii) S has justification for believing q in virtue of the truth of both (i) and (ii). Wright claims that (iii) remains unsatisfied whenever S's acquiring justification for believing p from e requires S to have antecedent justification for accepting q. Suppose for instance S has two identical copies, H and H*, of Hamlet. O is the disjunctive proposition that this book looks like H or H*. A is the proposition the book is actually H. B is the proposition that the book is not H*. S's acquiring justification for believing A from O requires S to have antecedent justification for accepting B. Suppose that this requirement is met and that (i) S learns O thereby acquiring justification for believing A. Also suppose that (ii) S knows that A entails B. In these circumstances – according to Wright (Reference Wright2002, Reference Wright and Nuccetelli2003, Reference Wright and Nuccetelli2008) – it is intuitive that S cannot acquire justification for believing B in virtue of the truth of (i) and (ii). So (iii) is false. This is a case of transmission failure. If (PJ) is true, the entailment from p to ~sh should also instantiate transmission failure, for S's acquiring justification for believing p from her experience as if p requires S to possess antecedent justification for accepting ~sh (cf. Wright Reference Wright and Nuccetelli2008).

My best interpretation of Wright's passage quoted above is this: if you have the impression that the epistemic risk of ~sh transmits to p, this is only because you mistakenly presuppose that evidential justification is unrestrictedly transmissive so that any evidential justification for p must transmit to ~sh. In fact, if you presuppose this and realize that S doesn't have evidential justification for ~sh because ~sh is epistemically risky, you are bound to conclude – on pain of contradiction – that S doesn't have justification for believing p either, which means that p is also epistemically risky.

This diagnosis is misguided because it confuses S's justification for ~sh that S acquires upon experiencing as if p with S's antecedent justification for ~sh resting on S's mere entitlement to ~sh. Suppose you endorse both (PJ) and Wright's entitlement theory but presuppose that evidential justification is unrestrictedly transmissive. Imagine you realize that S lacks antecedent justification for believing ~sh. Given your presupposition, you can still conclude without contradiction that S has justification for believing ~sh – namely, evidential justification transmitted to ~sh from p. In fact note that this justification transmitted to ~sh is not antecedent justification for believing ~sh, which S lacks, but justification that S is supposed to acquire when she experiences as if p and deduces ~sh from p. Since you can conclude that S has evidential justification for ~sh, you aren't bound to maintain that S lacks evidential justification for p, so that p is epistemically risky. This shows that the intuition that ~sh’s epistemic risk transmits to p doesn't depend on presupposing (mistakenly or not) that evidential justification is unrestrictedly transmissive.

Wright (Reference Wright, Zardini and Dodd2014: 228–35) has given Moruzzi's objection a novel response. It says that no epistemic risk transmits from ~sh to p because ~sh is not epistemically risky after all. This response too appears flawed to me.Footnote 9

Although Wright (Reference Wright2014) endorses (PJ), in this paper he concedes that evidential justification – when suitably qualified – transmits from p to ~sh. Wright contends that (PJ) blocks the transmission of two types of justification. Firstly, no justification transmitted from p to ~sh can be a first-time justification for accepting ~sh. For S can acquire justification for p from experiencing as if p only if S has already justification for accepting ~sh. Furthermore, no justification transmitted to ~sh from p can raise ~sh’s ‘rational credibility’. For ‘whatever limit there was to the rational credibility of [~sh] as an object of trust … it remains as an upper bound on its rational credibility as an object of belief based on the appearance that [p]’ (Wright Reference Wright, Zardini and Dodd2014: 233).Footnote 10 Wright argues that, nevertheless, (PJ) doesn't debar evidential justification from transmitting from p to ~sh if the justification is neither a first time justification for accepting ~sh nor one that boosts ~sh’s credibility. Drawing from Hawthorne (Reference Hawthorne2004: 39–40) and McGlynn (Reference McGlynn, Dodd and Zardini2014), Wright contends that this transmission can persuasively take place through a two-stage inference: suppose S has evidential justification for p. This justification will first transmit to the disjunction p v ~sh, entailed by p. This is so, for Wright, because it is compelling that any justification for believing either disjunct of a disjunction is by itself justification for believing the disjunction. S's justification for p v ~sh will then transfer to ~sh, which is a priori equivalent to the disjunction (cf. Wright Reference Wright, Zardini and Dodd2014: 231–233). Wright thinks that since S is entitled to ~sh, S will acquire justification for believing p from her experience as if p, and this evidential justification will transfer to ~sh. This would show that Moruzzi's challenge ultimately dissolves, as ‘we no longer have the assumption in place that there can be no evidential [justification] for [~sh]’ (Wright Reference Wright, Zardini and Dodd2014: 235).Footnote 11 In other words, we no longer have the assumption in place that ~sh is epistemically risky.

This response to Moruzzi puts the cart before the horse. Wright contends that evidential justification can transmit from p to ~sh. Suppose his explanation is correct. Evidential justification will transmit from p to ~sh only if S does have evidential justification for p in the first instance. But Moruzzi's objection was precisely that S couldn't have this justification. Given that S's entitlement to ~sh cannot remove ~sh’s epistemic risk, and this risk – according to Moruzzi – transmits to p, p must be epistemically risky when S experiences as if p. So S's justification for p based on S's experience as if p (if any) will be unable to sustain S's belief that p. Hence, there will be no evidential justification to be transmitted from p to ~sh in the first instance.

5. Transmission of epistemic risk

Although Wright's responses to Moruzzi are ineffective, we cannot conclude yet that Moruzzi's objection goes through. For Moruzzi's claim that ~sh’s epistemic risk transmits to p hasn't been substantiated. In this section I will show that this claim can be validated through (PC) once the standard probabilistic account of risk is presupposed. Since this standard account has recently been challenged, I would like to dwell on this issue before proceeding any further.

The term ‘risk’ is customarily taken to refer to the probability of an unwanted event, where this probability is estimated on a relevant body of evidence. This usage is for instance exemplified by the statement that, on the current medical evidence, the risk that a smoker's life is shortened by some smoking-related disease is about ½ (cf. Hansson Reference Hansson and Zalta2018).Footnote 12 It might look self-evident that our judgements about risk track probability. Pritchard (Reference Pritchard2015, Reference Pritchard2016) has nevertheless challenged this thesis with an apparent counterexample.

(BOMB)

Case 1: An evil scientist has rigged up a large bomb, which he has hidden in a populated area. If the bomb explodes, many people will die. There is no way of discovering the bomb before the time it is set to detonate. The bomb will only detonate, however, if a certain set of numbers comes up on the next national lottery draw. The odds of these numbers appearing is fourteen million to one. It is not possible to interfere with this lottery draw.

Case 2: An evil scientist has rigged up a large bomb, which he has hidden in a populated area. If the bomb explodes, many people will die. There is no way of discovering the bomb before the time it is set to detonate. The bomb will only detonate, however, if a series of three highly unlikely events obtains. First, the weakest horse in the field at the Grand National, Lucky Loser, must win the race by at least ten furlongs. Second, the worst team remaining in the FA Cup draw, Accrington Stanley, must beat the best team remaining, Manchester United, by at least ten goals. And third, the queen of England must spontaneously choose to speak a complete sentence of Polish during her next public speech. The odds of this chain of events occurring are fourteen million to one. It is not possible to interfere with the outcomes of any of the events in this chain. (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2015: 441)

Pritchard observes that although the unwanted event – the bomb's detonating – is equally likely in both cases, its risk in Case 1 is intuitively higher than in Case 2. For we have the feeling that, despite the detonation triggering events having equal chances in both cases, the detonation triggering event in Case 1 could happen more easily than the detonation triggering event in Case 2. All that is needed for the detonation triggering event in Case 1 to materialize is simply that a few numbered balls be extracted in a particular sequence. In contrast, the detonation triggering event in Case 2 could take place only if many weird things took place all together.

To explain our intuitions about risk elicited by cases like (BOMB), Pritchard develops a modal conception of risk alternative to the probabilistic one. Pritchard explicates the notion of easy possibility by exploiting the familiar idea that possible worlds are more or less close to the actual world in the sense that they are more or less similar to it. He submits that an event could easily happen just in case the closest worlds in which it takes place are very similar to the actual world, and that an event could happen more easily than another just in case the closest worlds in which it takes place are more similar to the actual one than the closest worlds in which the other event occurs. The detonation triggering event in Case 1 could happen more easily than the detonation triggering event in Case 2 because the closest worlds in which it takes place are more similar to the actual one than the closest worlds in which the other event occurs.

In this account, the degree of risk of an unwanted event is proportional to its modal distance from the actual world, rather than its likelihood. Precisely, the degree of risk of a proposition p describing a given event is determined by the degree of closeness to the actual world of the closest worlds in which p is true: the closer these worlds, the higher the risk. Suppose now that P states that the bomb is detonating. Since P is true in very close worlds in Case 1, but only in remote worlds in Case 2, P proves more risky in Case 1 than in Case 2.

Bricker (Reference Bricker2018) observes that Pritchard's modal account, if working at all, would also explain cases in which our judgements seem to track probability, since probability and modal ordering are often correlated. (For example, note that you seriously bodily injuring yourself from playing chess is both a very improbable event and one that happens only in very remote worlds.) The modal account of risk would thus be capable of handling cases that the probabilistic account cannot handle but also cases that appear to suggest that risk tracks probability.

It is far from clear, however, that Pritchard's account constitutes “the correct analysis of risk” or that it should be preferred to the probabilistic account. Pritchard's reasons to reject the probabilistic account primarily hinge on our intuitive judgments about risk elicited by (BOMB). Pritchard thinks that the best explanation of why we make these judgments is that we apply his modal notion of risk, which we would implicitly possess. But this argument can be questioned. The judgments elicited by (BOMB) might simply stem from our heuristics, cognitive biases, or similar psychological factors. So these judgments might be no evidence that our pre-theoretical conception of risk is akin to that outlined by Pritchard. For instance, note that the degree of probability of the detonation triggering event in Case 2 has been stipulated – no explanation of how it has been worked out is offered. Since the numerical value supplied by Pritchard looks terribly far-fetched, it is perhaps natural that we (or our sub-personal cognitive systems) tend to ignore that piece of information. If this is true, psychology can offer various explanations of why we end up judging that the unwanted event is less risky in Case 2 than in Case 1. Some explanations are compatible with the probabilistic account of risk. For instance, Kahneman and Tversky (Reference Kahneman, Tversky, Kahneman, Slovic and Tversky1974) have shown that there is a positive correlation between how easily a subject simulates (i.e. mentally pictures) an event and how probable she estimates that the event is. Note that the detonation triggering event of Case 2 is far less easy to simulate than the detonation triggering event of Case 1.

The modal account of risk has counterintuitive consequences that the probabilistic account doesn't imply. Suppose you are about to flip a coin C that you know to be fair, and you have bet £100 on heads, while your opponent has bet £100 on tails. If you win, you get £100, otherwise you lose £100.Footnote 13 It is intuitive that before seeing the outcome, you should judge the proposition that

(P) C lands tails,

to be considerably risky. The probabilistic account explains why: given your evidence, the chance that the unwanted event P takes place is ½. The modal account provides an alternative explanation: your evidence allows you to conclude that the possible worlds in which P is true are very close. Imagine now that C lands heads, and that you see it. In light of your new evidence, you should no longer judge P to be risky to any extent. This is straightforwardly explained by the probabilistic account: the new evidence indicates that P’s chance has dropped to zero. However, on the modal account you are still rationally required to take P to be risky to some degree. For your new evidence still allows you to conclude that the worlds in which P is true are very close. (In those worlds you don't see that C lands heads – you see it lands tails. But this doesn't make them remote worlds.) More generally, on the modal account, any event that could have easily happened but is known not to have happen must be taken to be risky to some extent. This doesn't match the intuitive idea of risk. As Hansson (Reference Hansson2005: 68) has emphasized, ‘Risks are always connected to lack of knowledge … if we know that no explosion will take place, then there is no reason … to talk about risk.’

Producing a thorough assessment of the modal account of risk would take us too far afield. Let me only add that Pritchard (Reference Pritchard2015, Reference Pritchard2016) has attempted to defend his account by showing that it can illuminate (BOMB) but also by describing independent supporting evidence available in psychology and cognitive sciences. Bricker (Reference Bricker2018) has nonetheless adduced alternative empirical evidence that looks incompatible with Pritchard's modal account. Importantly, Bricker has also detailed an imaginary case similar to (BOMB) that prompts judgments about risk that appear unexplainable by both the modal account and the probabilistic account. Thus, this interesting dispute is far from being settled.

My view is that to investigate whether epistemic risk transmits, we don't need to produce “the correct analysis of risk”. There might be no such analysis – perhaps our pre-theoretical conception of risk is partly incoherent or indeterminate and admits of more than just one analysis or precisification. To investigate whether or not epistemic risk transmits, we only need to rely on a notion of risk sufficiently close to the one that Wright and Moruzzi presuppose in their dispute. There is no reason to think that Wright and Moruzzi adopt a conception of risk different from the orthodox one, which is probabilistic.

It is also noteworthy that if Wright endorsed Pritchard's modal conception of risk, he would face a kind of conceptual incoherence. For he would have to acknowledge that there are many propositions the acceptance of which is epistemically risky but, simultaneously, not risky. To see this, remember that Wright holds that thanks to our entitlements to rule out all sceptical alternatives, our perceptual beliefs are normally justified. Wright is thus committed to taking the actual world to be broadly as it appears to be, and so to taking any sceptical conjecture sh to be true only in remote possible worlds. Consider now any conjecture sh of this type. If Wright adopted the modal conception of risk, he would need to acknowledge that although our best evidence cannot justify believing ~sh, so that accepting ~sh is epistemically risky, accepting ~sh is not risky. For ~sh is false only in remote possible worlds.Footnote 14

Let me now show that once the probabilistic account of risk is presupposed, Moruzzi's claim that epistemic risk transmits can be validated through (PC). Take any perceptual proposition p, a proposition e stating that S experiences as if p, and any correlated sceptical alternative sh. The degree of risk that ~sh is false – expressed by RSF(~sh) can be identified with Pr(sh), where Pr is a probability function interpreted subjectively.Footnote 15 The degree of risk that p is false given e – expressed by RSF(p|e) can be identified with Pr(~p|e). Since RSF(~sh) = Pr(sh) and RSF(p|e) = Pr(~p|e), it is easy to show that (PC) Pr(p|e) < Pr(~sh) is equivalent to:

(RS) RSF(p|e) > RSF(~sh).

(RS) states that the degree of risk that p is false given e is strictly higher than the degree of risk that ~sh is false independent of e. (RS) validates Moruzzi's claim that ~sh’s epistemic risk transmits to p. To see this, take r to be a threshold value of epistemic risk. In other words, suppose that whenever r is exceeded by a proposition, the risk that it is false is so high that S's believing that proposition would be unjustified. (RS) entails that if RsF(~sh) > r, then RsF(p|e) > r. That is to say, if S's accepting ~sh on the basis of a non-evidential entitlement (and so prior to learning e) is epistemically risky, S's accepting p upon learning e is also epistemically risky.

6. Concluding remarks

Since it is plausible that the epistemic risk of ~sh transmits to p, Wright's entitlement theory appears unable to neutralize the sceptical challenge arising from (PJ). Wright still has some space for manoeuvre though. He could try to argue that White's Bayesian model is unreliable or misleading. For instance, he might contend that probability calculus is ill-suited to model our rational confidence when we reflect on outlandish conjectures like those adduced by the sceptic (cf. Weatherson Reference Weatherson2007).Footnote 16 As already suggested, Wright could also challenge the assumption at the heart of White's model that one's experience and one's reflective belief that one has an experience are relevantly similar in terms of justifying power (cf. Moretti Reference Moretti2015). If responses like these were to succeed, however, Wright should drop the apparently convincing case for (PJ) made by White. One way or another, Wright's epistemology of perception would be endangered.Footnote 17

Footnotes

1 By ‘justification’ I will always mean propositional (rather than doxastic) justification.

2 Epistemic conservatives like White (Reference White2006) and Neta (Reference Neta2010) defend similar principles.

3 By ‘sceptical alternative’ I refer to global sceptical hypotheses like the Cartesian demon scenario or the Matrix scenario.

4 (PJ) is normally attributed to Wright (see for instance White Reference White2006, Silins Reference Silins, Gendler and Hawthorne2007, Neta Reference Neta2010 and Silva Reference Silva2010). Wright seems sometimes to endorse an alternative principle, according to which S's experience as if p gives S justification for claiming that S has justification for believing p only if S has antecedent justification for accepting ~sh. In this paper I criticize Wright interpreted as a supporter of (PJ). For discussion about these two alternative readings of Wright's conception of the structure perceptual justification see McGlynn (Reference McGlynn2017).

5 I use small letters for propositional variable and capital letters for propositional constants.

6 For instance, they would produce easy justification and infringe probability principles.

7 The objection – which Wright attributes to Schiffer (Reference Schiffer2004) – says that the dogmatist is committed to maintaining that, for any p and e, Pr(p|e) must be sufficiently high, but that she cannot provide a justification for the required value of Pr(~sh) and other priors.

8 More generally, for Wright, we are entitled to accept certain hinge propositions inclusive of these negations.

9 I put forward this diagnosis more hesitantly, as I found Wright's discussion less clear in this case.

10 This claim is vindicated by White's model, as Pr(~sh|e) < Pr(~sh).

11 Wright maintains that (what he calls) the leaching problem dissolves, but Moruzzi's challenge is the only version of the leaching problem analysed in his paper (cf. Wright Reference Wright, Zardini and Dodd2014: 228–9).

12 A refinement of this conception, adopted in professional risk management and economics, interprets ‘risk’ as referring to the expectation value of a possible negative event, which is the product of the event's probability and some measure of its severity (cf. Hansson Reference Hansson and Zalta2018). To avoid sterile complications, I follow Pritchard (Reference Pritchard2015, Reference Pritchard2016) and Bricker (Reference Bricker2018) in setting aside this more technical notion.

13 If you don't value money, replace it with anything else you value.

14 I don't want to suggest that Pritchard's modal account of risk is epistemologically flawed or problematic because of this result. My view is that the modal account may harmonize with externalist epistemologies (like the one described in Pritchard Reference Pritchard2016) but it appears incoherent with the internalist approach to justification and knowledge generally favoured by Wright.

15 Risk is usually interpreted as referring to the objective probability or chance of an event. Nevertheless, objective probability can in principle be translated into subjective probability because, for every proposition q, any rational subject S must conform her degree of confidence in q to the chance of q once S knows this chance, in accordance with Lewis’ Principal Principle.

16 Weatherson (Reference Weatherson2007) argues that sceptical conjectures (and their negations) are uncertain rather than risky – in accordance with Keynes' (Reference Keynes1937) distinction – and that standard probability calculus cannot model uncertainty.

17 I'm very grateful to Peter Brössel, Davide Fassio, Federico Luzzi, Matthew McGrath, Kevin Olivier, Tommaso Piazza, Jim Pryor, Martin Smith, Ulrich Stegmann, Stephan Torre, Crispin Wright and a Reviewer and an Associate Editor of Episteme for helpful criticism and comments upon drafts of this paper.

References

Bricker, A.M. (2018). ‘Do Judgements About Risk Track Modal Ordering?Thought 7, 200–8.Google Scholar
Chignell, A. (2017). ‘The Ethics of Belief’. In Zalta, E.N. (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/ethics-belief/.Google Scholar
Jenkins, C. (2007). ‘Entitlement and Rationality.’ Synthese 157, 2545.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hansson, S.O. (2005). ‘The Epistemology of Technological Risk.’ Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology 9, 6880.Google Scholar
Hansson, S.O. (2018). ‘Risk.’ In Zalta, E.N. (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/risk/.Google Scholar
Hawthorne, J. (2004). Knowledge and Lotteries. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kahneman, D. and Tversky, A. (1974). ‘Simulation Heuristic.’ In Kahneman, D., Slovic, P. and Tversky, A. (eds), Judgement Under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases, pp. 201–8. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Keynes, J.M. (1937). ‘The General Theory of Employment.’ Quarterly Journal of Economics 51, 209–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGlynn, A. (2014). ‘On Epistemic Alchemy.’ In Dodd, D. and Zardini, E. (eds), Scepticism and Perceptual Justification, pp. 173–89. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGlynn, A. (2017). ‘Epistemic Entitlement and the Leaching Problem.’ Episteme 14, 89102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGrath, M. (2013). ‘Dogmatism, Underminers and Skepticism.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 86, 533–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moretti, L. (2015). ‘In Defence of Dogmatism.’ Philosophical Studies 172, 261–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neta, R. (2010). ‘Liberalism and Conservatism in the Epistemology of Perceptual Belief.’ Australasian Journal of Philosophy 88, 685705.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pritchard, D. (2005). ‘Wittgenstein's On Certainty and Contemporary Anti-Scepticism.’ In Moyal-Sharrock, D. and Brenner, W.H. (eds), Readings of Wittgenstein's On Certainty, pp. 189224. London: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pritchard, D. (2015). ‘Risk.’ Metaphilosophy 46, 436–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pritchard, D. (2016). ‘Epistemic Risk’. Journal of Philosophy 113, 550–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pryor, J. (2000). ‘The Skeptic and the Dogmatist.’ Noûs 34, 517–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pryor, J. (2004). ‘What's Wrong with Moore's Argument?Philosophical Issues 14, 349–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schiffer, S. (2004). ‘Skepticism and the Vagaries of Justified Belief.’ Philosophical Studies 131, 525–57.Google Scholar
Silins, N. (2007). ‘Basic Justification and the Moorean Response to the Skeptic.’ In Gendler, T.S. and Hawthorne, J. (eds), Oxford Studies in Epistemology Vol. 2, pp. 108–40. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Silva, P. (2010). ‘How to be Conservative: A Partial Defence of Epistemic Conservatism.’ Australasian Journal of Philosophy 91, 501–14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weatherson, B. (2007). ‘The Bayesian and the Dogmatist.’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 107, 169–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, R. (2006). ‘Problems for Dogmatism.’ Philosophical Studies 131, 525–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, C. (2002). ‘(Anti-)Sceptics Simple and Subtle: G. E. Moore and John McDowell.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65, 330–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, C. (2003). ‘Some Reflections on the Acquisition of Warrant by Inference’. In Nuccetelli, S. (ed.), New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self-Knowledge, pp. 5777. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Wright, C. (2004). ‘On Epistemic Entitlement: Warrant for Nothing (and Foundations for Free?).’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 78, 167212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, C. (2008). ‘Perils of Dogmatism’. In Nuccetelli, S. (ed.), Themes from G. E. Moore: New Essays in Epistemology and Ethics, pp. 2548. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wright, C. (2014). ‘On Epistemic Entitlement (II): Welfare State Epistemology.’ In Zardini, E. and Dodd, D. (eds), Scepticism and Perceptual Justification. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar